05.11.2014 Views

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

172 JOSEPH TORCHIA<br />

culation of his own teachings, or discarding what is wholly<br />

unacceptable from a Christian perspective. 14<br />

The Augustine of the Cassiciacum dialogues (A.D. 386-388)<br />

was especially receptive to Stoic ethics. This intellectual dependence<br />

is reflected in his emphasis on the role of reason in the<br />

moral life, and the assumption that conduct should stand in harmony<br />

with both nature and reason. In Augustine’s earliest definitions<br />

of the happy life, we find some of the key components of<br />

the classical Stoic understanding of virtue: an emphasis on the<br />

quality of the inner life, the primacy of intention, correct ratiocination,<br />

and equanimity in the face of the vicissitudes of<br />

human existence. 15 Conversely, vice was seen as the product of<br />

the irrational tendencies of the will which find expression in<br />

pleasure, pain, desire, and fear. 16 Like the Stoics, the early<br />

Augustine endorsed the position that the wise man was able to<br />

subordinate his desires for transitory things to a higher vision of<br />

the good, and thereby, ground his happiness upon what is<br />

immutable and certain. 17<br />

Augustine’s early confidence in the autonomy and self-sufficiency<br />

of the life of virtue underwent considerable change as he<br />

progressed in his own spiritual journey to God. An awareness of<br />

his moral and metaphysical contingency (rendered more acute<br />

as a result of his controversy with the Pelagians and an increasing<br />

emphasis upon the radical fallenness of human nature)<br />

prompted a serious revision of his attitude toward Stoic ethics.<br />

Accordingly, his initial definitions of virtue as rightly ordered<br />

reason were supplanted by an understanding of the virtuous life<br />

14<br />

For an extended discussion regarding the evolution of Augustine’s attitude<br />

toward Stoicism and the ways in which he used Stoic thought, see<br />

COLISH’S The Stoic Tradition from Antiquity to the Early Middle Ages, <strong>Vol</strong>ume II.<br />

15<br />

The works in question encompass the Cassiciacum dialogues, written<br />

shortly after Augustine’s conversion and Baptism (i.e., between late A.D. 386<br />

and early 387). See De ordine II,8(25); II,9(27); De Beata Vita IV,25(33); De<br />

Quantitate Animae 17(30); 33(73); Soliloquia I,6(13).<br />

16<br />

De libero arbitrio I,3(8)-I,4(10); I,8(18).<br />

17<br />

In this regard, Augustine reflects the influence of both Stoicism (and<br />

its emphasis upon the proper use of reason and will) and the Neoplatonic<br />

notion of an immutable Good that is immune to loss. Cf., Soliloquia I,12(21).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!