05.11.2014 Views

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

Vol. XXXVIII / 1 - Studia Moralia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

120 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

warrants careful rational justification. If such presuppositions<br />

are not critically examined they are in danger of uncritically<br />

absorbing the current prejudices and distortions of a given<br />

cultural context. In this regard a number of authors have noted<br />

the roots of human rights discourse in the ambitious<br />

Enlightenment claims concerning “right and reason”. 21<br />

In the light of this reading of the preamble, we can conclude<br />

that the text indeed implies a normative ethical system, but it<br />

does not articulate one. If we reconstruct in a critical fashion the<br />

process of reasoning presupposed by the text, it proves to be<br />

remarkably similar to that traditional form of ethical<br />

argumentation known as “natural law”. 22 How else is one to<br />

describe the normative basis of a theory which ascribes such<br />

inherent value to human beings and prescribes such specific<br />

norms for their treatment? It is surely ironic that the preferred<br />

juridical discourse of liberal culture proves to be so heavily<br />

reliant on a classical ethical theory, even if the presence of this<br />

latter would seem to be largely in incognito.<br />

We can imagine the comment of a postmodern philosopher<br />

on such normative affirmations 23 . Smiling with a benevolent<br />

condescension he or she would explain: “But I too am a member<br />

of Amnesty International, I am no less in favour of human rights<br />

than you are, but I simply do not see the need for this<br />

rationalistic superstructure. In order to reject torture I do not<br />

need your abstract discourse on the dignity of the human<br />

21<br />

For a lucid synthesis of recent literature on this point see P. BOURETZ,<br />

“Droits” in Dictionnaire d’éthique et de philosophie morale (Paris: Presses<br />

Universitaires de France, 1996).<br />

22<br />

It is a commonplace that “natural law” is used to refer not to one<br />

ethical theory but to a whole gamut of theories, some of which contradict<br />

each other. Here the term is used to refer to the “mainline” classical natural<br />

law tradition as articulated in Augustine, systematically presented in<br />

Aquinas and consistently refined in the intervening theological reflection.<br />

23<br />

For texts which contain far more audacious declarations than those<br />

represented here see: R. RORTY, “Diritti Umani, razionalità e sentimento” in<br />

I Diritti Umani, Oxford Amnesty Lectures, a cura di Stephen Shute e Susan<br />

Hurley (Garanzi Editore, 1994) Italian trans. S. Lauzi, original title On<br />

Human Rights (Basic Books, 1993); Z. BAUMAN, Postmodern Ethics (Oxford:<br />

Blackwell, 1993), 24-59, Italian trans. G. Bettini, Le sfide dell’etica (Milano:<br />

Feltrinelli Editore, 1993).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!