02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Scerri’s says about <strong>the</strong> case of chromium: “It appears that<br />

both non-relativistic <strong>and</strong> relativistic calculations fail to predict<br />

<strong>the</strong> experimentally observed ground state which is <strong>the</strong><br />

4s 1 3d 5 configuration” (2004, 101), but he immediately<br />

goes on to admit “Of course I do not deny that if one goes<br />

far enough <strong>in</strong> a more elaborate calculation <strong>the</strong>n eventually<br />

<strong>the</strong> correct ground state will be recovered. But <strong>in</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so<br />

one knows what one is driv<strong>in</strong>g at, namely <strong>the</strong> experimentally<br />

observed result. This is not <strong>the</strong> same as strictly predict<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> configuration <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> absence of experimental<br />

<strong>in</strong>formation.” Right, it isn’t; but that failure has not revealed<br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g new at work.<br />

As Galison says of a different case, “The reductionist<br />

physicists reply that it is true that you might not guess<br />

<strong>the</strong>se collective behaviors; but if you ask why very cold<br />

copper superconducts, <strong>the</strong> answer <strong>in</strong>cludes noth<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than electrons <strong>and</strong> electrodynamics-<strong>the</strong>re's no magical<br />

supplementary th<strong>in</strong>g over <strong>and</strong> above <strong>the</strong>se” (2008, 121).<br />

We can see <strong>the</strong> po<strong>in</strong>t at issue <strong>in</strong> a case even Horst<br />

acknowledges is not decisive: <strong>the</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical <strong>in</strong>tractability<br />

of <strong>the</strong> three-body problem for Newtonian <strong>the</strong>ory is no<br />

reason to suppose that anyth<strong>in</strong>g new has entered a Newtonian<br />

system when a third mass is <strong>in</strong>troduced. The cases<br />

Horst th<strong>in</strong>ks are more significant than this do not seem to<br />

<strong>in</strong>volve anyth<strong>in</strong>g very different, however. I appeal to Azzouni’s<br />

authority <strong>in</strong> agree<strong>in</strong>g with Nagel that <strong>the</strong> idealis<strong>in</strong>g<br />

assumptions required <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>the</strong>rmodynamics case are not<br />

a barrier to <strong>the</strong> worthwhile k<strong>in</strong>d of reduction she calls “scientific”.<br />

She says “Imag<strong>in</strong>e, contrary to fact, that a genu<strong>in</strong>e<br />

derivational reduction is available, but only if constra<strong>in</strong>ts<br />

are placed on gas states that are—given <strong>the</strong> physics of<br />

micro-particles—quite probabilistically low. In such a case<br />

… physicalism fails: emergent phenomena, <strong>in</strong>dicated by<br />

physically <strong>in</strong>explicable constra<strong>in</strong>ts on <strong>the</strong> probability space<br />

of micro-particles, show this” (2000, 45). She comments <strong>in</strong><br />

a footnote: “Garf<strong>in</strong>kel (1981:70-1) seems aware of this<br />

possibility, but seems also, falsely, to th<strong>in</strong>k that <strong>the</strong> actual<br />

derivation of <strong>the</strong> Boyle-Charles law from <strong>the</strong> statistical<br />

behavior of <strong>the</strong> ensemble of molecules illustrates it just<br />

because of <strong>the</strong> use of <strong>the</strong> conservation of energy (<strong>in</strong><br />

closed systems) <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> assumption of a normal distribution<br />

of velocities.”<br />

There are, of course, contentious issues <strong>in</strong> what<br />

scientists consider successful or unsuccessful reductions<br />

(e.g. <strong>the</strong> temporal isotropy of statistical mechanics as<br />

aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong> directedness of phenomenological <strong>the</strong>rmodynamics).<br />

But <strong>the</strong> types of idealis<strong>in</strong>g assumption that Horst<br />

is appeal<strong>in</strong>g to are not usually someth<strong>in</strong>g that should underm<strong>in</strong>e<br />

our confidence <strong>in</strong> a reduction.<br />

30<br />

Informal <strong>Reduction</strong> — E.P. Br<strong>and</strong>on<br />

While I have been happy to call upon Azzouni for<br />

support, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>deed f<strong>in</strong>d her account of scientific reduction<br />

very close to what I have been urg<strong>in</strong>g myself, 2 I will close<br />

with one quibble. If we can legitimately see scientific reduction<br />

as not requir<strong>in</strong>g formal derivations but simply “all<br />

that is desired is an extension of <strong>the</strong> scope of an underly<strong>in</strong>g<br />

science <strong>in</strong> a way illum<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g both to that science <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> special science above it” (2000, 40), I would like to<br />

suggest that we can extend <strong>the</strong> same sympathy to Nagel’s<br />

own derivational model of reduction. As I <strong>in</strong>dicated at <strong>the</strong><br />

start, Nagel saw <strong>the</strong> relation as explanatory. Work<strong>in</strong>g with<br />

<strong>the</strong> tools available to him he took that to <strong>in</strong>volve formal<br />

derivation, though actual cases, of explanation <strong>and</strong> of reduction,<br />

might well only exhibit <strong>the</strong> elements that Hempel<br />

called an “explanation sketch” (Hempel 1965 [1942], 238,).<br />

Allow<strong>in</strong>g for Nagel’s clear recognition that his account is<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed an idealisation of <strong>the</strong> reductions we actually f<strong>in</strong>d,<br />

we may resist agree<strong>in</strong>g with Azzouni that <strong>the</strong> concern for<br />

derivation has been altoge<strong>the</strong>r a mistaken “obsession with<br />

words”. It provides a picture that we can adjust to get<br />

closer to <strong>the</strong> realities we are <strong>in</strong>terested <strong>in</strong>, as <strong>in</strong>deed her<br />

own explorations reveal.<br />

Literature<br />

Azzouni, Jodi 2000 Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Reference <strong>in</strong> Empirical Science,<br />

London: Routledge.<br />

Friedrich, Bretislav 2004 “…Hasn’t it?”, Foundations of Chemistry<br />

6, 117–132.<br />

Galison, Peter 2008 “Ten Problems <strong>in</strong> History <strong>and</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong> of<br />

Science”, Isis 99, 111–124.<br />

Hempel, Carl G. 1965 [1942] “The Function of General Laws <strong>in</strong><br />

History”, <strong>in</strong>: Aspects of Scientific Explanation, New York: The<br />

Free Press.<br />

Horst, Steven 2007 Beyond <strong>Reduction</strong>: <strong>Philosophy</strong> of M<strong>in</strong>d <strong>and</strong><br />

Post-<strong>Reduction</strong>ist <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Science, Oxford: Oxford University<br />

Press.<br />

Nagel, Ernest 1961 The Structure of Science, London: Routledge<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kegan Paul.<br />

O'Connor, Timothy, <strong>and</strong> Hong Yu Wong 2006 “Emergent Properties”,<br />

<strong>in</strong> Stanford Encyclopedia of <strong>Philosophy</strong><br />

(http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties-emergent/).<br />

Scerri, Eric 2004 “Just How Ab Initio is Ab Initio Quantum Chemistry?”<br />

Foundations of Chemistry 6, 93-116.<br />

Silberste<strong>in</strong>, M., 2002. <strong>Reduction</strong>, Emergence <strong>and</strong> Explanation. In<br />

The Blackwell Guide to <strong>the</strong> <strong>Philosophy</strong> of Science, edited by P.<br />

Machamer <strong>and</strong> M. Silberste<strong>in</strong>. Oxford: Blackwell.<br />

2 She says, for <strong>in</strong>stance, “talk of <strong>the</strong>re be<strong>in</strong>g a scientific reduction <strong>in</strong> this sort of<br />

situation is still legitimate because we really do take As, <strong>and</strong> what is go<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

with <strong>the</strong>m, to be noth<strong>in</strong>g more than Bs, <strong>and</strong> what is go<strong>in</strong>g on with <strong>the</strong>m; we<br />

recognize <strong>and</strong> expect that if, <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> cases, we overcome (particular) tractability<br />

problems (as we sometimes do) <strong>in</strong> treat<strong>in</strong>g As as Bs, we will not discover<br />

recalcitrant emergent phenomena. Scientific reduction is a project with methodological<br />

depth: <strong>the</strong> idealized model is one where deviations from what is<br />

actually go<strong>in</strong>g on are deviations we can study directly, extract <strong>in</strong>formation<br />

from, <strong>and</strong>, when we're lucky, m<strong>in</strong>imize. This is <strong>the</strong> full content of <strong>the</strong> claim that<br />

As, <strong>and</strong> what is go<strong>in</strong>g on with <strong>the</strong>m, are really just Bs, <strong>and</strong> what is go<strong>in</strong>g on<br />

with <strong>the</strong>m” (43-44).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!