02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

What we now require is a bridge <strong>the</strong>ory–someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

which, based on <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g, says how ord<strong>in</strong>ary likes<br />

<strong>and</strong> dislikes differ from moral beliefs. The bridge <strong>the</strong>ory<br />

lists conditions I call marks of <strong>the</strong> moral. Satisfy<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong><br />

marks of <strong>the</strong> moral tells us that S believes or at least<br />

asserts that A is immoral, but it does not tell us that A is<br />

immoral. Our ancestors had moral beliefs <strong>and</strong> moral codes<br />

when <strong>the</strong>ir aversions, hates <strong>and</strong> lik<strong>in</strong>gs came to satisfy <strong>the</strong><br />

marks of <strong>the</strong> moral. If <strong>the</strong>ir beliefs only partly satisfied<br />

<strong>the</strong>se conditions <strong>the</strong>y would have had borderl<strong>in</strong>e cases of<br />

moral beliefs. We want to th<strong>in</strong>k a judgment is ei<strong>the</strong>r moral<br />

or non moral, but <strong>in</strong> human affairs almost everyth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

shades off <strong>in</strong>to what it isn’t. A dislike or negative attitude<br />

toward someth<strong>in</strong>g turns <strong>in</strong>to a moral belief or moral<br />

judgment when enough of <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g features<br />

characterize it:<br />

1. It concerns benefit <strong>and</strong> harm to humans <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

higher animals.<br />

2. It is communicated by special words.<br />

3. It appeals to reasons that have a general appeal<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> community.<br />

4. It is universalizable, that is, a person is will<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

judge similar cases similarly, even when one of<br />

<strong>the</strong>se cases concerns oneself.<br />

5. It can require actions contrary to self-<strong>in</strong>terest.<br />

6. It is taught to <strong>the</strong> young.<br />

7. It is all th<strong>in</strong>gs considered, that is, it judges an action<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light of self-<strong>in</strong>terest, effects on o<strong>the</strong>rs, <strong>and</strong><br />

anyth<strong>in</strong>g else thought relevant.<br />

8. It often is promulgated ritually <strong>and</strong> ceremonially,<br />

as a way of <strong>in</strong>dicat<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> community <strong>and</strong> not<br />

just an <strong>in</strong>dividual is speak<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

9. It expresses a positive or negative attitude toward<br />

<strong>the</strong> object of <strong>the</strong> judgment.<br />

10. It is urged upon <strong>the</strong> listener <strong>and</strong> rejection of<br />

what is urged is answered with anger or argument.<br />

11. It is preached <strong>in</strong> formal religious <strong>and</strong> political<br />

sett<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

If a clan spoke, reasoned <strong>and</strong> acted <strong>in</strong> ways 1-11 <strong>the</strong>y had<br />

morals, but if <strong>in</strong> not enough of <strong>the</strong>se ways <strong>the</strong>y did not.<br />

The list aims to describe <strong>the</strong> contexts <strong>and</strong> conditions under<br />

which reasonably educated English speakers use “morally<br />

wrong,” etc., <strong>and</strong> is what I suggest should replace def<strong>in</strong>itions<br />

of moral words. This is <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> spirit of Ludwig Wittgenste<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

admonition, <strong>in</strong> Philosophical Investigations, to<br />

consult <strong>the</strong> use, not <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g. These eleven conditions,<br />

s<strong>in</strong>gly or toge<strong>the</strong>r, carry nei<strong>the</strong>r moral realist nor emotivist<br />

<strong>the</strong>oretical implications.<br />

Before <strong>the</strong>y had language our ancestors had to be<br />

social. The emotional predispositions for sociality had to<br />

evolve before <strong>the</strong> evolution of language, <strong>the</strong> latter requir<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> evolution of <strong>the</strong> bra<strong>in</strong>’s speech center, <strong>the</strong> voice box,<br />

<strong>in</strong>fant babbl<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong>, of course, people to talk to. Could <strong>the</strong>y<br />

have moral beliefs? My suggestion is <strong>the</strong>y could not if <strong>the</strong>y<br />

couldn’t talk, <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore couldn’t give reasons <strong>and</strong><br />

argue. The evolutionary sequence had to be sociality first,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n language, <strong>and</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ally morals.<br />

We can conjecture how particular moral ideas<br />

arose. For example, sense of unfairness, a moral idea,<br />

very likely can be deconstructed <strong>in</strong>to clan rejection anxiety.<br />

The mechanics of unfairness is relatively straightforward; it<br />

is be<strong>in</strong>g denied benefits o<strong>the</strong>rs receive <strong>in</strong> similar<br />

circumstances. A clue to underst<strong>and</strong><strong>in</strong>g this is <strong>the</strong> outrage<br />

<strong>and</strong> anger perceived unfairness elicits, typically more than<br />

from equally harmful illnesses, accidents or combat.<br />

The Evolution of Morals — Andrew Oldenquist<br />

Unfairness has little to do with degree of perceived harm<br />

<strong>and</strong> everyth<strong>in</strong>g to do with actual or symbolic exclusion,<br />

with be<strong>in</strong>g treated as an outsider or non-member when<br />

one is not an outsider.<br />

When young people are not shamed or blamed for<br />

behavior for which o<strong>the</strong>rs are shamed <strong>and</strong> blamed, <strong>the</strong>y<br />

are be<strong>in</strong>g treated like outsiders or non-members, that is,<br />

like <strong>in</strong>vad<strong>in</strong>g Huns or wild animals. The result is alienation,<br />

a loss of sense of belong<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> hence loss of one’s social<br />

identity. Given that <strong>the</strong>se young people evolved to be<br />

<strong>in</strong>nately social animals like <strong>the</strong> rest of us, <strong>the</strong>y seek<br />

substitute social identities <strong>in</strong> gangs or counter-culture<br />

groups. Alienation kills sense of belong<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> hence<br />

pride <strong>and</strong> shame on which traditional social control largely<br />

depends.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r bridge <strong>the</strong>ory provides an explanation of<br />

retributive justice. It is often said that retribution is revenge<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>refore has no moral status. Retributivists expla<strong>in</strong><br />

retribution <strong>in</strong> terms of desert, reciprocity, or mak<strong>in</strong>g th<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

even aga<strong>in</strong>, so as to dist<strong>in</strong>guish <strong>the</strong> moral idea of<br />

retributive justice from <strong>the</strong> non-moral (or immoral) idea of<br />

revenge. I accept that retribution is a moral idea <strong>and</strong><br />

revenge is not. However, expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g retributive justice<br />

without <strong>in</strong>corporat<strong>in</strong>g revenge is hopeless. Revenge turns<br />

<strong>in</strong>to retributive justice when <strong>the</strong> desire to harm wrongdoers<br />

is constra<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g empirical conditions (or by<br />

an improved version of <strong>the</strong>m):<br />

1. Those who decide how, if at all, to punish A are<br />

nei<strong>the</strong>r A’s relatives or friends nor st<strong>and</strong> to ga<strong>in</strong> or<br />

lose from <strong>the</strong> decision.<br />

2. Similar punishments are given for similar offenses.<br />

3. The punishment is decreed <strong>in</strong> a sett<strong>in</strong>g of formality<br />

<strong>and</strong> ritual, which conveys <strong>the</strong> idea that <strong>the</strong> community<br />

<strong>and</strong> not just an <strong>in</strong>dividual is speak<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

4. Punishments are not secret but are codified <strong>and</strong><br />

promulgated by an appropriate official body.<br />

5. Crim<strong>in</strong>als must be believed to have actually done<br />

<strong>the</strong> deed for which <strong>the</strong>y are be<strong>in</strong>g punished.<br />

Retributive justice thus is sanitized revenge. Vengeance,<br />

<strong>the</strong> idea of a person be<strong>in</strong>g owed someth<strong>in</strong>g bad, is fundamental<br />

to humans, show<strong>in</strong>g itself not just <strong>in</strong> crim<strong>in</strong>al justice<br />

but also <strong>in</strong> countless <strong>in</strong>formal <strong>in</strong>teractions such as ignor<strong>in</strong>g<br />

or snubb<strong>in</strong>g someone, curs<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, ignor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m, refus<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to <strong>in</strong>vite or to help someone, assault<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>m <strong>and</strong> so<br />

on. Personal accountability is a primary way societies dist<strong>in</strong>guish<br />

members from non-members. The anthropologist<br />

Christoph von Furer-Haimendorf (Furer-Haimendorf, 1971)<br />

expla<strong>in</strong>ed crim<strong>in</strong>al justice as <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>stitutionalization <strong>and</strong><br />

ritualization of retaliation as societies became sufficiently<br />

secure <strong>and</strong> complex.<br />

But are moral judgments true or false, do <strong>the</strong>y<br />

assert moral facts? These moral realist claims are logically<br />

compatible with <strong>the</strong> explanation of morality I have laid out.<br />

But must genu<strong>in</strong>e moral judgments assert moral facts or<br />

be literally true or false? Many people, philosophers as<br />

well as non-philosophers, believe this is part of what moral<br />

words mean <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>y would feel that morality is an illusion<br />

or a fraud if moral judgments were never true or factual.<br />

Suppose <strong>the</strong>re is an antiquated community where<br />

shepherds tell time, direction <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> seasons by watch<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> stars <strong>and</strong> planets. When asked what stars are <strong>the</strong>y say<br />

<strong>the</strong> stars are gods. One of <strong>the</strong>m is persuaded, with <strong>the</strong> aid<br />

of telescopes <strong>and</strong> a little school<strong>in</strong>g, that <strong>the</strong> stars are not<br />

gods. He might respond, “Rats, stars don’t exist” <strong>and</strong> stop<br />

251

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!