02.11.2012 Views

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

Reduction and Elimination in Philosophy and the Sciences

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Properties <strong>and</strong> <strong>Reduction</strong> between Metaphysics <strong>and</strong> Physics<br />

Matteo Morganti, London, Engl<strong>and</strong>, UK<br />

1. Tropes<br />

Trope <strong>the</strong>ory is <strong>the</strong> ontological view that reality is constituted<br />

by so-called abstract particulars (property-<strong>in</strong>stances<br />

not derived from multiply <strong>in</strong>stantiable universals) grouped<br />

toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> concrete particulars (objects).<br />

Such a view must first of all expla<strong>in</strong> similarity, which,<br />

so to speak, ‘comes for free’ if one subscribes to realism<br />

about universals. Normally, trope ontologists argue that a<br />

trope a resembles ano<strong>the</strong>r trope b exclusively <strong>in</strong> virtue of a<br />

<strong>and</strong> b, that is, of <strong>the</strong>ir primitively given ‘causal role’ <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

world. This may appear more contentious than <strong>the</strong> realist’s<br />

claim that similarity is determ<strong>in</strong>ed by <strong>the</strong> numerical identity<br />

of all <strong>in</strong>stances of <strong>the</strong> same universal. In fact, however, it is<br />

analogous to what <strong>the</strong> realist must accept <strong>in</strong>sofar as nonexact<br />

resemblances are concerned. For, surely nonexactly-resembl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

entities can still be similar to various<br />

degrees, <strong>and</strong> this must be expla<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> terms o<strong>the</strong>r than<br />

numerical identity even <strong>in</strong> ontologies with universals.<br />

Hence <strong>the</strong> trope ontologist’s typical claim of primitiveness<br />

appears plausible <strong>in</strong> this case.<br />

Someth<strong>in</strong>g must also be said with respect to <strong>the</strong><br />

way <strong>in</strong> which tropes constitute complex particulars. Initially<br />

(Williams 1953), compresence was taken to be sufficient.<br />

However, if compresence is regarded as an external<br />

relation additional to <strong>the</strong> compresent tropes, it seems that<br />

a form of regress cannot be avoided: what connects <strong>the</strong><br />

compresence trope <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> compresent tropes? More<br />

generally, compresence does not appear sufficient for<br />

ground<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternal unity of th<strong>in</strong>gs: what about<br />

overlapp<strong>in</strong>g objects?<br />

This leads <strong>the</strong> trope <strong>the</strong>orist to account for <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>ner<br />

cohesion of concrete particulars <strong>in</strong> terms of <strong>in</strong>ternal<br />

relations of existential dependence among <strong>the</strong>ir constituent<br />

tropes. The first suggestion <strong>in</strong> this sense was made <strong>in</strong><br />

(Simons 1994), who takes his clue from Husserl’s<br />

foundation relations. As po<strong>in</strong>ted out by (Denkel 1997), if<br />

one wants to provide room for substantial change (that is,<br />

for <strong>the</strong> type of change <strong>in</strong>volv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> partial or total loss of<br />

an object’s essence) <strong>the</strong>se relations must be regarded as<br />

hold<strong>in</strong>g not between specific tropes, but ra<strong>the</strong>r between<br />

tropes as tokens of more general trope-types (so that<br />

replacement of any trope – <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g essential ones<br />

belong<strong>in</strong>g to what Simons calls <strong>the</strong> ‘nucleus’, or ‘kernel’, of<br />

<strong>the</strong> object - with ano<strong>the</strong>r that acts as determ<strong>in</strong>ate for <strong>the</strong><br />

same determ<strong>in</strong>able is possible).<br />

Lastly, if tropes truly are <strong>the</strong> basic ‘build<strong>in</strong>g blocks’<br />

of reality, it seems that <strong>the</strong>y had better be understood from<br />

<strong>the</strong> perspective of a sparse conception of properties,<br />

accord<strong>in</strong>g to which not all predicates correspond to actual<br />

properties. For obviously not all mean<strong>in</strong>gful predicates can<br />

plausibly be taken to refer to fundamental, non-fur<strong>the</strong>ranalysable<br />

tropes. Follow<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> ‘scientific’ approach to<br />

sparseness (Armstrong 1978), this implies that it is<br />

necessary to look at physical <strong>the</strong>ory <strong>in</strong> order to identify <strong>the</strong><br />

fundamental tropes.<br />

2. Apply<strong>in</strong>g Trope Ontology<br />

(Campbell 1990) suggests tak<strong>in</strong>g physical fields as <strong>the</strong><br />

elementary tropes. However, <strong>the</strong> canonical def<strong>in</strong>ition of a<br />

field as an extended entity with vary<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tensities at various<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ts of space seems to suggest an <strong>in</strong>ternal complexity<br />

<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> existence of (dis)similarities between fieldvalues,<br />

which immediately leads one to th<strong>in</strong>k that someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

more basic exists.<br />

It seems more advisable to follow (Simons 1994) <strong>in</strong><br />

look<strong>in</strong>g for fundamental tropes at <strong>the</strong> level of particles. In<br />

fact, Simons’ view, based on particles as ‘kernels’ of<br />

foundationally related tropes plus ‘peripheral’ tropes, just<br />

needs some fur<strong>the</strong>r articulation <strong>and</strong> specification.<br />

The hypo<strong>the</strong>sis that is taken nowadays to be <strong>the</strong><br />

best available description of <strong>the</strong> elementary constituents of<br />

reality <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>teractions is <strong>the</strong> so-called St<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

Model. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to it, <strong>the</strong> fundamental particles are 12<br />

fermions constitut<strong>in</strong>g matter <strong>and</strong> 12 bosons mediat<strong>in</strong>g<br />

forces. Fermions can be ei<strong>the</strong>r quarks (six types, or<br />

‘flavours’) or leptons (six more flavours). Bosons comprise<br />

photons, W + , W - <strong>and</strong> Z 0 gauge bosons, <strong>and</strong> eight gluons.<br />

Fermions have antiparticles, that is, particles identical to<br />

<strong>the</strong>m but with opposite electric (<strong>and</strong>, possibly, colour)<br />

charge. Each boson-type constitutes <strong>in</strong>stead its own<br />

antiparticle, except for <strong>the</strong> W + <strong>and</strong> W - bosons, which are<br />

each o<strong>the</strong>r’s antiparticle. Each one of <strong>the</strong>se particles has<br />

at least one of three possible properties: mass, colour <strong>and</strong><br />

electric charge, <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong> most cases <strong>the</strong>y have both mass<br />

<strong>and</strong> electric charge. (Photons may seem to constitute an<br />

exception to this latter claim. However, each photon<br />

possesses energy, which entails that it can <strong>in</strong> fact be<br />

attributed relativistic mass. True, <strong>the</strong> latter is dist<strong>in</strong>ct from<br />

<strong>the</strong> masses of <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r types of particles, as those are<br />

<strong>in</strong>variant masses. Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> difference is one of<br />

‘form’ ra<strong>the</strong>r than ‘substance’: as is well-known, accord<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to relativity <strong>the</strong>ory energy <strong>and</strong> mass are two ‘aspects’ of<br />

<strong>the</strong> same th<strong>in</strong>g. Hence, tropes from <strong>the</strong> same ‘family’ can<br />

be attributed to photons <strong>and</strong> to <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r particles as <strong>the</strong>ir<br />

‘masses’).<br />

In addition to <strong>the</strong>se ‘fully state-<strong>in</strong>dependent’<br />

properties, which rema<strong>in</strong> completely <strong>the</strong> same throughout<br />

<strong>the</strong> whole of a particle’s existence (unless, of course,<br />

substantial change occurs), all particles have sp<strong>in</strong>.<br />

However, only <strong>the</strong> absolute magnitude of sp<strong>in</strong> is fixed for<br />

each particle (1/2 for fermions, 1 for bosons), while <strong>the</strong><br />

sign can change. In fact, particles can be <strong>in</strong> a<br />

‘superposition’ of <strong>the</strong> two sp<strong>in</strong> values. How is this to be<br />

accounted for from <strong>the</strong> trope-<strong>the</strong>oretic perspective?<br />

In general, <strong>in</strong> quantum mechanics a specific<br />

property can be possessed with probability p such that<br />

0≤p≤1. Follow<strong>in</strong>g (Suarez 2007), I suggest a dispositional<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation of this: whenever a quantum system does<br />

not have a specific property with probability 1, it possesses<br />

a dispositional property (or ‘propensity’) correspond<strong>in</strong>g to a<br />

weighted sum of possible actual properties. In more<br />

technical terms, if Q is a discrete observable for <strong>the</strong><br />

system Ψ with spectral decomposition given by Q =<br />

n n n aP ∑ ,<br />

where Pn = vn v , <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> system is <strong>in</strong> a state<br />

n<br />

Ψ=∑ cn v (a l<strong>in</strong>ear superposition of eigenstates of Q for<br />

n<br />

235

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!