29.10.2014 Views

The Handbook of Discourse Analysis

The Handbook of Discourse Analysis

The Handbook of Discourse Analysis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Discourse</strong> and Semantics 85<br />

Generative semantics in effect tried to build discourse contexts into its deep syntactic<br />

analysis and trans-derivational constraints, for instance G. Lak<strong>of</strong>f (1970, 1971).<br />

Gordon and Lak<strong>of</strong>f (1975) argued that syntax requires a characterization <strong>of</strong> entailments<br />

in standardized contexts, and they proposed so-called “conversational postulates”<br />

to describe such entailments. Even though Green (1975), Morgan (1977), and others<br />

rejected conversational postulates on grounds that they were derivable from more<br />

general principles <strong>of</strong> inference, Gordon and Lak<strong>of</strong>f’s proposal generated increased<br />

interest in contexts and ways to describe them.<br />

In opposition to speech act theory, conversation analysis seeks to show that placement<br />

in the sequential organization <strong>of</strong> talk determines the force <strong>of</strong> an utterance. Even<br />

if one works from direct to indirect illocutionary force, placement will overrule both in<br />

concrete conversational contexts. Schegl<strong>of</strong>f (1984, 1988) shows that apparent questions<br />

characteristically act as “pre-announcements.” Thus, conversationalists tend to hear<br />

utterances like “Do you know who’s going to that meeting?” as herolding an announcement.<br />

Only secondarily do they interpret such utterances as requests for an answer to<br />

the question <strong>of</strong> “Who’s going.” Moreover, the literal question about the hearer’s knowledge<br />

seems to play no role at all. Speech act theory cannot develop a correct description<br />

<strong>of</strong> pre-sequences without taking sequentiality into account, and consequently does<br />

not <strong>of</strong>fer a plausible model <strong>of</strong> conversational meaning, according to Schegl<strong>of</strong>f. See<br />

Levinson (1983: 345–64) on the significance <strong>of</strong> pre-sequences generally.<br />

Meanwhile, other semanticists were developing inferential approaches to meaning.<br />

Fodor (1975) argued for an inferential semantic theory versus the componential<br />

analysis <strong>of</strong> Katz (1972), while Bach and Harnish (1979) and Gazdar (1979) championed<br />

inferential models <strong>of</strong> meaning incorporating speech act theory and Gricean<br />

pragmatics. <strong>The</strong>se attempts went along with an increasing awareness that the socalled<br />

“null context” posited by Katz and others in interpretive semantics was itself<br />

a special context or at least an invitation to image some context appropriate to the<br />

sentence in question.<br />

5 Entailment<br />

Areas <strong>of</strong> meaning like entailment divide less obviously into truth-functional semantic<br />

versus discourse areas. That uncle entails some feature like and that dead<br />

entails may be easily described within traditional structural semantics by<br />

means <strong>of</strong> so-called redundancy rules. Thus, sentence pairs like those in (8) and (9) can<br />

be recognized as logically sound within semantics alone:<br />

(8) a. Sue’s uncle arrived late.<br />

b. <strong>The</strong>refore, some male arrived late.<br />

(9) a. Judy has been dead for years.<br />

b. Judy is no longer alive.<br />

Other entailments, however – say, that rob entails and – become quite cumbersome in any structural semantics. Such

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!