28.10.2014 Views

Pascual Masullo (Pittsburgh) and Marcela Depiante

Pascual Masullo (Pittsburgh) and Marcela Depiante

Pascual Masullo (Pittsburgh) and Marcela Depiante

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

GLOW 27, Thessaloniki April 18–21, 2004<br />

44<br />

Gender is in the Lexicon, Number is in the Syntax:<br />

Evidence from Nominal Ellipsis in Spanish<br />

<strong>Pascual</strong> José <strong>Masullo</strong>, University of <strong>Pittsburgh</strong>, pascual@pitt.edu<br />

<strong>Marcela</strong> <strong>Depiante</strong>, Universidad del Comahue (Argentina), depiantem@yahoo.com<br />

It has been traditionally assumed that while gender is a lexical feature, number inflection is<br />

determined post-lexically. This paper claims that the behavior of nominal ellipsis in Spanish<br />

confirms this traditional view. As (1) below shows, while a mismatch in number is allowed<br />

between antecedent <strong>and</strong> elided element, ellipsis requires a match in gender features (a<br />

phenomenon noted by Brucart 1999, among others):<br />

(1) a. Juan visitó a sus tíos y Pedro visitó al tío suyo.<br />

John visited his uncles <strong>and</strong> Peter visited the (MASC-SING) his.<br />

“John visited his uncles <strong>and</strong> Peter visited his uncle.”<br />

b. * Juan visitó a su tío y Pedro visitó a la tía suya.<br />

John visited his uncle <strong>and</strong> Peter visited the (FEM-SING) his.<br />

“John visited his uncle <strong>and</strong> Peter visited his aunt”.<br />

This is reminiscent of the different behavior of main <strong>and</strong> auxiliary verbs with respect to<br />

ellipsis, noted by Lasnik (1995):<br />

(2) a. John slept soundly <strong>and</strong> Mary will sleep too.<br />

b. *John was here <strong>and</strong> Mary will be too.<br />

c. ?? John was sleeping soundly <strong>and</strong> Mary will be sleeping too.<br />

To account for the contrast in (2), Lasnik ab<strong>and</strong>ons Chomsky’s (1993, 1995)<br />

assumption that all elements enter the computational system fully inflected, <strong>and</strong> proposes a<br />

mixed system instead: while auxiliary verbs are already inflected in the numeration, main<br />

verbs enter the syntactic component without any inflectional markings. If this is so, Lasnik<br />

argues, at some point in the derivation we will have the representation (3) for (2a), in which<br />

the required identity between antecedent <strong>and</strong> elided element (viz. sleep) is guaranteed:<br />

(3) John T PRET sleep soundly <strong>and</strong> Mary will sleep too.<br />

We will assume that ellipsis consists in a deletion process at PF under formal identity<br />

(Chomsky & Lasnik 1993, Sag 1976, among others), <strong>and</strong> that the elided element in (1) above<br />

is the actual head noun <strong>and</strong> not a higher projection, as in the case of NP-ellipsis in English<br />

(Contreras 1989). If, moreover, we (partially) extend Lasnik’s mixed system to the nominal<br />

domain, we can account for the contrast in (1): Just like main verbs <strong>and</strong> T, N <strong>and</strong> Number<br />

enter the computational system separately. This will ensure the required identity for ellipsis in<br />

the case of (1a) prior to the overt movement of N to Number, as is shown in (4a). In contrast,<br />

if gender is an intrinsic feature of the noun, so that at no point in the derivation is the noun<br />

stem detached from its gender feature, we can’t obtain identity between the nouns involved in<br />

the case of (1b), <strong>and</strong> so ellipsis is not licensed, as is shown in (4b).<br />

(4) a. Juan visitó a su Num PL tío MASC y Pedro visitó al Num SG tío MASC suyo.<br />

b. * Juan visitó a su tío MASC y Pedro visitó a la tía FEM suya.<br />

Although number in Spanish is generally a variable feature (syntactically acquired, as<br />

we have seen), it can sometimes be intrinsic. Thus, some nouns are always plural, regardless


Main Session Abstracts<br />

of meaning (albricias “good tidings”, bodas “wedding”, noticias “news”, etc.). Our analysis<br />

therefore predicts that this kind of noun will not be able to license ellipsis of a singular but<br />

otherwise identical noun (in the few cases where this is possible). The unacceptability of (5)<br />

below bears out our prediction, lending further support to the analysis we have proposed:<br />

(5) ?? Las noticias de la televisión y la noticia de la radio no coinciden.<br />

The news of the TV <strong>and</strong> the news of the radio do not agree.<br />

“The news on the TV <strong>and</strong> those on the radio do not agree”.<br />

While nominal ellipsis prohibits a gender mismatch, ellipsis of nominal modifiers<br />

(quantifiers, adjectives, etc.) does not require gender identity (6), which might be taken as a<br />

serious counterexample to the proposal that gender is lexically determined:<br />

(6) El niño es bueno y la niña es buena también.<br />

The boy is good-MASC <strong>and</strong> the girl is good-FEM too.<br />

However, if we recall that the gender markings on adjectives <strong>and</strong> determiners in Romance<br />

result from agreement with the noun they modify, our proposal is reinforced, since these must<br />

necessarily enter the computational system without any gender specification. Thus, before<br />

noun modifiers acquire their gender (the mechanism whereby they do so is irrelevant for our<br />

purposes), the formal identity required for ellipsis is obtained:<br />

(7) El niño MASC es buen- y la niña FEM es buen- también.<br />

The following example of a related phenomenon in English (one-substitution) might<br />

also be construed as a counterexample:<br />

(8) I have a neighbor who once played third base for the White Sox, <strong>and</strong> I have one who was Miss<br />

Georgia of 1976 (McCawley 1998, p. 371).<br />

This apparent problem can be solved, however, once we realize that nouns like neighbor are<br />

not ambiguous with respect to gender, but rather referentially vague, i.e. the natural gender<br />

(or sex) of the referent must be pragmatically determined. There is no actual gender feature<br />

associated with this kind of noun, <strong>and</strong> so the formal identity required (in this case, for onesubstitution)<br />

is once again ensured.<br />

Finally, in light of the data examined, we will briefly consider the controversy over<br />

the need to postulate both Number <strong>and</strong> Gender projections within DP (as in Picallo 1991,<br />

Bernstein 1991), or only a Number projection (as in Ritter 1991).<br />

45

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!