Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

27.10.2014 Views

16 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ITALIAN RENAISSANCE desire to challenge this hierarchy. Their primary concern was instead to maintain the separation of the two realms, thus protecting their right to use rational, and only rational, arguments in philosophical contexts. Just as it was necessary, they asserted, when discussing matters of faith, to leave behind one’s philosophical mentality, so when discussing philosophy, one had to set aside one’s Christian faith. 4 Scholastics read Aristotle in late medieval Latin translations, which were unclassical in style and terminology. This type of Latin continued to be one of the hallmarks of scholastic treatises produced during the Renaissance. Another was their rigidly logical format: works were divided and subdivided into propositions or questions; arguments for and against were laid out; a solution was reached; possible objections were raised and appropriate responses supplied. This structure had the advantage of covering issues from all possible angles and ensuring that the opinions of a wide variety of ancient and medieval thinkers were aired, even if Aristotle’s were the most frequently endorsed. In the judgement of Petrarch (Francesco Petrarca, 1304–74), the founder of Italian humanism, such treatises were barbaric, tediously pedantic, arid and incomprehensible. 5 His own style was diametrically opposed to that of the scholastics. He modelled his Latin prose on that of the best classical authors, avoiding terms and expressions which were unknown in antiquity. He also eschewed the methodical rigour and systematic presentation found in scholastic treatises, favouring instead a loose—almost at times rambling—structure and adopting genres such as the letter, dialogue and invective which had been used by the Roman authors he most admired. Deeply interested in the state of his own soul, Petrarch ridiculed the scholastics for devoting so much of their energies to natural, rather than moral, philosophy: ‘What is the use,’ he asked, ‘of knowing the nature of quadrupeds, fowls, fishes, and serpents and not knowing or even neglecting man’s nature…?’ The secrets of nature were ‘mysteries of God’, which Christians should accept with ‘humble faith’ rather than attempt to seize ‘in haughty arrogance’. 6 As for scholastic logicians, Petrarch had nothing but contempt for what he regarded as their empty loquacity and their addiction to disputation for its own sake: ‘They get the greatest pleasure out of strife and set out not to find the truth but to quarrel.’ 7 He especially disliked the logica modernorum, a highly technical and semantically orientated form of dialectic associated with William of Ockham and his followers, which had come over to Italy from England in the mid-fourteenth century. Petrarch believed that it reduced all speculation to problems of formal terminology, thereby deflecting philosophers from more important matters and turning theologians into mere dialecticians. 8 Another aspect of scholasticism attacked by Petrarch was the dominance of Aristotelianism. While there was much of value in Aristotle’s philosophy, there was also a great deal that from a Christian point of view was harmful, in particular his failure to give a firm endorsement to the immortality of the soul and his belief in the eternity of the world. Aristotle was not alone among pagans

RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM 17 in holding these erroneous views, but he presented the greatest danger, Petrarch believed, because he had the most authority and the greatest number of followers. And while the pagan Aristotle could not be blamed for holding these errors, his present-day acolytes had no excuse. 9 Despite their adulation of Aristotle, the scholastics failed, in Petrarch’s opinion, to understand his thought. They disdained eloquence, treating it as ‘an obstacle and a disgrace to philosophy’, whereas Aristotle had believed that it was ‘a mighty adornment’. 10 He blamed the inelegant style which characterized Latin versions of Aristotle not on the author’s inattention to style but on the ignorance of his medieval translators—a censure which was to be frequently repeated by later humanists. 11 Yet aside from the ethical treatises, Petrarch’s acquaintance with Aristotle’s writings was neither wide nor deep. If Petrarch was ill-informed about ‘the Philosopher’, he was positively ignorant about ‘the Commentator’, Averroes, probably never having read anything at all by him. This did not stop him from criticizing the Arabic interpreter even more strongly than he had done the Greek philosopher. 12 In sharp contrast to the scholastics, who considered Arabic learning to be an important part of their intellectual legacy, Petrarch and his humanist successors restricted their philosophical interests almost exclusively to the Greco-Roman past. Among the doctrines traditionally associated with Averroism was the double truth, 13 which theologians such as Thomas Aquinas rejected, maintaining that there was only one truth, the truth of faith, and that any philosophical proposition which contradicted it was necessarily false. Petrarch shared this point of view, arguing that since ‘knowledge of the true faith’ was ‘the highest, most certain, and ultimately most beatifying of all knowledge’, those who temporarily set it aside, wishing ‘to appear as philosophers rather than as Christians’, were in reality ‘seeking the truth after having rejected the truth’. 14 According to him, scholastics were forced into this position not by an inevitable conflict between philosophy and religion, but rather by their support for one particular philosophy, Aristotelianism, which on certain crucial issues —the eternity of the world and the immortality of the soul—denied the fundamental truths of Christianity. The solution was therefore not to abandon philosophy per se, but to adopt a different sort of philosophy, one which avoided these theological errors. That philosophy, for Petrarch, was Platonism. Plato, who offered convincing rational arguments in support of both the immortality of the soul and the creation of the world, had risen higher ‘in divine matters’ than other pagans. Because Plato ‘came nearer than all the others’ to Christian truth, he, and not his student Aristotle, deserved to be called ‘the prince of philosophy’. By promoting Plato as a more theologically correct, and hence more profound, philosopher than Aristotle, Petrarch was able to mount yet another challenge to the scholastic philosophy of his day. 15 But for all his advocacy of Plato, Petrarch’s knowledge of his works—like that of all Western scholars in this period—was very limited. Of the four dialogues then available in Latin, he made extensive use only of the

16 THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ITALIAN RENAISSANCE<br />

desire to challenge this hierarchy. Their primary concern was instead to maintain<br />

the separation <strong>of</strong> the two realms, thus protecting their right to use rational, and<br />

only rational, arguments in philosophical contexts. Just as it was necessary, they<br />

asserted, when discussing matters <strong>of</strong> faith, to leave behind one’s philosophical<br />

mentality, so when discussing philosophy, one had to set aside one’s Christian<br />

faith. 4<br />

Scholastics read Aristotle in late medieval Latin translations, which were<br />

unclassical in style and terminology. This type <strong>of</strong> Latin continued to be one <strong>of</strong><br />

the hallmarks <strong>of</strong> scholastic treatises produced during the Renaissance. Another<br />

was their rigidly logical format: works were divided and subdivided into<br />

propositions or questions; arguments for and against were laid out; a solution<br />

was reached; possible objections were raised and appropriate responses supplied.<br />

This structure had the advantage <strong>of</strong> covering issues from all possible angles and<br />

ensuring that the opinions <strong>of</strong> a wide variety <strong>of</strong> ancient and medieval thinkers<br />

were aired, even if Aristotle’s were the most frequently endorsed.<br />

In the judgement <strong>of</strong> Petrarch (Francesco Petrarca, 1304–74), the founder <strong>of</strong><br />

Italian humanism, such treatises were barbaric, tediously pedantic, arid and<br />

incomprehensible. 5 His own style was diametrically opposed to that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

scholastics. He modelled his Latin prose on that <strong>of</strong> the best classical authors,<br />

avoiding terms and expressions which were unknown in antiquity. He also<br />

eschewed the methodical rigour and systematic presentation found in scholastic<br />

treatises, favouring instead a loose—almost at times rambling—structure and<br />

adopting genres such as the letter, dialogue and invective which had been used<br />

by the Roman authors he most admired.<br />

Deeply interested in the state <strong>of</strong> his own soul, Petrarch ridiculed the<br />

scholastics for devoting so much <strong>of</strong> their energies to natural, rather than moral,<br />

philosophy: ‘What is the use,’ he asked, ‘<strong>of</strong> knowing the nature <strong>of</strong> quadrupeds,<br />

fowls, fishes, and serpents and not knowing or even neglecting man’s nature…?’<br />

The secrets <strong>of</strong> nature were ‘mysteries <strong>of</strong> God’, which Christians should accept<br />

with ‘humble faith’ rather than attempt to seize ‘in haughty arrogance’. 6 As for<br />

scholastic logicians, Petrarch had nothing but contempt for what he regarded as<br />

their empty loquacity and their addiction to disputation for its own sake: ‘They<br />

get the greatest pleasure out <strong>of</strong> strife and set out not to find the truth but to<br />

quarrel.’ 7 He especially disliked the logica modernorum, a highly technical and<br />

semantically orientated form <strong>of</strong> dialectic associated with William <strong>of</strong> Ockham and<br />

his followers, which had come over to Italy from England in the mid-fourteenth<br />

century. Petrarch believed that it reduced all speculation to problems <strong>of</strong> formal<br />

terminology, thereby deflecting philosophers from more important matters and<br />

turning theologians into mere dialecticians. 8<br />

Another aspect <strong>of</strong> scholasticism attacked by Petrarch was the dominance <strong>of</strong><br />

Aristotelianism. While there was much <strong>of</strong> value in Aristotle’s philosophy, there<br />

was also a great deal that from a Christian point <strong>of</strong> view was harmful, in<br />

particular his failure to give a firm endorsement to the immortality <strong>of</strong> the soul<br />

and his belief in the eternity <strong>of</strong> the world. Aristotle was not alone among pagans

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!