27.10.2014 Views

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

Routledge History of Philosophy Volume IV

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

12 RENAISSANCE AND SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY RATIONALISM<br />

31 cf. to Mersenne, 11 October 1638 (CSM iii, p. 124), where Descartes criticizes<br />

Galileo on the grounds that ‘his building lacks a foundation’. (See also G. Molland,<br />

Chapter 3 <strong>of</strong> this volume, p. 129.)<br />

32 This view has been challenged, where Spinoza is concerned, by Alan Donagan<br />

(Spinoza, Brighton, Harvester, 1988, esp. p. 68). Donagan argues that Spinoza did<br />

not so much try to justify the principles <strong>of</strong> the new physics as generalize from them.<br />

It has also been argued by Stuart Brown that Leibniz was a foundationalist only<br />

during his early years, but later took the view that the philosopher should seek out<br />

and explore fruitful hypotheses (Stuart Brown, Leibniz, Brighton, Harvester, 1984).<br />

I have discussed this thesis in my paper, ‘Leibniz’s Philosophical Aims:<br />

Foundation-laying or Problem-solving?’, in A. Heinekamp, W.Lenzen and<br />

M.Schneider (eds) Mathesis Rationis: Festschrift für Heinrich Schepers (Münster,<br />

Nodus, 1990), pp. 67–78.<br />

33 Meditations V, CSM ii, 45. Compare Leibniz, Nouveaux Essais, <strong>IV</strong>. 11.14, on the<br />

‘eternal truths’ <strong>of</strong> mathematics.<br />

34 There were two such methods, traditionally known as ‘analysis’ and ‘synthesis’.<br />

These are discussed in this volume in Chapter 3 (pp. 107–9), Chapter 5 (pp. 183–6)<br />

and Chapter 8 (pp. 279–80).<br />

35 Though Leibniz added the qualification that it must first be shown that the concept<br />

<strong>of</strong> God—i.e. <strong>of</strong> a most perfect or necessary being—is self-consistent. See, for<br />

example, Leibniz, Discourse on Metaphysics, sec. 23.<br />

36 cf. p. 4 above.<br />

37 The main sources <strong>of</strong> deism were Lord Herbert <strong>of</strong> Cherbury, De Veritate (1624), and<br />

Locke, The Reasonableness <strong>of</strong> Christianity (1695). However, they were not the sole<br />

sources; as Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Stuart Brown has pointed out to me, there is reason to believe<br />

that the seventeenth-century rationalists had some influence on deistic thought.<br />

Deism has a long history, and the term meant different things to different people.<br />

(Samuel Clarke, in his Demonstration <strong>of</strong> the Being and Attributes <strong>of</strong> God (1704–6),<br />

recognized no fewer than four types <strong>of</strong> deism.) What matters here is that many<br />

deists believed in a creative deity whose wisdom and power are such as to make it<br />

irrational to suppose that he should intervene in the workings <strong>of</strong> the universe, once<br />

he has created it. This position is close to that taken by seventeenth-century<br />

rationalists. Pascal declared that he ‘could not forgive’ Descartes for reducing<br />

God’s role in the workings <strong>of</strong> the universe almost to nothing (Pensées, Brunschvicg<br />

ed., No. 77), and a similar position is implied by what other seventeenth-century<br />

rationalists said about miracles. For Spinoza, it was impossible that any miracles<br />

should occur; for Leibniz and Malebranche, God’s miraculous intervention in the<br />

universe was a possibility, but such interventions were very few. See, for example,<br />

G.H.R.Parkinson, ‘Spinoza on Miracles and Natural Law’, Revue internationale de<br />

philosophie 31 (1977) 145–57, and Logic and Reality in Leibniz’s Metaphysics<br />

(Oxford, Clarendon, 1965), pp. 102, 155–6; Daisie Radner, Malebranche (Assen,<br />

Van Gorcum, 1978), p. 32.<br />

38 Descartes tried to derive universal laws <strong>of</strong> science from the immutability <strong>of</strong> God.<br />

Spinoza seems to have thought that no scientific laws other than those that actually<br />

hold are strictly speaking thinkable, though in his attempt to establish such laws he<br />

was compelled to appeal to experience. (See Chapter 8, pp. 289, 298, on Spinoza’s<br />

‘postulates’. See also Chapter 3, pp. 131–2, for Descartes’s views about hypotheses

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!