27.09.2014 Views

Notes on Relativity and Cosmology - Physics Department, UCSB

Notes on Relativity and Cosmology - Physics Department, UCSB

Notes on Relativity and Cosmology - Physics Department, UCSB

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

56 CHAPTER 3. EINSTEIN AND INERTIAL FRAMES<br />

carefully, taking the greatest care with our logical reas<strong>on</strong>ing. As we saw in chapter<br />

1, careful logical reas<strong>on</strong>ing can <strong>on</strong>ly proceed from clearly stated assumpti<strong>on</strong>s<br />

(a.k.a. ‘axioms’ or ‘postulates’). We’re throwing out almost everything that we<br />

thought we understood about space <strong>and</strong> time. So then, what should we keep?<br />

We’ll keep the bare minimum c<strong>on</strong>sistent with Einstein’s idea. We will take our<br />

postulates to be:<br />

I) The laws of physics are the same in every inertial frame.<br />

II) The speed of light in an inertial frame is always c = 2.99... × 10 8 m/s.<br />

We also keep Newt<strong>on</strong>’s first law, which is just the definiti<strong>on</strong> of an inertial frame:<br />

There exists a class of reference frames (called inertial frames) in which an<br />

object moves in a straight line at c<strong>on</strong>stant speed if <strong>and</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly if zero net force<br />

acts <strong>on</strong> that object.<br />

Finally, we will need a few properties of inertial frames. We therefore postulate<br />

the following familiar statement.<br />

Object A is in an inertial frame ⇔ Object A experiences zero force ⇔ Object<br />

A moves at c<strong>on</strong>stant velocity in any other inertial frame.<br />

Since we no l<strong>on</strong>ger have S <strong>and</strong> T, we can no l<strong>on</strong>ger derive this last statement.<br />

It turns out that this statement does in fact follow from even more elementary<br />

(albeit technical) assumpti<strong>on</strong>s that we could introduce <strong>and</strong> use to derive it. This<br />

is essentially what Einstein did. However, in practice it is easiest just to assume<br />

that the result is true <strong>and</strong> go from there.<br />

Finally, it will be c<strong>on</strong>venient to introduce a new term:<br />

Definiti<strong>on</strong> An “observer” is a pers<strong>on</strong> or apparatus that makes measurements.<br />

Using this term, assumpti<strong>on</strong> II becomes: The speed of light is always c =<br />

2.9979 × 10 8 m/s as measured by any inertial observer.<br />

By the way, it will be c<strong>on</strong>venient to be a little sloppy in our language <strong>and</strong> to say<br />

that two observers with zero relative velocity are in the same reference frame,<br />

even if they are separated in space.<br />

3.2 Time <strong>and</strong> Positi<strong>on</strong>, take II<br />

Recall that in Chapter 1 we used the (mistaken!) old assumpti<strong>on</strong>s T <strong>and</strong> S to<br />

show that our previous noti<strong>on</strong>s of time <strong>and</strong> positi<strong>on</strong> were well-defined. Thus, we<br />

can no l<strong>on</strong>ger rely even <strong>on</strong> the definiti<strong>on</strong>s of ‘time <strong>and</strong> positi<strong>on</strong> of some event in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!