26.09.2014 Views

biology-immigration

biology-immigration

biology-immigration

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

KYKLOS, Vol. 65 – May 2012 – No. 2, 164–178<br />

Biology, Immigration, and Public Policy<br />

Gregory B. Christainsen*<br />

I. INTRODUCTION<br />

What is human nature? To what extent is human behavior determined by biological<br />

factors? To what extent is it influenced by social factors: child-rearing<br />

practices, peer groups, intellectual currents, and public policies? Much debate on<br />

these matters has unfolded since the time of Darwin.<br />

This article discusses modern developments in the fields of <strong>biology</strong>, evolutionary<br />

psychology, psychometrics, and behavioral genetics. Researchers from<br />

many countries have now contributed to this literature. It then refers to related<br />

<strong>immigration</strong> issues and public policies – e.g., the American Head Start program<br />

and European preschool efforts – that have been recommended to improve the<br />

cognitive skills and preference sets of immigrant children.<br />

Section II of the paper surveys perspectives on human nature, starting with<br />

those of Adam Smith and David Hume – two Scottish Enlightenment figures who<br />

influenced the emergence of a distinct discipline known as economics – and<br />

proceeding to those of Darwin’s circle, anthropologist Franz Boas, and more<br />

recent thinkers. Section III highlights some of the major contributions to the<br />

scientific fields referred to above. Section IV discusses the relevance of the<br />

scientific research for <strong>immigration</strong> issues. Section V refers to related research on<br />

preschool education and provides a summary and concluding remarks.<br />

II. HUMAN NATURE<br />

Adam Smith is justly famous in the history of economic thought for maintaining<br />

that human behavior is largely self-interested in nature. In The Theory of Moral<br />

Sentiments (1759/1976) he also highlighted the human capacity for sympathy,<br />

but he had no illusions about the strength of people’s humanitarian inclinations.<br />

* Professor, California State University, East Bay, USA 94542. E-mail: gregory.christainsen@<br />

csueastbay.edu. The author would like to thank participants in the 2011 conference of the Association of<br />

Private Enterprise Education for productive discussions. The journal editors also offered helpful comments.<br />

David Cesarini provided leads to some of the reference material. The usual caveat applies.<br />

164<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 9600 Garsington Road,<br />

Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

For the most part, Smith’s friend David Hume echoed Smith on human nature,<br />

alleging that people have “limited generosity” (Hayek 1967). Hume also<br />

launched a notorious attack on orthodox religion and the so-called Argument<br />

from Design. According to the argument, the order in the universe cannot be<br />

explained without invoking a Grand Designer, or God. But just as Smith talked<br />

of the market as a self-ordering process, Hume argued that the order in the<br />

universe as a whole does not require a Central Planner. The universe has selfordering<br />

processes of its own (Hume 1779/1990).<br />

Hume went so far as to offer a preview of Charles Darwin’s theory of adaptive<br />

evolution, noting that the “. . . parts in the animals or vegetables and their curious<br />

adjustment to each other” does not require a Designer because he (Hume)<br />

“would fain know how an animal could subsist unless its parts were so adjusted?<br />

Do we not find that it perishes whenever this adjustment ceases, and that its<br />

matter corrupting tries some new form?” Human beings cannot “pretend to an<br />

exemption from the lot of all living animals” (Hayek 1967).<br />

Hume saw the human mind itself as consisting of features selected for in a<br />

process of evolution. For example, we hold dogmatically to common-sense<br />

notions of physics that cannot be proven with absolute certainty – e.g., that<br />

gravity will continue to exist in the near future. If we did not subscribe to such<br />

common-sense notions, we might take actions that would threaten our survival<br />

(e.g., leaving a building via an upstairs window) (Hume 1739–40).<br />

Erasmus Darwin, the grandfather of Charles, was a contemporary of Smith<br />

and Hume and himself a participant in the Enlightenment. His influence on<br />

Charles has been widely accepted by intellectual historians. However, in his<br />

book, On the Origin of Species (1859), Charles Darwin did not refer to the<br />

market order discussed by Adam Smith, nor did he endorse what was later called<br />

“Social Darwinism”. Hume had pointed out long before (Hume 1739–40) that<br />

showing something is the case, does not, in and of itself, tell us what ought to<br />

be the case. For example, if free markets result in huge differences in<br />

wealth between rich and poor, we are not automatically obliged to accept those<br />

differences.<br />

The science of genetics was still primitive at the time of Darwin’s work. His<br />

half-cousin Francis Galton became the world’s leading proponent of the view<br />

that human traits are strongly influenced by heredity. A behavioral geneticist<br />

before “behavioral genetics” existed as a formal academic discipline, Galton<br />

suggested that researchers conduct studies of identical twins as a way to try to<br />

isolate the effects of nature and nurture on outcomes. If, when placed in different<br />

social environments, the twins ended up more or less the same in terms of<br />

intelligence and dispositions, it would suggest a major role for heredity.<br />

However, if the twins turned out to be very different, it would lend support to the<br />

view that factors in the social environment are of greater importance in shaping<br />

people.<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 165


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

Many commentators today are unaware of how prevalent the hereditarian<br />

viewpoint was in the late 19 th and early 20 th centuries. In the United States 30<br />

states passed laws providing for compulsory sterilization of groups of individuals.<br />

By the time such laws had been enacted, however, socialist and progressive<br />

ideas had already begun to permeate the intellectual classes of Europe and the<br />

US, and these ideas would eventually prevail (at least in a practical sense) on the<br />

question of nature vs. nurture.<br />

Karl Marx, of course, had an enduring influence. He asserted that “the human<br />

essence is no abstraction inherent in each individual. In its reality it is the<br />

ensemble of the social relations.” Marxists have fought hard to keep Darwinian<br />

concepts out of the social realm. Darwinism is thought to offer a quite good<br />

account of the development of non-human species and the evolution of humans’<br />

physical attributes, but the development of human consciousness is thought to<br />

depend on the economic system and the interplay of economic classes. The<br />

human mind can only reach its full potential with the emergence of a classless<br />

society, i.e., communism.<br />

Marxists were thus quite happy to see Darwinism undermine belief in the god<br />

of Christianity, but not the god of communism. The influence of Marxist ideas<br />

concerning the nature of Man remained strong for most of the 20 th century. There<br />

was a downplaying of any independent role for ethnicity (and gender). To be<br />

sure, one might observe differing behaviors from one ethnic group to another, but<br />

this was seen – even by many economists – to be the result of the different social<br />

conditions in which the groups had to operate.<br />

In intellectual circles support for eugenics and for rankings of races on human<br />

traits went out of fashion with the end of Nazism. In the field of anthropology<br />

Franz Boas led the way by even denying the existence of distinct biological<br />

races. Aside from superficial characteristics such as skin and eye color or hair<br />

texture, the idea of “races” was viewed as a purely social construct. The American<br />

Anthropological Association has endorsed this view into the 21 st century.<br />

The victory of the nurturists had far-reaching consequences. If there are no<br />

significant biological differences among races – and no significant differences<br />

between male and female brains – why on average are there very different labor<br />

market outcomes for races and genders? Racist and sexist attitudes and institutions<br />

are typically held responsible.<br />

III. PSYCHOMETRICS, BIOLOGY, EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY,<br />

AND BEHAVIORAL GENETICS<br />

It was in this milieu in 1969 that Arthur Jensen dropped a 123-page bomb in the<br />

Harvard Educational Review (Jensen 1969). Jensen argued that (a) there is a<br />

genuine difference in the average intelligence level of whites and blacks, (b)<br />

166 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

compensatory education has little to recommend it as a way of improving<br />

people’s general ability to reason and to learn, and (c) the white-black difference<br />

probably has a genetic component. The backlash against the article was so<br />

intense that Jensen had to be provided security just to help him walk across the<br />

campus at Berkeley 1 .<br />

A similar response confronted Harvard entomologist Edward O. Wilson with<br />

the publication of Socio<strong>biology</strong>: A New Synthesis (Wilson 1975). In Wilson’s case<br />

his sin was to view people’s behavior in biological terms; people are seen as just<br />

another animal species, albeit with more highly developed brains. From a Marxist<br />

perspective, Wilson’s work was an illegitimate extension of Darwinian concepts<br />

into the human realm. Two Marxist colleagues of Wilson, Richard Lewontin and<br />

Stephen Jay Gould, led the charge, with the climactic moment in the struggle being<br />

a conference at which Wilson was doused with a pitcher of water.<br />

Perhaps the most persuasive work to emerge in opposition to a Marxist<br />

perspective has been that of Thomas Bouchard, Sandra Scarr, Robert Plomin<br />

(Plomin et al. 2008), and others in the field of behavioral genetics, with their use<br />

of twin and adoption studies. While Eric Turkheimer in particular has pleaded<br />

with his peers not to underestimate the impact of the social environment, the<br />

findings in the field have been stunning: identical twins separated early in life<br />

nevertheless resemble one another later on in terms of intelligence and personality;<br />

they tend to resemble each other more so than do fraternal twins separated<br />

early in life. Fraternal twins, in turn, even if separated at birth, tend to resemble<br />

each other later in life more so than two people selected at random off the street.<br />

On the other hand, biologically-unrelated adoptees reared in the same family<br />

do not show a clear tendency to resemble one another later in life – despite the<br />

shared environment of their foster parents and the surrounding community. How<br />

could one expect a government program to shape people in a predictable way if<br />

living in a certain family has no predictable (long-term) result?<br />

Most controversially, black adoptees raised in white families ended up scoring<br />

near a typical “black” level on intelligence tests (on average), not at all near a<br />

“white” level; by adulthood, their adoptive parents and the community in which<br />

they were raised counted for essentially nothing as far as general intelligence was<br />

concerned (Weinberg, Scarr, and Waldman 1992) 2 . Less noticed was the finding<br />

1. In a separate work Jensen (1980) spelled out – to the satisfaction of most practitioners in the psychology<br />

profession – the statistical conditions that have to met for tests to be considered unbiased. He went on<br />

to argue that the white-black difference in average test scores cannot be explained by test bias.<br />

Furthermore, controlling for socioeconomic status only marginally affects average racial differences in<br />

the results, and socioeconomic status itself depends on intelligence, among other factors (Jensen 1998).<br />

2. It is true that the authors of the study suggested that its results could be due to factors in the social<br />

environment. Black children raised in white households might be treated differently than white children,<br />

not only by their adoptive parents, but also by members of the surrounding community. They also said<br />

that the results may have been confounded by preadoption influences. Note, however, that the measured<br />

IQs of the adopted black children originally were found to be higher than the average for black children,<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 167


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

from formal personality testing (DeBerry 1991) that, relative to whites, the black<br />

adoptees were also inclined (on average) to be impulsive, extroverted, aggressive,<br />

rebellious, and hedonistic.<br />

In sharp contrast, East Asians growing up in white households in the US and<br />

Belgium have tended to score considerably above the white mean in terms of<br />

intelligence (Winick, Meyer, and Harris 1975; Clark and Hanisee 1982; Frydman<br />

and Lynn 1989). East Asians, or at least the Chinese among them, also tend to be<br />

relatively quiescent independently of their child-rearing environment and have<br />

less variable heart rates (Kagan, Resnick, and Snidman 1988).<br />

While not subscribing to a genetic view of racial differences in average<br />

intelligence or personality, Turkheimer (2000, 2011) has endorsed a stillprovocative<br />

set of “laws of behavioral genetics”: (1) all human behavioral traits<br />

are heritable; (2) by adulthood, the effect of being raised in the same family is<br />

smaller than the effect of genes; and (3) a substantial portion of the variation in<br />

complex behavioral traits is not accounted for by either genetic inheritance or<br />

families. For Turkheimer “the bottom-line is that everything is heritable, an<br />

outcome that has taken all sides of the nature-nurture debate by surprise”<br />

[emphasis added]. Happiness (De Neve et al. 2011, Nettle 2011), religiosity,<br />

homosexuality, general political orientation (Settle et al. 2010) – they all have a<br />

genetic component.<br />

Most studies have found personality characteristics – conscientiousness, introversion,<br />

neuroticism, etc. – to be as much as 50 percent heritable, but typically<br />

their heritability comes out lower than 50 percent. Richard Nisbett (2009) grants<br />

that intelligence has a significant genetic component, but argues that it, too, has<br />

a heritability of less than 50 percent. Turkheimer has argued that the heritability<br />

of intelligence is lower for people of lower socioeconomic status (e.g., Turkheimer<br />

et al. 2003), whereas adoptees tend to be placed in middle and upper-middle<br />

income families. However, most studies of adults (as opposed to children) have<br />

found general intelligence to be strongly heritable. Two twin studies of Indians<br />

reared in India (Nathawat and Puri 1995; Pal, Shyam, and Singh 1997) found the<br />

heritability of intelligence to exceed 0.80.<br />

so we are supposed to believe that social factors may first have acted to raise their IQs and then acted<br />

to bring them back down. No one has shown the mechanism whereby the social environment would have<br />

had these effects, whereas the pattern directly conforms to what would be predicted by the behavioral<br />

genetics literature; the role of heredity increases with age.<br />

It is also true that, later on, the study’s most famous author, Sandra Scarr, in an article testifying to the<br />

strength of Arthur Jensen’s integrity, admitted that she and her colleagues had deliberately slanted their<br />

narrative to appease their overwhelmingly nurturist peers. “The test performance of the . . . adoptees was<br />

not different from that of ordinary Black children reared by their own families in the same area of the<br />

country. My colleagues and I reported the data accurately and as fully as possible, and then tried to make<br />

the results palatable to environmentally committed colleagues. In retrospect, this was a mistake” (Scarr<br />

1998).<br />

168 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

All factors considered, earning income – which involves intelligence, aggressiveness,<br />

other personality characteristics, and looks – appears to be at least<br />

40–60 percent heritable (Bowles and Gintis 2002; Björklund, Jäntti, and Solon<br />

2005; Cesarini 2010). Further research on permanent income, as opposed to 1–3<br />

year income measures influenced by transitory factors, is expected to yield<br />

higher heritability estimates.<br />

The absence of influences from the “shared environment” (e.g., family) on<br />

intelligence and personality has been startling to researchers, and it should be<br />

emphasized that this result has still not been absorbed by many of the people who<br />

participate in the making of public policy. Indeed, many are completely unaware<br />

of it. Families (or governments) can certainly provide opportunities and encourage<br />

achievement by children, but child-rearing practices and the presence of<br />

siblings affect personality and intelligence much less than people generally<br />

imagine. And as David Rowe (1994) pointed out, parenting styles themselves are<br />

somewhat heritable.<br />

In childhood, child-rearing practices do seem to have an impact, but the<br />

impact fades by adulthood. It is thus now commonplace in behavioral genetics to<br />

say that the influence of heredity increases with age, whereas a “common sense,”<br />

but false, assumption of many people is that child-rearing has a cumulative<br />

impact on the way people are by adulthood.<br />

As far as factors in the social environment outside the family are concerned,<br />

Judith Rich Harris (1998) has stressed the possible impact of peer groups, with<br />

the roles that children adopt inside groups being somewhat dependent on chance<br />

factors. For example, a child who might have developed leadership qualities in<br />

one group may end up being an also-ran in another group. Rowe, the tenacious<br />

hereditarian, pointed out that the peer groups to which children gravitate are also<br />

somewhat dependent on genetically-influenced inclinations.<br />

Another line of research in <strong>biology</strong> emphasizes the somewhat random nature<br />

of early development. For example, identical twins sharing a womb will not get<br />

exactly the same nutrients from their mother. One twin may get more and be<br />

heavier at birth. The tiny, rather fragile brains of fetuses are subject to disturbances<br />

during pregnancy such that an axon, configurations of cells, or neural<br />

pathways may not end up the same in otherwise identical creatures. Experiments<br />

with genetically identical mice, flies, and other creatures have found that, even at<br />

an early stage, they do not necessarily resemble one another even when put in the<br />

same environment (Finch and Kirkwood 2000, Austad 2000).<br />

Genetic mutations may play a critical role. It has been understood for some<br />

time that genetic mutations occur during the long sweep of evolution. Mutations<br />

can result from radiation, viruses, mutagenic chemicals, and other sources. What<br />

recent research has added to the discussion, with special application to identical<br />

twins, is the common presence of “somatic mutations,” i.e., alterations in DNA<br />

that often occur after conception. Thus, these mutations are not passed on to the<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 169


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

next generation of children. If the mutant cells then divide, an individual can<br />

have patches of tissue that differ genetically from that of the body’s other cells.<br />

More broadly, identical twins may differ from each other in a variety of ways<br />

although they are still much more alike one another than biologically-unrelated<br />

people (Maiti et al. 2011).<br />

Cells may lose or acquire additional DNA as they divide. Some genes, such as<br />

those in the brain, are notorious for doing this. The mechanism that causes genes<br />

to increase or decrease in number is not yet well understood, but the upshot of<br />

this research is that, even before birth, and well before the social environment<br />

could have an impact, it is predictable that monozygotic twins will vary in the<br />

amount of DNA they have, a matter of potentially great importance for their<br />

respective psychiatric profiles (Maiti et al. 2011).<br />

There thus seem to be chance influences on development that can be said to be<br />

biological, but not inherited. The field of epigenetics, which expands on the<br />

possibility that factors in the environment can cause genes to “switch off” and<br />

have an impact on the next generation as well, also raises provocative questions,<br />

but there has as yet been no big payoff from research efforts in the field.<br />

Wilson’s “socio<strong>biology</strong>” was so vociferously attacked that researchers<br />

started to shy away from practicing it. Led by John Tooby and Leda Cosmides<br />

(e.g., Cosmides and Tooby 1992), “evolutionary psychology” is a somewhat<br />

more acceptable field (in a political sense) that has emerged to help take its<br />

place. What has helped to make it more acceptable is its emphasis (so far) on<br />

human similarities instead of human differences. An emphasis on similarities<br />

would appear to be more consistent with a vision of Equality for the peoples<br />

of the world. A focus on differences raises the discomfiting specter of Inequality.<br />

In this case, the similarities refer to human dispositions that appear to<br />

exist irrespective of culture: e.g., preferences for one’s own children and kin,<br />

admiration for generosity, facial expressions for various emotions, incest<br />

taboos, beliefs about death, privacy for copulation, revulsion at the sight of<br />

excrement, etc.<br />

Evolutionary psychology has also ventured into biological differences<br />

between male and female brains (e.g., Pinker 2002, chap 18), but it has shied<br />

away from discussions of racial differences. Nevertheless, there has now been<br />

a great deal of genetic research indicating the existence of biologicallydistinguishable<br />

peoples. Groups of people differ not only in terms of eye color,<br />

hair texture, and the like, but in terms of many other physical characteristics<br />

including average brain size (Rushton and Ankney 2009).<br />

Genetic classifications of different peoples do not necessarily correlate with<br />

skin color, but they are essentially continental in scope and do correspond<br />

rather well with every-day concepts of “race” or “ethnicity”, including selfclassifications.<br />

Cavalli-Sforza (Cavalli-Sforza, Menozzi, and Piazza 1994),<br />

Rosenberg (Rosenberg et al 2002), Risch (Tang et al. 2005), and Allocco<br />

170 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

(Allocco et al. 2007) have been just a few of the major contributors to this<br />

literature. Serre and Paabo (2004) have dissented from the direction of this<br />

research.<br />

With improved technology now available for the research, studies are now<br />

finding “genetic clusters within clusters,” for example, Ashkenazi Jews who are<br />

biologically distinguishable from other ethnic Europeans, who can, in turn, be<br />

reliably divided into gentiles with southeastern European ancestry and gentiles<br />

with northwestern European ancestry (Price et al. 2008).<br />

Of course, it is a very contentious matter, especially in the United States, to<br />

suggest that ethnic Europeans and people of sub-Saharan African ancestry may<br />

differ with respect to the frequency with which they possess the genes that are<br />

relevant for intelligence. Rushton and Jensen (2005) presented multiple lines<br />

of (indirect) evidence that they do, including data concerning the ubiquity of<br />

the difference in mean intelligence levels on a worldwide basis, average brain<br />

size, reaction times, and the intelligence of transracial adoptees. Richard<br />

Nisbett (2005, 2009) has been perhaps their most notable critic, but Nisbett<br />

now concurs that there is such a thing as general intelligence (‘g’), that IQ is<br />

predictive of success at school and work, that genes significantly influence IQ<br />

scores, that IQ is related to brain size, and that some studies have found<br />

average brain size to vary along racial lines. There is now a consensus<br />

(Wicherts et al. 2010a, Lynn and Meisenberg 2010, Wicherts et al. 2010b) that<br />

the average level of intelligence in sub-Saharan Africa is quite low. The only<br />

question is why.<br />

The more pressing issue for Europe concerns the intelligence of immigrants<br />

of North African and Middle Eastern/South Asian origin, including Turks. There<br />

is a significant – on the order of 8 percent – difference in average brain size<br />

between the indigenous people of such ancestry and ethnic Europeans (Jurgens<br />

et al. 1990, Smith and Beals 1990). Again, a consensus is emerging that there<br />

are real and substantial differences in average intelligence between the immigrants<br />

and the native populations. Gaps in average test results narrow some over<br />

time, but sizable differences persist into the second and third generations of<br />

immigrant families. Some groups in Britain have scored reasonably well, but a<br />

typical group of immigrants on the European continent from North Africa/South<br />

Asia averages at least half a standard deviation lower on an IQ test than ethnic<br />

Europeans.<br />

The (average) IQ deficits of indigenous South Asians and North Africans can<br />

to some extent be plausibly explained, at least in part, by lower standards for<br />

nutrition, health, and education. Nutritional differences can also help to account<br />

for differences in average brain size across groups. In the case of immigrants in<br />

more affluent countries such as Germany, France, and the Netherlands, however,<br />

efforts to downplay the possible existence of genetic factors start to lose their<br />

force.<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 171


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

The low average test scores may be partly due to the practice of cousin<br />

marriages in some segments of these immigrant groups. Contemporary scientific<br />

research suggests that cousin marriages can result in increased birth defects,<br />

illness, and infant mortality. British Pakistanis, more than 50 percent of whom<br />

marry first cousins, account for almost a third of all British children with genetic<br />

illnesses (BBC News, 16 November 2005). Schull and Neel (1965) found an<br />

average IQ deficit of 4 points among Japanese children produced after marriages<br />

of first cousins. Others (Ansari and Sinha 1978, Afzal and Sinha 1983, Jensen<br />

1998, p. 194) have found larger effects, but may not have adequately controlled<br />

for the children’s socioeconomic status.<br />

In any case, the host countries must now support dependent communities for<br />

an indefinite period. In a similar fashion, Hispanics (primarily mestizos) in the<br />

US score poorly on intelligence tests (on average), tend to have less massive<br />

brains than whites (Ralph Holloway, cited in Rushton and Ankney 2009, p. 709),<br />

and have a high rate of dependency. In Israel, Jews with significant European<br />

ancestry generally have higher test scores than Jews with exclusively North<br />

African/South Asian ancestry.<br />

IV. IMMIGRATION AND COOPERATION<br />

However, there is still a case to be made for a liberal policy with respect to<br />

<strong>immigration</strong>, just as there is a case for a liberal trade policy with respect to less<br />

developed countries (LDCs). With respect to trade policy, even if a less developed<br />

country did not have a productivity advantage in any industry, there could<br />

nevertheless be mutual gains from trade insofar as the LDC would have a<br />

comparative advantage in various sectors. A more developed country would then<br />

be advised to concentrate resources in its areas of comparative advantage and<br />

trade for the goods and services for which the LDC has the comparative edge.<br />

In a similar fashion, insofar as even lesser-skilled immigrants are able to<br />

perform work or start businesses in many areas, some native residents are freed<br />

up to work in areas of greater relative strength. Members of both groups can be<br />

made better off. Lejour and de Mooij (2005) estimated that Turkey’s accession<br />

to the European Union would produce net gains, with additional gains coming<br />

from the impact that accession could have on internal Turkish policies.<br />

The other side of the <strong>immigration</strong> argument involves not only concerns about<br />

the high dependency rates among such immigrant groups (e.g., Borjas 2001), but<br />

broader issues of social cooperation. The cooperation, or lack thereof, affects the<br />

performance of work teams in private, profit-seeking enterprises, affects the<br />

formation and operation of nonprofit entities, and also affects the operation and<br />

the very nature of political institutions. It may unfortunately be the case that mass<br />

– as opposed to selective – <strong>immigration</strong> has a negative impact in these areas.<br />

172 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

Insofar as the effects potentially involve private organizations, <strong>immigration</strong>’s<br />

impact can be internalized to a large extent. Managers can decide in a particular<br />

case if the benefits of employing immigrant workers exceed the costs. The impact<br />

on political institutions and the broader society is more worrisome in light of its<br />

pervasiveness. Parts of cities, whole cities, and possibly whole countries may<br />

reflect the relative presence or relative absence of cooperative efforts.<br />

Obstacles to social cooperation concern factors related to intelligence, impulsiveness,<br />

and ethnic diversity. As Garett Jones (2008) has found, in cases where<br />

the incentives to cooperate are ambiguous – as in so-called “prisoner’s dilemmas”<br />

– a certain threshold of intelligence may have to be crossed for cooperation<br />

to occur. The gains from cooperation may not always be clear to all. Thus,<br />

intelligent people may realize gains to cooperation that less intelligent people, or<br />

mixed groups of intelligent and less-intelligent people, may miss out on.<br />

Impulsiveness is relevant insofar as cooperation involves the passage of time<br />

and reciprocity. Perhaps I would be willing to help you now on the expectation<br />

that, later on, you would be willing to help me. But, to make the arrangement<br />

worthwhile, the present value of the help I expect to receive later on must equal<br />

or exceed the sacrifice that I would make for you. Present value, in turn, depends<br />

on my discount rate, and discount rates vary across groups of people. For<br />

example, if children are asked to postpone the receipt of a candy bar or a<br />

marshmallow on the understanding that they will receive a bigger one or a greater<br />

number later on, not all children respond in the same way (Mischel 1961, 1996).<br />

And impulsiveness seems to be related to intelligence (Dohmen et al. 2010).<br />

Robert Putnam (2007) has undertaken the most exhaustive study of the impact<br />

of ethnic diversity on cooperation and was quite chastened by his findings. He sat<br />

on them for more than five years before he finally published them. Putnam found<br />

resoundingly that, other things equal, the more ethnically diverse the community,<br />

the less that cooperation tends to take place. For example, Los Angeles was<br />

found to be a rather uncooperative place. Other things equal, people in ethnically<br />

diverse communities develop fewer friendships, participate less in community<br />

activities, watch more television, and are less happy. Bjørnskov (2003) concluded<br />

that high levels of life satisfaction in still-not-highly-diverse Scandinavia<br />

are more dependent on social capital than on affluence.<br />

William Hamilton (1964) articulated a genetic basis for altruism in terms of<br />

the likelihood of the altruism’s beneficiaries’ passing on copies of the genes of<br />

the acting person. However, his math initially suggested that genuine altruism<br />

would extend only to close relatives. According to his method, for example, you<br />

are only 1/32 related to a second cousin and only trivially related to randomly<br />

selected members of the general population.<br />

Hamilton (1975) later noted that inbreeding among members of an ethnic<br />

group could significantly lessen the genetic distance between oneself and a<br />

randomly selected member of the same ethnic group. Harpending (2002) calcu-<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 173


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

lated that a typical person is almost as genetically close to an average member of<br />

his own ethnic group vs. the rest of humanity as he is to a nephew vs. the rest of<br />

the ethnic group.<br />

Singer (2000, p. 44) remarked on the highly-cooperative aspects of Japanese<br />

society. In 2011, there was not a significant amount of looting in Japan even in<br />

the wake of a massive earthquake. In fact, 2.3 billion yen of lost cash was turned<br />

in, having been found in wallets and safes that had disappeared in the aftermath<br />

of the quake (Daily Mail, 17 August 2011). However, Singer made no mention of<br />

Japan’s ethnic homogeneity, its high average level of intelligence, or its lack of<br />

impulsiveness. Nor did he mention its paucity of <strong>immigration</strong>. Cesarini et al.<br />

(2008) found that a willingness to cooperate is, itself, significantly heritable.<br />

Last, and certainly not least, is the impact of <strong>immigration</strong> on political institutions.<br />

Preserving an impartial Rule of Law is difficult under the best of<br />

circumstances, but putting aside parochial interests for the sake of the benefits of<br />

political cooperation becomes more difficult in the presence of a very diverse<br />

population. Rindermann (2008) found that education and intelligence lend<br />

support for the Rule of Law, democracy, and political liberty, with the acquisition<br />

of education depending on underlying cognitive ability. Caplan and Miller<br />

(2010) reported that a pro-market orientation is better predicted by cognitive<br />

ability than educational level. Cousin marriages are doubly problematic for a<br />

classically liberal society; they not only depress IQ, but increase the intensity of<br />

nepotism in political affairs.<br />

IV. SUMMARY AND CONCLUDING REMARKS<br />

Recent literature in <strong>biology</strong> and related disciplines may ultimately have a profound<br />

impact on how we view the world. It is becoming more firmly established<br />

that all human traits have a genetic component. Less appreciated are findings that<br />

people’s shared environment is of comparatively little importance, at least for<br />

intelligence and standard personality characteristics. More esoteric features of<br />

the natural and social environment – somatic mutations, gene-environment interactions<br />

within peer groups – merit additional research.<br />

A propensity to cooperate has a genetic component and is positively related to<br />

intelligence and a lack of impulsiveness. What has been less obvious is the basis<br />

for cooperation among seemingly-unrelated members of an ethnic group. The<br />

extent of cooperation may depend on the degree of inbreeding within the group.<br />

Ethnic diversity, the presence of which is affected by <strong>immigration</strong> levels (as well<br />

as birth rates), appears to have negative consequences for cooperation.<br />

Intelligence and income are strongly influenced by genetic factors and are<br />

important not only for personal success (Gottfredson 2003), but in terms of not<br />

having to be supported by people outside of one’s family. Immigration is problematic<br />

in this context, too; low IQ immigrants increase the rate of dependency.<br />

174 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

Intelligence and (a lack of) impulsiveness are also important for the maintenance<br />

of functioning markets, the Rule of Law, and democratic institutions.<br />

Immigration offers gains from trade, but low intelligence tends to reduce support<br />

for markets and lessen social cooperation. Ethnic diversity has negative effects<br />

here as well insofar as it spawns favoritism.<br />

It is possible that a disposition toward low intelligence or impulsiveness can be<br />

remediated by certain programs in cost-effective ways. However, the American<br />

Head Start program, which offers enrichment initiatives on behalf of preschool<br />

children, has not been found to have any lasting effects on the intelligence of<br />

African-Americans (Currie and Thomas 1995). Oklahoma and Georgia guarantee<br />

preschool for all, but with no enduring impact on test scores. Scarr (1997)<br />

found no lasting effects of childcare programs on children’s personalities except<br />

in extreme cases. These outcomes are consistent with the thrust of the research<br />

in behavioral genetics.<br />

Heckman and his colleagues (Heckman et al. 2006) concluded their research<br />

without much enthusiasm about efforts to alter general intelligence, but much<br />

more hope about efforts to improve children’s “preference sets” – i.e., get<br />

children pointed in the right direction and limit bad behavior. Baumister et al<br />

(2011) concluded that preschool education efforts in the German-speaking world<br />

enhance the cognitive ability of children, but the magnitude of this impact<br />

decreases over time. They did not follow children all the way to adulthood, nor<br />

was there a clear impact on the children of immigrants. Moreover, preschool<br />

education appeared to worsen behavioral problems. In the end, it is a question of<br />

weighing risks and benefits. Mass <strong>immigration</strong> does have benefits, but also very<br />

large risks.<br />

REFERENCES<br />

Afzal, Md. and S.P. Sinha (1983). Consanguinity Effects on Intelligence Quotient and Neonatal<br />

Behaviors of nsari Muslim Children. Proceedings of the Indian National Science Academy. B49:<br />

407–411.<br />

Allocco, Dominic J., Qing Song, Gary H. Gibbons, Marco F. Ramoni and Isaac S. Kohane (2007).<br />

Geography and Genography: Prediction of Continental Origin Using Randomly Selected Single<br />

Nucleotide Polymorphisms. BMC Genomics. 8: 68.<br />

Ansari, N.A. and S.P. Sinha (1978). Survey on the Effects of Inbreeding in Two Populations of Bihar.<br />

Indian Journal of Medical Research. 68: 295–305.<br />

Austad, Stephen (2000). Varied Fates from Similar States. Science. 290: 944.<br />

Baumister, Antonia, Heiner Rindermann, Katharina Tatzl, and Elke Fuhrer (2011). Impact of Pre-K<br />

Education on Children’s Intelligence and Behavior (unpublished).<br />

Björklund, Anders, Markus Jäntti and Gary Solon (2005). Influences of Nature and Nurture on<br />

Earnings Variation: A Report on a Study of Various Sibling Types in Sweden, in: Samuel Bowles,<br />

Herbert Gintis, and Melissa Osborne Groves (eds.), Unequal Chances: Family Background and<br />

Economic Success. Princeton: Princeton University Press.<br />

Bjørnskov, Christian (2003). The Happy Few: Cross-Country Evidence on Social Capital and Life<br />

Satisfaction. Kyklos. 56: 3–16.<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 175


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

Borjas, George J. (2001). Heaven’s Door. Princeton: Princeton University Press.<br />

Bowles, Samuel and Herbert Gintis. (2002). The Inheritance of Inequality. Journal of Economic<br />

Perspectives. 16: 3–30.<br />

Caplan, Bryan and Stephen C. Miller (2010). Intelligence Makes People Think Like Economists:<br />

Evidence from the General Social Survey. Intelligence. 38: 636–647.<br />

Cavalli-Sforza, L.L., P. Menozzi and A. Piazza (1994). The History and Geography of Human Genes.<br />

Princeton: Princeton University Press.<br />

Cesarini, David, Christopher Dawes, James Fowler, Magnus Johanneson, Paul Lichenstein and Bjorn<br />

Wallace (2008). Heritability of Cooperative Behavior in the Trust Game. Proceedings of the<br />

National Academy of Sciences. 105: 3721–3726.<br />

Cesarini, David C. (2010). Essays on Genetic Variation and Economic Behavior. Ph.D. Dissertation.<br />

Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Supervised by David Laibson and Drazen Prelec.<br />

Clark, E.A. and J. Hanisee (1982). Intellectual and Adaptive Performance of Asian Children in<br />

Adoptive American Settings. Developmental Psychology. 18: 595–599.<br />

Cosmides, Leda and John Tooby (eds.) (1992). The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the<br />

Generation of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Currie, J. and D. Thomas (1995). Does Head Start Make a Difference? American Economic Review.<br />

85: 341–364.<br />

Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation<br />

of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: John Murray.<br />

DeBerry, Kimberly (1991). Modeling Ecological Competence in African American Transracial<br />

Adoptees. Ph.D. Dissertation. University of Virgina, Charlottesville. Supervised by Sandra Scarr.<br />

De Neve, Jan-Emmanuel, Nicholas A. Christakis, James H. Fowler and Bruno S. Frey (2011). Genes,<br />

Economics, and Happiness (unpublished).<br />

Dohmen, T., A. Falk, D. Huffman and U. Sunde (2010). Are Risk Aversion and Impatience Related<br />

to Cognitive Ability? American Economic Review. 100: 1238–1260.<br />

Finch, Caleb and Thomas Kirkwood (2000). Chance, Development and Aging. New York: Oxford<br />

University Press.<br />

Frydman, M. and R. Lynn (1989). The Intelligence of Korean Children Adopted in Belgium. Personality<br />

and Individual Differences. 10: 1323–1326.<br />

Gottfredson, Linda S. (2003). g, Jobs, and Life, in: Helmut Nyborg (ed.), The Scientific Study of<br />

General Intelligence. New York: Pergamon: 293–342.<br />

Hamilton, William (1964). The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour. Journal of Theoretical<br />

Biology. 7: 17–52.<br />

Hamilton, William (1975). Innate Social Aptitudes of Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics,<br />

in: R. Fox (ed.), Biosocial Anthropology. London: Malaby Press: 133–153.<br />

Harpending, Henry (2002). Kinship and Population Subdivision. Population and Environment 24:<br />

141–147.<br />

Harris, Judith Rich (1998). The Nurture Assumption: Why Children Turn Out the Way They Do. New<br />

York: Free Press.<br />

Hayek, F.A. (1967). The Legal and Political Philosophy of David Hume. In Studies in Philosophy,<br />

Politics, and Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.<br />

Heckman, James J., Jora Stixrud, and Sergio Urzua (2006). The Effects of Cognitive and Noncognitive<br />

Abilities on Labor Market Outcomes and Social Behavior. Journal of Labor Economics. 24:<br />

411–482.<br />

Hume, David (1739-40/2000). A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by David Norton and Mary<br />

Norton. New York: Oxford University Press.<br />

Hume, David (1779/1990). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. New York: Penguin Group.<br />

Jensen, Arthur (1969). How Much Can We Boost IQ and Scholastic Achievement? Harvard Educational<br />

Review. 39: 1–123.<br />

176 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.


BIOLOGY, IMMIGRATION, AND PUBLIC POLICY<br />

Jensen, Arthur (1980). Bias in Mental Testing. New York: Free Press.<br />

Jensen, Arthur (1998). The g Factor. Westport, CT: Praeger.<br />

Jones, Garett (2008). Are Smarter Groups More Cooperative? Evidence from Prisoner’s Dilemma<br />

Experiments, 1959–2003. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 68: 489–497.<br />

Jurgens, H.W., I.A. Aune and U. Pieper (1990). International Data on Anthropometry. Geneva:<br />

International Labor Office.<br />

Kagan, J., J. Reznick, and N. Snidman (1988). Biological Basis of Childhood Shyness. Science. 240:<br />

167–171.<br />

Lejour, Arjan M. and Ruud A. de Mooij (2005). Turkish Delight: Does Turkey’s Accession to the EU<br />

Bring Economic Benefits? Kyklos. 58: 87–120.<br />

Lynn, Richard and Gerald Meisenberg (2010). The Average IQ of Sub-Saharan Africans: Comments<br />

on Wicherts, Dolan, and Van der Maas. Intelligence. 38: 21–29.<br />

Maiti, S., K. Halagur, B.G. Kumar, C. Castellani, C.R. O’Reilly and S. Singh (2011). Ontogenetic De<br />

Novo Copy Number Variations (CNVs) as a Source of Genetic Individuality: Studies on Two<br />

Families with MZD Twins for Schizophrenia. PloS One. 6: e17125.<br />

Mischel, Walter (1961). Preference for Delayed Reinforcement and Social Responsibility. Journal of<br />

Abnormal and Social Psychology, 62: 1–7.<br />

Mischel, Walter (1996). From Good Intentions to Willpower, in: P.M. Gollwitzer and J.A. Bargh<br />

(eds.), The Psychology of Action. New York: Guilford Press.<br />

Nathawat, S.S. and P. Puri (1995). A Comparative Study of MZ and DZ Twins on Level 1 and Level<br />

11 Mental Abilities and Personality. Journal of the Indian Academy of Applied Psychology. 21:<br />

545–546.<br />

Nettle, Daniel (2011). Happiness: The Science behind Your Smile. New York: Oxford University<br />

Press.<br />

Nisbett, Richard (2005). Heredity, Environment, and Race Differences in IQ: A Commentary on<br />

Rushton and Jensen. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law. 11: 302–310.<br />

Nisbett, Richard (2009). Intelligence and How to Get It: Why Schools and Cultures Count. New York:<br />

Norton.<br />

Pal, S., R. Shyam and R. Singh (1997). Genetic Analysis of General Intelligence g: A Twin Study.<br />

Personality and Individual Differences. 22: 779–780.<br />

Pinker, Steven (2002). The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. New York: Penguin<br />

Group.<br />

Plomin, R., J.C. DeFries, G.E. McClearn and P. McGuffin (2008). Behavioral Genetics. New York:<br />

Worth Publishers.<br />

Price, A.L.; J. Butler, N. Patterson, C. Capelli, V.L. Pascali (2008). Discerning the Ancestry of<br />

European Americans in Genetic Association Studies. PLoS Genetics. 4: e236.<br />

Putnam, Robert (2007). E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-first Century.<br />

Scandinavian Political Studies. 30: 137–174.<br />

Rindermann, Heiner (2008). Relevance of Education and Intelligence for the Political Development<br />

of Nations: Democracy, Rule of Law and Political Liberty. Intelligence 36: 306–322.<br />

Rosenberg, N., J. Pritchard, J. Weber, H. Cann, K. Kidd, L. Zhivotovsky, and M. Feldman (2002).<br />

Genetic Structure of Human Populations. Science. 298: 2381–2385.<br />

Rowe, David (1994). The Limits of Family Influence: Genes, Experience and Behavior. New York:<br />

Guilford Press.<br />

Rushton, J. Philippe and C. Davison Ankney (2009). Whole Brain Size and General Mental Ability:<br />

A Review. International Journal of Neuroscience. 119: 691–731.<br />

Rushton, J. Philippe and Jensen, Arthur (2005). Thirty Years of Research on Black-White Differences<br />

in Cognitive Ability. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law. 11: 235–294.<br />

Scarr, Sandra (1997). Why Child Care Has Little Impact on Most Children’s Development. Current<br />

Directions in Psychological Science. 6, 143–148.<br />

© 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 177


GREGORY B. CHRISTAINSEN<br />

Scarr, Sandra (1998). On Arthur Jensen’s integrity. Intelligence. 26: 227–232.<br />

Schull, W.J. and J.V. Neel (1965). The Effects of Inbreeding on Japanese Children. New York: Harper<br />

and Row.<br />

Serre, D. and S. Paabo (2004). Evidence for Gradients of Human Genetic Diversity within and among<br />

Continents. Genome Research. 14: 1679–1685.<br />

Settle, Jaime, Christopher Dawes, Nicholas Christakis and James Fowler (2010). Friendships Moderate<br />

an Association Between a Dopamine Gene Variant and Political Ideology. The Journal of<br />

Politics. 72: 1189–1198.<br />

Singer, Peter (2000). A Darwinian Left: Politics, Evolution and Cooperation. New Haven: Yale<br />

University Press.<br />

Smith, Adam (1759/1976). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.<br />

Smith, C.L. and K.L. Beals (1990). Cultural Correlates with Cranial Capacity. American Anthropologist.<br />

92: 193–200.<br />

Tang, H., T. Quertermous, B. Rodriguez, S. Kardia, X. Zhu, A. Brown, J. Pankow, M. Province, S.<br />

Hunt, E. Boerwinkle, N. Schork, N. Risch (2005). Genetic Structure, Self-identified Race/<br />

Ethnicity and Confounding in Case-Control Association Studies. American Journal of Human<br />

Genetics. 76: 268–275.<br />

Turkheimer, Eric (2000). Three Laws of Behavior Genetics and What They Mean. Current Directions<br />

in Psychological Science. 9: 160–164.<br />

Turkheimer, Eric (2011). Still Missing. Research in Human Development. 8: 227–241.<br />

Turkheimer, Eric, A. Haley, M. Waldron, B. D’Onofrio, and I. Gottesman (2003). Socioeconomic<br />

Status Modifies Heritability of IQ in Young Children. Psychological Science. 14: 623–628.<br />

Weinberg, Richard, Sandra Scarr and Irwin Waldman (1992). The Minnesota Transracial Adoption<br />

Study: A Follow-Up of IQ Test Performance at Adolescence. Intelligence. 16: 117–135.<br />

Wicherts, J.M., C.V. Dolan and H.L.J. Van der Maas (2010a). A Systematic Literature Review of the<br />

Average IQ of Sub-Saharan Africans. Intelligence. 38: 1–20.<br />

Wicherts, J.M., C.V. Dolan and H.L.J. Van der Maas (2010b). The Dangers of Unsystematic Selection<br />

Methods and the Representativeness of 46 Samples of African Test-Takers. Intelligence. 38:<br />

30–37.<br />

Wilson, Edward (1975). Socio<strong>biology</strong>: A New Synthesis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.<br />

Winick, M., K.K. Meyer and R.C. Harris (1975). Malnutrition and Environmental Enrichment by<br />

Early Adoption. Science. 190: 1173–1175.<br />

SUMMARY<br />

This paper discusses recent scientific research that has shifted the terms of the debate about the respective<br />

roles of nature and nurture in shaping behavior. The research includes literature in the areas of <strong>biology</strong>,<br />

psychometrics, evolutionary psychology, and behavioral genetics. The paper then shows the relevance of this<br />

literature for ongoing concerns about mass <strong>immigration</strong> in developed countries. The literature has implications<br />

not only for the personal success of the immigrants, but rates of social dependency and the outlook for<br />

political and social cooperation in increasingly diverse societies. Efforts to remediate IQ deficits or behavioral<br />

problems in some immigrant groups are seen to be problematic.<br />

178 © 2012 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!