09.09.2014 Views

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ent Colour in Fridell Anter refers to a reference point or ‘helper concept’, as<br />

she says, to which perceived colour changes of surfaces are compared. She<br />

does, however, use the same method as Hård for determining inherent<br />

colours, <strong>and</strong> this is why she chose to use the same term. But unlike Hård,<br />

Fridell Anter makes no claims about the inherent colour representing any<br />

‘real’ colour in the meaning discussed in this article. (Fridell Anter 2000, pp<br />

59–64). Fridell Anter suggested already in her thesis that the term nominal<br />

colour would be more fitting as a description of the concept behind inherent<br />

colour, <strong>and</strong> the authors of this volume suggest that nominal colour should<br />

replace this term in all similar uses of the concept. (See Light <strong>and</strong> Colour, p.<br />

50 in this volume). The Dictionary gives nominal as “in name only; theoretical<br />

– – minimal in comparison with real worth or what is expected…” (Collins<br />

2003). It connotes face value, <strong>and</strong> as in the world of money <strong>and</strong> finance,<br />

nominal value can have a precise meaning without direct reference to anything<br />

real. This is exactly the relation of nominal colour to ‘real’ experienced<br />

colours.<br />

On a very fundamental level there are at least two modes of perceiving colour.<br />

One entails the relative, relational <strong>and</strong> variable nature of colour, how it changes<br />

<strong>and</strong> how the appearance of objects changes in relation to environmental<br />

factors <strong>and</strong> time. It helps to place objects <strong>and</strong> spatial features in relation to<br />

distance, time of day <strong>and</strong> season. This faculty is involved in our ability to<br />

enjoy <strong>and</strong> evaluate our relation to our surroundings, to atmosphere <strong>and</strong> the<br />

changes of natural conditions. The other level has to do with the material<br />

qualities of objects irrespective of these conditions <strong>and</strong> changes.<br />

As both Karin Fridell Anter <strong>and</strong> Monica Billger point out in their theses, we<br />

are able to change our mode of attention <strong>and</strong> thus extract several levels of<br />

perception from the same set of colour stimuli. (Fridell Anter 2000, pp. 36–<br />

38; Billger 1999, pp. 10–12). Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s concepts of the ‘reflective<br />

attitude’ <strong>and</strong> ‘living perception’, as discussed in his Phenomenology of<br />

Perception (Merleau-Ponty 2002) are fundamental to the work of both<br />

Fridell Anter <strong>and</strong> Billger. (See also Natural Experience <strong>and</strong> physical Abstractions,<br />

pp. 23–24 in this volume).<br />

A wall may be seen as ‘overlaid’, ‘covered’ or ‘coloured’ by shadows or colours<br />

reflected from nearby surfaces. For the purpose of separating <strong>and</strong> analyzing<br />

these layers or variations in perceived colour Monica Billger has introduced<br />

in her thesis Colour in Enclosed Space, the concept of identity colour. Billger<br />

writes:<br />

The perceived colour is analyzed on two levels of reflective attention, one<br />

that can be called holistic <strong>and</strong> one that is more detailed. With the former<br />

attitude to the room we perceive the identity colour, <strong>and</strong> with the latter<br />

the colour variations. Identity colour is defined as the main<br />

colour impression of surfaces or parts of a room that are perceived as<br />

97

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!