09.09.2014 Views

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

oth for perception of lightness (Gilchrist et al. 1999) <strong>and</strong> hue (Klarén <strong>and</strong><br />

Fridell Anter 2011).<br />

But even if we experience that an object has almost the same colour in a different<br />

light, we can at the same time perceive a slight tone of colour that reveals<br />

the character of the light. For nominally achromatic surfaces this effect<br />

is more obvious than for nominally chromatic surfaces. We experience that<br />

the surface is white but we feel at the same time that it is illuminated with a<br />

light of a special quality <strong>and</strong> intensity. This involves not only light coming<br />

directly from the light source, but also light reflected from surrounding surfaces.<br />

Depending on modes of attention, a nominally white wall lit by ‘warm’ sunlight<br />

can be seen (with a reflective attitude) as slightly yellowish or (with<br />

living perception) as the “proper” or “real” colour of the wall experienced<br />

beyond the perceived colour. As a suggestion one could call this colour constancy<br />

colour 26 (Fig. 1). (See also <strong>Lightness</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Brightness</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>Other</strong> <strong>Confusions</strong><br />

in this volume).<br />

According to Alva Noë, different kinds of visual appearances can be experienced<br />

simultaneously. Noë gives an example from shape perception: When a<br />

circular plate is held up at an angle, we are able to experience circularity in<br />

what we simultaneously perceive as an elliptical shape. In the same way, we<br />

can experience, say, a white constancy colour in a surface that we simultaneously<br />

perceive as having a hue caused by light. (Noë 2004, pp 131–132).<br />

26<br />

Ewald Hering’s concept memory colour (Gedächtnisfarbe) touches on this phenomena,<br />

but confines to expected colours in objects: “What the layman calls the real colour<br />

of an object is a colour of the object that has become fixed, as it were, in his memory; I<br />

should like to call it the memory colour of the object”. Hering (1920). Constancy colour<br />

refers to a natural perceptual ‘skill’; we make ‘hypotheses’ of what the colour is from<br />

perceived visual information in a given context. Merleau-Ponty says that the “real”<br />

colour persists “not as a seen or thought-of quality, but through a non-sensory presence.”<br />

(Merleau-Ponty 2002, p 356). See also Klarén <strong>and</strong> Fridell Anter, 2011.<br />

24

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!