09.09.2014 Views

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

Lightness and Brightness and Other Confusions

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

limited to what is required for human life <strong>and</strong> survival. Gibson describes our<br />

senses as perceptual systems: instead of five separate senses he prefers to talk<br />

about five modes of external attention. (Gibson 1966, pp 166-167) MANFRED<br />

ZIMMERMANN 25 estimates the potential capacity of the human visual system at<br />

10 million bit/second (which would mean the ability to discriminate 10 millions<br />

colours). In information theory the concept bit is used as a measure of<br />

quantity of information; it indicates a smallest perceivable unit in the information<br />

flow. It does not describe content of information only perceivable<br />

quantity of information. The total information capacity of all senses together<br />

is supposed to be about 11,2 million bit/second <strong>and</strong> the information capacity<br />

for our conscious experience of the world around is not more than 40<br />

bit/second. (Zimmermann 1989, p 172). Principles for selection <strong>and</strong> reduction<br />

of information correspond to human existential needs. Every creature<br />

has its own special access to the world. William James compares the work of<br />

our senses with the work of sculptors:<br />

<strong>Other</strong> sculptors, other statues from the same stone! <strong>Other</strong> minds, other<br />

worlds from the same monotonous <strong>and</strong> inexpressive chaos! My world is<br />

but one in a million alike embedded, alike real to those who may abstract<br />

them. How different must be the worlds in the consciousness of an ant,<br />

cuttlefish or a crab! (James 1890, pp 288–289).<br />

Reducing information <strong>and</strong> selecting what in a given context has to be attended<br />

to requires some kind of attention structure. An attention structure –<br />

conscious or unconscious – directs attention to certain aspects of a phenomenon.<br />

In science such a perceptual principle is usually called a theoretical<br />

perspective. (Eneroth 1994, p 24). Acquiring knowledge is to develop attention<br />

structures. (Gardner 1994, p 24).<br />

Merleau-Ponty discusses how we experience the surrounding world in different<br />

ways depending on situation. He makes a distinction between two modes<br />

of attention: the reflective attitude <strong>and</strong> living perception. (Merleau-Ponty<br />

2002, p 355). This distinction is significant to our perception of colour.<br />

Strictly speaking it is not possible to find out how we perceive colour in living<br />

perception, since every question that directs our attention towards a colour<br />

gives, of necessity, rise to a reflective attitude.<br />

When perceiving colours, our vision does not recognize the absolute intensity<br />

or the absolute spectral distribution of radiation that reaches our retina. Instead<br />

distinctions <strong>and</strong> relations are registered. Our visual system is developed<br />

for a continuous spectrum of light <strong>and</strong> gradual changes between different<br />

illuminations, <strong>and</strong> under these circumstances we perceive colours as more or<br />

less constant. Our visual sense adapts to current light conditions: what we<br />

perceive as white in a given illumination functions as a perceptual “anchor”<br />

25<br />

German neurophysiologist, 1933–<br />

23

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!