17.06.2014 Views

printer-friendly version (PDF) - Reflex Sympathetic Dystrophy ...

printer-friendly version (PDF) - Reflex Sympathetic Dystrophy ...

printer-friendly version (PDF) - Reflex Sympathetic Dystrophy ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

and experienced in three time frames (past, present, and future). 3<br />

Consider some examples: guilt and shame are varieties of disgust<br />

in differing social contexts. When disgust is directed outward, it<br />

may take the form of disdain; when combined with anger, it<br />

may turn to recrimination and vengeance. The experience of primary<br />

emotions is modified by the virtually infinite variety of<br />

states of mind, particularly considering that the associations of<br />

long-term memory are unique representations of objects and<br />

events. One potential criticism of this taxonomy is that it is<br />

reductive or deterministic. I refute such criticism by calculating 4<br />

the unlimited variety of the precursors of suffering, values, and<br />

behavior. The present discussion is about suffering; but I cannot<br />

ignore the fact that creativity cannot be predicted by a reduction<br />

to finite elements. Our appetites for curiosity and mastery will<br />

sometimes motivate us to think and do outrageous and wonderful<br />

things. When considering the variety of experiences that<br />

result in suffering, most observers recall the opening of Tolstoy’s<br />

Anna Karenina: “All happy families resemble one another; every<br />

unhappy family is unhappy in its own fashion.”<br />

PREMISE 2<br />

When pain evokes fear and grief, the effect on the<br />

maps in the brain’s body-sensing regions is the<br />

same as for fear and grief alone.<br />

I PROPOSE THAT CHRONIC PAIN, OR SEVERE ACUTE PAIN,<br />

evokes fear and grief and that the pain-evoked fear and grief<br />

have the same effect on the maps in the body-sensing regions of<br />

the brain as do fear and grief alone. When pain evokes fear or<br />

grief by threatening the existential domains of the individual, as<br />

in Cassell’s formulation, the suffering that results is qualitatively<br />

no different from any other form of suffering. The differences<br />

in the varieties of the experience of suffering, I propose, arise<br />

from its context—what Cassell referred to as “the meaning” of<br />

suffering. The current technology of neuroscience does not have<br />

the resolution to address, no less to validate, this theoretical<br />

postulate. I have no doubt that it will.<br />

PREMISE 3<br />

Suffering is not an emotion, but is an “emotionally<br />

competent stimulus” capable of evoking emotions.<br />

FEAR AND GRIEF, THE PROPOSED ANTECEDENTS OF SUFFERING,<br />

ARE EMOTIONS. I propose that suffering is not. Emotions evoke<br />

action, somatic and visceral motor activity, and aversive behavior<br />

in the face of fear and disgust. I propose that if fear and<br />

grief do not evoke suffering, they do motivate corrective or<br />

aversive action in the face of danger or loss. 5<br />

I am persuaded to think that suffering does not evoke aversive<br />

or corrective behavior by itself. Suffering is involutional,<br />

resulting in withdrawal, stasis, and inaction. Suffering is interior<br />

and isolating. Suffering is experienced as distress, misery, agony,<br />

anguish, torment, wretchedness, despair, hopelessness, excruciation,<br />

and woe. When we are lonely, we seek companionship.<br />

When we “suffer” the death of a loved one, we shut ourselves<br />

off and rely on the cultural rituals of the funeral, wake, or<br />

receiving of friends and family to provide resilience and connection<br />

to others. We recognize and admire the resilience of those<br />

who console others around them, even though everyone has<br />

experienced the same loss or, in the case of danger, the same<br />

jeopardy and fear.<br />

I have portrayed suffering as leading to inaction and stasis.<br />

I propose that with the evolution of suffering, the emotions of<br />

disgust and anger took on the role of decreasing the intensity of<br />

suffering by motivating action. Such actions often appear to be<br />

maladaptive when they are resentful or hostile. The ancient role<br />

of disgust was to protect against injury from contamination by<br />

waste, decay, and contagion. To experience disgust at the perception<br />

of an abstract stimulus or of a benign object is a recent<br />

response. Rage once served for aggressive display and dominance<br />

in reproductive and survival conflicts. Now, exploitation<br />

and dominance, as expressed in revenge, are more common. 6<br />

Although Elisabeth Kubler-Ross’s work has been criticized after<br />

her death, her well-known monograph on loss and grief<br />

demonstrates how suffering evokes disgust and rage (11).<br />

3 Time frames include the “past” from long-term memory, both declarative<br />

and non-declarative; the “present” from short-term memory (the answer to<br />

Emily Webb’s question [from Thornton Wilder’s Our Town] is: no, we do<br />

not experience life as we live it, we experience it after it happens); and the<br />

“future” as representations of anticipated objects and events (5).<br />

4 The calculation of possible states of mind multiplies six primary emotions,<br />

10 drive states, three time frames, and an arbitrary ordinal scale of intensity<br />

for the contribution of each of the other three dimensions. Even if many of<br />

the cells of such a matrix are empty, the product is a number beyond<br />

comprehension.<br />

5 For example, if I am afraid of a bull moose, I wait until he leaves and do<br />

not cross the valley to fish where he is feeding. But I do not suffer for it,<br />

unless he is feeding at the edge of the best pool in the river.<br />

6 We easily intuit the ancient survival value of fear, surprise, disgust, and anger;<br />

however, we might consider the role of disgust and anger in meliorating suffering<br />

when we recall the media frenzy that accompanies any human tragedy.<br />

Accusation, scapegoating, recrimination, and revenge follow hard upon fear<br />

and grief. A good example is the Sago Mine explosion in January 2006. After<br />

days of intense rescue efforts, a rumor spread that 1 miner was dead and that<br />

12 survived. The opposite was true and the truth was not transmitted to the<br />

community for 3 hours. The disgust and rage that followed were severe,<br />

arguably out of proportion to the offence. For many, rage and disgust were<br />

easily turned against the media for exploiting the suffering of the lost miners’<br />

families. Perhaps we cleave to the suffering of others to validate our own<br />

resilience, but our reactions only reveal our vulnerability.<br />

T H E PA I N P R A C T I T I O N E R | V O L U M E 16 , N U M B E R 1 | 77

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!