05.06.2014 Views

Ethical Issues of Reproductive Technologies: Designer Babies, Sex ...

Ethical Issues of Reproductive Technologies: Designer Babies, Sex ...

Ethical Issues of Reproductive Technologies: Designer Babies, Sex ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Ethical</strong> <strong>Issues</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong> <strong>Technologies</strong>:<br />

<strong>Designer</strong> <strong>Babies</strong>, <strong>Sex</strong> Selection and Donor <strong>Babies</strong><br />

Rachael Caffrey, 5 th Year Medical Student, Queen’s University<br />

Belfast<br />

Address for Correspondence: School <strong>of</strong> Medicine, Dentistry and Biomedical<br />

Sciences, Queen’s University Belfast, 71-73 University Road, Belfast BT7 1NN. Email:<br />

rcaffrey01@qub.ac.uk<br />

The technology <strong>of</strong> assisted reproduction has progressed rapidly in recent<br />

years, enabling infertile couples to have the children they long for.<br />

However, with these advances come numerous ethical dilemmas .This<br />

essay looks at three important areas <strong>of</strong> reproductive technologies;<br />

‘designer babies’, sex selection and ‘donor babies’, which all raise their<br />

own ethical issues; ethical arguments for and against each are<br />

discussed. ‘<strong>Designer</strong> babies’ describes the use <strong>of</strong> several technologies,<br />

particularly Pre-implantation Genetic Diagnosis, which give parents an<br />

element <strong>of</strong> control over their <strong>of</strong>fspring’s characteristics. The dilemma is<br />

whether it is ethical to design babies by selecting an embryo in this way.<br />

The main argument for these techniques is that they can help prevent<br />

certain genetic diseases. The main argument against is that <strong>of</strong> the<br />

‘slippery slope’ towards designing babies for physical or psychological<br />

traits. <strong>Sex</strong> selection for medical reasons is largely accepted as ethical,<br />

but when carried out for non-medical reasons, is met with objections.<br />

The case for permitting sex selection for non-medical reasons is that it<br />

serves the desires <strong>of</strong> couples who have strong preferences regarding the<br />

gender <strong>of</strong> their <strong>of</strong>fspring. However, this raises worries regarding gender<br />

discrimination and inappropriate use <strong>of</strong> medical resources. ‘Donor<br />

babies’ refers to the use <strong>of</strong> donated gametes by infertile couples. There<br />

is much debate on the acceptability <strong>of</strong> gamete donation in circumstances<br />

where infertility is due to psychosocial factors e.g. in lesbian couples or<br />

post-menopausal women. A major argument against oocyte donation to<br />

older women is that there is a ‘natural’ limit to reproductive capacity and<br />

87


to transcend this would be ‘unnatural’, balanced against an argument <strong>of</strong><br />

‘reproductive freedom’. New reproductive technologies are helping<br />

infertile couples have the children they yearn for, and additionally, are<br />

saving lives and preventing disease. However, there are clearly many<br />

ethical issues and contrasting viewpoints to consider with regards to<br />

these technologies, and it must be remembered, that regulation is<br />

important to avoid the use <strong>of</strong> these powerful technologies for<br />

inappropriate purposes. J NI Ethics Forum 2008, 5: 87-96<br />

Introduction<br />

The technology <strong>of</strong> assisted reproduction has progressed at a rapid pace<br />

in recent years, enabling many otherwise infertile couples to have the<br />

children they long for. [1],[2] Conception, pregnancy and childbirth, formerly<br />

an indivisible process, can now be considered as separable stages <strong>of</strong><br />

reproduction. [3] With these advances however, come numerous ethical<br />

dilemmas. In this essay I will look at three areas <strong>of</strong> reproductive<br />

technologies; ‘designer babies’, sex selection and ‘donor babies’, and<br />

discuss the ethical arguments for and against each one.<br />

<strong>Designer</strong> <strong>Babies</strong><br />

‘<strong>Designer</strong> babies’ is a term that has become part <strong>of</strong> everyday language,<br />

though it was a term initiated by journalists rather than scientists. [4],[5] It<br />

describes the use <strong>of</strong> several reproductive technologies, all with one thing<br />

in common; they give parents an element <strong>of</strong> control over the<br />

characteristics <strong>of</strong> their <strong>of</strong>fspring. [5] The technique at the centre <strong>of</strong> the<br />

debate about designer babies is Pre-implantation Genetic Diagnosis<br />

(PGD), which brings together two technologies: in vitro fertilisation (IVF)<br />

and genetic testing. [4] The dilemma is whether it is ethical to design<br />

babies by selecting an embryo in this way. [5] The main argument for<br />

these techniques is that they can help prevent certain genetic diseases<br />

e.g. single gene disorders such as cystic fibrosis, and chromosomal<br />

88


abnormalities such as Down’s Syndrome. [6],[7] In this way they can save<br />

children from debilitation and suffering and reduce the financial and<br />

emotional strain on the parents. [6] Furthermore, Verlinsky [5] tells us these<br />

techniques are used only by those requiring the help <strong>of</strong> a fertility clinic to<br />

have children, and therefore argues that since these people have<br />

invested so much time, energy and money in their effort to have a baby,<br />

shouldn’t they be able to ensure they have a healthy child? Another point<br />

to be noted is that many naturally conceived embryos are rejected from<br />

the womb due to disordered growth, and so it can be argued by<br />

screening embryos we are simply doing what nature would normally<br />

do. [5],[6]<br />

However, one argument against using PGD to prevent disease is that <strong>of</strong><br />

the ‘slippery slope’ argument. The worry is that we could get carried<br />

away ‘correcting’ babies. [6] The Human Fertilisation and Embryo<br />

Authority (HFEA), who regulate the use <strong>of</strong> PGD, state that it should only<br />

be used for detecting “very serious, life threatening conditions” and not<br />

for minor abnormalities, but ‘serious’ is difficult to define in this context. [7]<br />

Where do we draw the line? Furthermore, from a disability equality<br />

perspective, every life is <strong>of</strong> value and our diversity as a species has<br />

innate value. Therefore, to discriminate against an embryo, which could<br />

go on to become a person with a disability or disorder would be<br />

considered wrong. [8] Moreover, once on this slippery slope what is to stop<br />

us choosing babies for their physical or psychological traits? [5] The path<br />

from therapy to enhancement is a continuum rather than a clear and<br />

obvious dividing line. [9] It is argued this could be the first step towards<br />

allowing parents to choose other characteristics <strong>of</strong> their baby such as<br />

eye or hair colour. [10] There is always the looming shadow <strong>of</strong> eugenics<br />

and ‘improving’ the gene pool by the elimination <strong>of</strong> ‘undesirables’, in this<br />

case, undesirable embryos. [5]<br />

On the other hand, opposing this argument is the fact that merely<br />

asserting that this is the first step towards allowing parents to choose<br />

89


other characteristics is inadequate. [10] Through the use <strong>of</strong> careful<br />

regulations PGD could be used for some reasons and not for others,<br />

thereby avoiding a ‘slide down the slope’. [10] One form <strong>of</strong> ‘designing<br />

babies’ I have not yet considered is that <strong>of</strong> using PGD in conjunction with<br />

tissue typing to select an embryo for implantation that will go on to<br />

become a ‘saviour sibling’; a brother or sister capable <strong>of</strong> donating lifesaving<br />

tissue to an existing child. [10] An argument particular to this<br />

technique is that saviour siblings would be treated as mere commodities,<br />

not wanted for their own sake, but for some other purpose. [10] In the<br />

words <strong>of</strong> Kant’s famous dictum, “Never use people as means but always<br />

treat them as a end”. [7] However, in reality many children are born for a<br />

purpose: as a companion to a sibling, to ‘pass on the family name’, or<br />

bring happiness to the parents. Therefore, providing parents love their<br />

child, it is argued there is no harm in that child benefiting another. [7]<br />

Having discussed these issues I feel that using PGD is something that<br />

should not be done without careful consideration on behalf <strong>of</strong> the parents<br />

involved. Choosing which embryo to implant and which to discard is not<br />

an easy choice, nor should it ever be. [11] Nonetheless, in my opinion any<br />

technology that can reduce pain and suffering is one to be considered,<br />

be that by preventing a life <strong>of</strong> suffering or by easing the anguish <strong>of</strong> an<br />

existing child. By the implementation <strong>of</strong> regulations I believe this<br />

technology could be used for good, and any trivialisation <strong>of</strong> the technique<br />

to ‘design babies’ for cosmetic traits could be prevented.<br />

<strong>Sex</strong> Selection<br />

Another issue to consider is that <strong>of</strong> sex selection. The two main<br />

techniques used for this are, again, PGD or alternatively, sperm sorting.<br />

The HFEA’s recommendation is that sex selection should only be<br />

available “in cases in which there is a clear and overriding medical<br />

justification”, referring to the avoidance <strong>of</strong> sex-linked genetic conditions<br />

such as Tay-Sachs. [12] The British Medical Association is concurrent with<br />

this. [13] The main focus <strong>of</strong> ethical objections to this technique are linked<br />

90


with sex selection for non-medical reasons, with there being less debate<br />

over the ethical validity <strong>of</strong> sex selection when its aim is to prevent the<br />

transmission <strong>of</strong> sex-linked disease. [14] Taking this into account, and as I<br />

have already discussed the use <strong>of</strong> PGD to avoid genetic diseases, we<br />

are presented with questions such as: if a couple have two sons and<br />

desire a daughter, should they be allowed to employ this technology? [15]<br />

The case for permitting sex selection for non-medical reasons is that it<br />

serves the desires <strong>of</strong> couples who have strong preferences regarding the<br />

gender <strong>of</strong> their <strong>of</strong>fspring, some <strong>of</strong> whom feel so strongly they may resort<br />

to abortion or choose not to procreate unless the gender <strong>of</strong> their future<br />

baby can be determined. [16] Then again, one can question whether<br />

desire alone justifies acceptance <strong>of</strong> their preference, especially when it is<br />

a preference which is <strong>of</strong>ten self-imposed. [16] One suggested argument<br />

against the use <strong>of</strong> this technology in this way is that it constitutes an<br />

inappropriate use <strong>of</strong> medical resources. However, according to the<br />

American Society for <strong>Reproductive</strong> Medicine (ASRM) preconception<br />

gender selection (i.e. sperm separation followed by artificial<br />

insemination) is unlikely to drain substantial resources from the medical<br />

system. [15] Another ethical issue surrounding sex selection is that <strong>of</strong><br />

gender discrimination and, furthermore, that <strong>of</strong>fspring produced will be<br />

expected to act in certain gender specific ways. [15] Some argue that<br />

although the motivations for desiring a child <strong>of</strong> a particular sex vary, other<br />

than in the case <strong>of</strong> preventing a sex-linked disease, there are no nonsexist<br />

reasons for pre-selecting sex. [15] Furthermore, there is the worry<br />

that sex-selection will lead to adverse social consequences due to an<br />

unbalanced sex ratio. It is likely though that only a small percentage <strong>of</strong><br />

the population would request sex selection, therefore the impact on the<br />

sex ratio would be minimal. [1] Alternatively, if sex selection were to<br />

become very popular, laws could be introduced requiring providers to<br />

select both genders in equal numbers thereby avoiding a shift in the sex<br />

ratio. Although it could then be argued that the institution <strong>of</strong> laws in this<br />

way would result in a decrease in procreative liberty and defy the<br />

purpose <strong>of</strong> the procedure! [15] An alternative argument against sex<br />

91


selection is based on the parental virtue <strong>of</strong> acceptance. When an<br />

individual becomes a parent society expects him or her to maintain that<br />

role regardless <strong>of</strong> the specific characteristics <strong>of</strong> their child. [12]<br />

McDougall [12] proposes that it is an intrinsic feature <strong>of</strong> a child that his or<br />

her characteristics will be unpredictable. Even if their entire genetic<br />

make-up were known, the complexity <strong>of</strong> the child’s environment makes<br />

their characteristics, to some extent, unpredictable. Therefore, it follows,<br />

since a child’s characteristics are unpredictable, acceptance <strong>of</strong> those<br />

characteristics is a parental virtue. [12] A child’s sex would fall within the<br />

scope <strong>of</strong> this parental virtue <strong>of</strong> acceptance and on this basis sex<br />

selection would be regarded as wrong. McDougall [12] does acknowledge<br />

however, that acceptance is only one in a range <strong>of</strong> parental values and<br />

others, such as concern for a child’s opportunities, can conflict with this.<br />

Whilst I recognize that sex selection would satisfy the desires <strong>of</strong> couples<br />

to ‘balance’ their families, I feel that other than in exceptional<br />

circumstances, sex selection should only be available for medical<br />

reasons. I believe concern with gender, be that male or female, is not<br />

something to be encouraged. [16] Gender is not a medical condition, but<br />

rather, a characteristic to be accepted by parents. Therefore, I see no<br />

compelling argument to justify the use <strong>of</strong> this technology for social<br />

reasons.<br />

Donor <strong>Babies</strong><br />

A final area to look at is that <strong>of</strong> ‘donor babies’ or the use <strong>of</strong> donated<br />

gametes. For infertile couples who lack sperm or oocytes this may be<br />

the only solution to enable the accomplishment <strong>of</strong> a parental <strong>of</strong>fspring. [17]<br />

Gamete donation was introduced to address various medical problems,<br />

and is indicated where there is no possibility <strong>of</strong> pregnancy without the<br />

technique, or when other treatments have a minimal chance <strong>of</strong><br />

success. [1],[17] Such circumstances include the use <strong>of</strong> donated oocytes<br />

where a woman has suffered premature ovarian failure or because<br />

treatment such as chemotherapy has rendered her infertile. [18] It can<br />

92


also be used to evade transmission <strong>of</strong> a genetic disease to the<br />

<strong>of</strong>fspring. [17] These uses all fall into the realm <strong>of</strong> medical treatment and<br />

pose no unique ethical problems. Major ethical issues arise however,<br />

when the practise is used for non-medical reasons. There is much<br />

debate on the acceptability <strong>of</strong> gamete donation in circumstances where<br />

the infertility is due to psychosocial factors such as, in, lesbian couples or<br />

post-menopausal women. [19],[17] It is this use for older, post-menopausal<br />

women that is <strong>of</strong>ten debated and the area that I will focus on. Oocyte<br />

donation has been used for infertile women over the age <strong>of</strong> forty when<br />

IVF with their own oocytes has been unsuccessful and there is no<br />

explanation other than age for their infertility. The use <strong>of</strong> younger<br />

women’s donated eggs proved highly successful and paved the way for<br />

their use in postmenopausal women. [1] In this way a woman’s<br />

reproductive age has been artificially extended. [19] A major argument<br />

against oocyte donation to older women is that there is a ‘natural’ limit to<br />

reproductive capacity and to transcend this would be ‘unnatural’. [19]<br />

Furthermore, parenting can be a physically demanding, energyconsuming<br />

task and it is thought that older parents may be unable to<br />

meet the needs <strong>of</strong> a growing child. [1],[19] However, it can be pointed out<br />

that it is not unusual for children to be raised by grandparents and it is<br />

therefore put that older people are capable <strong>of</strong> fulfilling parental roles. [1]<br />

Arguments in favour are based on gender equality and reproductive<br />

freedom. It is argued that since older men may father children naturally,<br />

denying woman an alternative to reproduction at the equivalent age is<br />

sexist, especially since women generally live longer than men. [19],[20]<br />

However, there are real concerns regarding the health <strong>of</strong> the recipients.<br />

In a postmenopausal pregnancy the woman faces increased risk <strong>of</strong><br />

complications such as hypertension, diabetes, and preterm labour. [19]<br />

There are also concerns surrounding the interests <strong>of</strong> the child who, some<br />

feel, may be adversely affected psychologically and socially, and may<br />

resent having a mother old enough to be their grandmother. [19] In<br />

addition, there is the concern that there is increased likelihood that one<br />

or both parents will die before the child is raised. [1] Nonetheless, it<br />

93


should be noted that individuals with life-limiting illnesses are not<br />

prohibited from reproduction because <strong>of</strong> their shortened life<br />

expectancy. [19] In addition, Strong [1] makes the point that if a couple<br />

were to have a child at the age <strong>of</strong> 60, on average the life expectancy for<br />

the woman would be another 23 years, and for the man, another 19<br />

years. Thus, on average the child would be a young adult before its<br />

parents died. Having considered the above arguments I feel we cannot<br />

say absolutely that oocyte donation to older post-menopausal women is<br />

‘right’ or ‘wrong’. Whilst it can be argued that infertility should remain the<br />

natural characteristic <strong>of</strong> the menopause, I do not consider this reason<br />

persuasive enough to deem the practice unethical in every case. [19]<br />

There are many factors we have to take into account, such as the<br />

woman’s age, health, and personal circumstances. The specifics <strong>of</strong> each<br />

case should be carefully considered by the prospective parents and<br />

physician involved before choosing oocyte donation. [19]<br />

Conclusion<br />

There are clearly many ethical issues to consider with regards to<br />

reproductive technologies and many viewpoints to be looked at, all <strong>of</strong><br />

which cannot be included in the constraints <strong>of</strong> this essay. New<br />

reproductive technologies are helping infertile couples have the children<br />

they yearn for, and additionally, are saving lives and preventing disease.<br />

The good it will bring about is the moral motive for intervening in the<br />

natural lottery <strong>of</strong> life. [21] It must be remembered however, that<br />

regulations must be set in place to avoid the use <strong>of</strong> these powerful<br />

technologies for inappropriate purposes.<br />

Rachael undertook the 2 nd Year Student Selected Component ‘<strong>Reproductive</strong><br />

Technology” co-ordinated by Pr<strong>of</strong>essor Sheena Lewis, School <strong>of</strong> Medicine, Dentistry<br />

and Biomedical Sciences, QUB in spring 2006 and was joint runner-up in the Forum’s<br />

2006 Essay Competition.<br />

94


References<br />

[1] Strong C. Ethics in <strong>Reproductive</strong> and Perinatal Medicine. Yale<br />

University Press, New Haven, 1997<br />

[2] Haase J. Gamete and Embryo Donation: The Need For Regulation.<br />

Adoption Council <strong>of</strong> Canada.<br />

http://www.adoption.ca/viewpoints/gamete.htm (Accessed 9 April<br />

2006)<br />

[3] Van Dyck J. Manufacturing <strong>Babies</strong> and Public Consent: Debating the<br />

New <strong>Reproductive</strong> <strong>Technologies</strong>. Macmillen, Basingstoke, 1995<br />

[4] Lee E. Introduction. In: Institute <strong>of</strong> Ideas. <strong>Designer</strong> <strong>Babies</strong>: Where<br />

should we draw the line? Hodder and Stroughton, London, 2002<br />

[5] Verlinsky Y. Designing <strong>Babies</strong>: what the future holds. Ethics, Law<br />

and Moral Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong> Biomedicine 2005; 1(1): 24-26<br />

[6] Centre for the Study <strong>of</strong> Technology and Society. Biotechnology<br />

Special Focus – <strong>Designer</strong> <strong>Babies</strong>.<br />

http://www.tecsoc.org/biotech/focusbabies.htm (Accessed 23<br />

February 2006)<br />

[7] Boyle R, Savulescu J. Ethics <strong>of</strong> using preimplantation genetic<br />

diagnosis to select a stem call donor for an existing person. British<br />

Medical Journal 2001; 323(7323): 1240-1243<br />

[8] Fletcher A. Making it Better? Disability and Genetic Choice. In:<br />

Institute <strong>of</strong> Ideas. <strong>Designer</strong> <strong>Babies</strong>: Where should we draw the line?<br />

Hodder and Stroughton, London, 2002<br />

[9] English V, Sommerville. Drawing the Line: The Need for Balance. In:<br />

Institute <strong>of</strong> Ideas. <strong>Designer</strong> <strong>Babies</strong>: Where should we draw the line?<br />

Hodder and Stroughton, London, 2002<br />

[10] Sheldon S, Wilkinson S. Should selecting saviour siblings be<br />

banned? Journal <strong>of</strong> Medical Ethics 2004; 30: 533-637<br />

[11] Stock G. Germinal choice technology and the human future. Ethics,<br />

Law and Moral Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong> Biomedicine 2005; 1(1):<br />

27-35<br />

95


[12] McDougall R. Acting parentally: an argument against sex selection.<br />

Journal <strong>of</strong> Medical Ethics 2005; 31: 601-605<br />

[13] Doyal L, McLean S. Choosing children: intergenerational justice?<br />

Ethics, Law and Moral Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong> Biomedicine<br />

2005; 1(1): 24-26<br />

[14] The Ethics Committee <strong>of</strong> the American Society <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong><br />

Medicine. <strong>Sex</strong> selection and preimplantation genetic diagnosis.<br />

Fertility and Sterility 2004; 82(1 Suppl): 245-248<br />

[15] Cloonan K, Crumley C, Kiymaz S. <strong>Sex</strong> Selection: <strong>Ethical</strong> <strong>Issues</strong>.<br />

Developmental Biology Online, 2003<br />

http://7e.devbio.com/article.php?id=177 (Accessed 25 March 2006)<br />

[16] The Ethics Committee <strong>of</strong> the American Society for <strong>Reproductive</strong><br />

Medicine. Preconception gender selection for non-medical reasons.<br />

Fertility and Sterility 2004; 82(1 Suppl): 232-235<br />

[17] ESHRE Task force on Ethics and Law. Gamete and embryo<br />

donation. Human Reproduction 2002; 17(5): 1407-1408<br />

[18] The National Gamete Donation Trust (NGDT). Egg donation. NGDT,<br />

2002. http://www.ngdt.co.uk (Accessed 8 April 2006)<br />

[19] The Ethics Committee <strong>of</strong> the American Society <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong><br />

Medicine. Oocyte donation to postmenopausal women. Fertility and<br />

Sterility 2004; 82(1 Suppl): 254-255<br />

[20] Sauer M, Paulson R, Lobo R. Pregnancy in women 50 or more years<br />

<strong>of</strong> age: outcomes <strong>of</strong> 22 consecutively established pregnancies for<br />

oocyte donation. Fertility and Sterility 1995; 64: 111-115<br />

[21] Harris J. <strong>Reproductive</strong> liberty, disease and disability. Ethics, Law and<br />

Moral Philosophy <strong>of</strong> <strong>Reproductive</strong> Biomedicine 2005; 1(1): 13-16<br />

96

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!