05.06.2014 Views

Catherwood, J. - Queen's University Belfast

Catherwood, J. - Queen's University Belfast

Catherwood, J. - Queen's University Belfast

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Tearing Down the Slippery Slope<br />

John <strong>Catherwood</strong>, Lecturer in Applied Ethics<br />

Address for Correspondence: School of Politics, International Studies and Philosophy, <strong>Queen's</strong> <strong>University</strong><br />

<strong>Belfast</strong>, 21 <strong>University</strong> Square, <strong>Belfast</strong> BT7 1PA, Northern Ireland. Email: j.catherwood@qub.ac.uk<br />

The logic of ‘Slippery slope’ arguments and their related variants ‘the thin end of the wedge’<br />

‘opening the floodgates’ ‘great oaks from little acorns’, etc., has been widely criticised. Yet<br />

these ‘slope-type’ arguments remain popular in the messy business of real-life moral discourse<br />

even at the highest levels of social policy making. [1] I believe that a hitherto unregarded<br />

property of these arguments plays an import role: it is the imagery used that makes these<br />

arguments attractive and persuasive and we need to analyse the image if we are to understand<br />

the appeal of these arguments and successfully debunk them. J NI Ethics Forum 2006, 3: 42-51<br />

Each image has particular properties which require exploration, but there are two aspects that<br />

all slope-type arguments share: they appeal to caution and to cynicism. When faced with<br />

novelty which may have dire moral implications people look on the new activity with caution<br />

and perhaps fear. ‘Better safe than sorry’ is the maxim invoked; slope-type arguments sow the<br />

seed of doubt. Caution and experience tell us to avoid any possibility of permitting evil. Even if<br />

only one person became a heroin junkie after trying legalised cannabis, or one doctor slid<br />

towards killing patients against their will, one is one too many.<br />

These arguments also play on a cynical (if often justified) view of our fellow man. Descent to<br />

the bottom of the slippery slope is inevitable: temptation, like the pull of gravity, is constant and<br />

unavoidably drags us down. The claim that no abuse will follow from relaxing a strict moral<br />

principle is always dubitable. We might have enough moral strength to avoid the moral decline<br />

or horrible result that slope-type arguments predict, but we know that others are not so rational,<br />

strong-willed or morally aware. These aspects of the arguments are especially pernicious<br />

because most people have problems with the proper assessment of risk and probability. The<br />

most miniscule risk can become a powerful influence if the possible outcome is emotionally<br />

charged.<br />

Although all slope-type arguments play on the emotional responses outlined above, the<br />

different images that each invokes have their own peculiar emotional and psychological force.<br />

The most powerful of these is the Slippery Slope itself.<br />

No matter what is at the bottom of it, the prospect of facing a slippery slope is enough to raise<br />

tension in even an experienced mountaineer. The image has an emotive effect that is drummed<br />

into us from childhood: “Be careful that you don’t slip!” is every parent’s cry to adventurous<br />

toddlers. Slipping leads to falling, to pain and embarrassment. Even if a fall is avoided, anyone<br />

who has ever slipped unintentionally will know the discomfort of that experience. To slip is to<br />

loose control and be in danger of harm. Of course we are not morally responsible for actions<br />

over which we have no control, but we would be morally irresponsible to put ourselves<br />

knowingly in a position where control will be lost and harm caused. It is not merely fear of<br />

falling that the image evokes; it is fear of the possibility of falling.<br />

The slippery slope image is also an attack on our self-image, as well as a threat to our personal<br />

safety. We are in the centre of the picture. It is us who will slide to the moral low. Some forms<br />

suggest we will become corrupt and no longer recognise our acts as evil. All imply that we will


e unable to rise again to the moral heights. It suggests that we are weak, corruptible, a notion<br />

reinforced by the related image of our lives being ‘a moral journey’ on which we could become<br />

‘lost’.<br />

Negative associations are not the sole root of power for the Slippery slope image. Unlike the<br />

images of floodgates and wedges, which are almost entirely fuelled by implied threats, the<br />

Slippery Slope image also draws on flattery and self-delusion. People like to think of<br />

themselves as good, and there is a flattering appeal in the suggestion that we are at the top of<br />

a slope. It implies that we are better than those who are foolish or morally corrupt enough to<br />

have hit the bottom. We are already on ‘the moral high ground’, a common positive image<br />

which also implies the existence of a moral low ground, and presumably slopes to connect<br />

them. It is in many people’s nature to take pleasure in looking down on those below.<br />

However if we further unpack the slippery slope image it becomes incoherent. A slope (slippery<br />

or not) is a three dimensional shape, which must be set in a ‘moral landscape’. This image is<br />

supported by many others: the moral high ground, mountains to climb, paths to tread (some<br />

broad and paved with good intentions, others straight and narrow), sloughs of despond, moral<br />

mazes and bridges up ahead. These metaphors and analogies seem meaningful since for most<br />

of us our primary sense is vision and it is natural for us to talk in spatial and visual terms even<br />

when describing abstract, non-spatial things. So we talk of ‘moral positions’ as if they were<br />

spatial positions and understand the notion of a person being close to our position, or of our<br />

aims being higher than others. The image of sliding down the slope suggests that we are<br />

capable of moral movement within the landscape and that we can become better or worse<br />

people, make moral progress and perhaps climb ever higher through moral struggle. All of<br />

these ideas are controversial.<br />

While moral change is undeniable, progress is not. Progress implies goals and purpose and<br />

improvement measured against standards. Individuals and societies change their opinions but<br />

whether or not the changes are for the better is open to debate. ‘Progress’ will be defined in<br />

terms of whatever moral principles we hold at the time, and any changes in our moral position<br />

may also change our notion of what it is to progress. Some predictions of deleterious moral<br />

change have come true, but we look upon those changes as progress, given our new moral<br />

position. [2] Perhaps we are now corrupt, but equally we may have slipped upwards, or slipped<br />

along so that we are now neither better nor worse. Perhaps we did not slide at all; we walked a<br />

deliberately chosen path, applying a little moral grit when necessary.<br />

It is also difficult to fully cash out the idea of moral movement. When we change our opinions it<br />

is natural to use the imagery of having ‘shifted’ positions, or being ‘moved’ by an argument.<br />

However there is no physical movement and there is no object that transfers from one place to<br />

another in normal space time. If there is moral movement then it can only happen in moral<br />

space, which itself needs further examination.<br />

Whatever moral space is like, ‘moral movement’ is still mysterious, for there is no moral<br />

corollary of Newton’s Laws of Motion. There is no mass to my thoughts to be accelerated in<br />

law-like way by (moral?) force. We may talk of our thoughts having ‘momentum’, but we are not<br />

doomed to continue to change our position at a constant rate unless stopped, nor to have an<br />

equal and opposite reaction to moral forces brought to bear on us. Physical movement occurs<br />

through space and over time – we move from one place to another by moving to adjacent<br />

places in sequence until the final destination is reached. Moral ideas, even ideas about the<br />

same or similar issues held by the same person at one or different times, do not require<br />

contiguity, (they may be radically different or even reversed, and bear no relation to each<br />

other). A change in moral position can be instantaneous without passing through a series of


other positions in moral space, even if the new position is far from the old. In a moment’s<br />

thought I can be instantly at the bottom of the slope, without having to slide down it. Or I may<br />

leap to the top, avoiding the slippery surface altogether.<br />

We also have to consider how many positions in moral space one person can hold at any one<br />

time. We speak of ‘having a position on this issue’, which suggests we could have other<br />

positions on other issues. However to make sense of the image of an individual being located<br />

in moral space it seems strange to think of them as having more than one position. Of course<br />

there could be more than one moral space: I have a position in moral space related to drug<br />

legalisation, a different space for abortion sees me in a different position, etc, but this is also<br />

counter intuitive. If we are to be able to make anything coherent of this image of a slippery<br />

slope lying before us on the path of life then we have to imagine one person on one path in one<br />

landscape. The image requires that at any time we only have one position, representing a<br />

summation of all our moral ideals and opinions.<br />

In moral space many individuals may occupy the same position, like angels on the point of a<br />

pin. What happens if all of these people take different decisions and move away from the<br />

shared position, each deciding about a different issue, and each making their choice in the face<br />

of claims that a slippery slope awaits them? The landscape now imagined must consist of<br />

multiple slopes all centred on the high ground of the shared position. At the same time there<br />

may be movements that can be made that do not lead on to a slippery slope, or which lead up<br />

or merely along. So we must imagine a point in our landscape with a large (infinite?) number of<br />

possible paths intersecting at all angles, on which potentially infinite numbers of individuals can<br />

stand together. Now consider that every other point in the landscape is similarly surrounded by<br />

a similar (infinite?) set of paths of every type and direction, since each point in moral space<br />

represents a possible position from which one may move any distance in any direction if a new<br />

decision is taken. We soon lose any comprehensible image of a single landscape, or the idea<br />

of a path. Even if we reduce the image to its simplest, so that we stand on firm ground at the<br />

top of a hill, we are still at a loss to make sense of what supports the surface upon which we<br />

are supposed to step. What is the moral rock beneath our feet?<br />

Perhaps the moral landscape could be seen as a snapshot of our current position and the<br />

moral choices available to us. We could view the moral landscape as a model, or a map, of the<br />

moral reality for each individual. This interpretation emphasises the personal nature of the<br />

moral journey. However in this personalised landscape one position may simultaneously be at<br />

the top of many supposed slopes (slippery or not) and at the bottom of many others, and<br />

anywhere in between. Perhaps it is just a lack of imagination on my part, but I think that even<br />

M.C. Escher would be unable to draw this image.<br />

Moral space would have a different and confusing topography for each person, and since each<br />

individual may change their ideas over time the map/landscape would change accordingly.<br />

Such change could be rapid, extreme, and unpredictable. Moreover each individual may also<br />

rearrange the scenery by altering which ideas they think are close to each other and which are<br />

separated. We might be able to agree that some particular position is morally similar in many<br />

respects and on the same level as another, but that does not mean that the two should be side<br />

by side. There are no common frameworks to suggest how the landscape should be organised.<br />

Indeed we could imagine a moral landscape that was made up of near random distributions of<br />

heights and depths [3] with no visual similarity to any real world geography.


Organising principles might be developed if we knew what the x and y co-ordinates of each<br />

point represented (height, the z axis is clearly moral worthiness). We can imagine a one<br />

dimensional representation of a moral position easily enough – a simple line with ‘good’ at one<br />

end and ‘evil’ at the other. We can place ourselves and others on this line, perhaps using a<br />

summing technique to determine how good or evil we are over all. We could regard movement<br />

towards good as moral progress. We could also extend this to two dimensions, perhaps plotting<br />

our position over time, with goodness on one axis and time on the other. Here we can make<br />

sense of the slope image if we see a downward plot as our goodness falls from a highpoint.<br />

However the difficulty in climbing back up the slope is supposedly because it is slippery, and<br />

there is some force akin to gravity that drives us down, not because it is impossible to travel<br />

backwards in time. If we wish to keep the analogy with a conventional landscape which can be<br />

traversed in any direction, then time must be the fourth dimension, and flows only one way.<br />

There do not seem to be any good candidates for what the other two axes could represent.<br />

Talk of a landscape without some understanding of the substrate of which it is built or the<br />

dimensional system by which it can be measured or described is not just metaphorical, or even<br />

allegorical. This image is not using language normally used to refer to one type of object or<br />

experience to refer to a different, but in some way similar or related, object or experience. This<br />

is not a simplifying analogy that informs and improves our understanding: we are not even<br />

using the image in a symbolic way. Direction, position, movement and extension (along with<br />

attributes of extended objects such as shape, texture or colour) are all impossible to<br />

understand without the context of understandable dimensions. It sounds like meaningful<br />

English, but on reflection it is no more meaningful than “Colourless green ideas sleep furiously”<br />

Any terms (such as ‘slope’) that rely on an understanding of these things are meaningless. The<br />

consequences for those who wish to use a Slippery Slope argument are plain: without a<br />

comprehensible shared notion of a moral landscape then the whole notion of a moral slope,<br />

slippery or otherwise, is misconceived. It obscures and misrepresents the issue we want to<br />

discuss. Since such a notion is not comprehensible, and the landscape is not shared, the use<br />

of a slippery slope argument is at best empty, at worst a flagrant attempt to influence by<br />

deception and emotional manipulation.<br />

The excuse that it is ‘just an image’, or even that it is a useful image, is not good enough. It is<br />

useful only because it seems meaningful, and because it is manipulative. If it is just an image,<br />

then why not use another image, one that is not manipulative or deceitful, one that is<br />

meaningful, and does not carry the sense of quiet, waiting, inevitable menace that the slippery<br />

slope suggests? Indeed it might be a useful test of any slippery slope argument to reword it as<br />

a slope-type argument with a different image<br />

Few acorns grow into mighty oaks. They are driven by forces of nature, and grow<br />

independently of human desires, but the process is not inevitable, and can be interrupted. We<br />

cut down or uproot even well established trees that are growing in the wrong place. It lacks the<br />

menace of the slope image, which may be why it is not as popular in general discourse.<br />

If we talk of ‘the thin end of the wedge’ we must also conjure the image of the wedge as being<br />

something that has to be placed, and has to be driven. We may wonder who is the person<br />

wielding the sledgehammer to drive the wedge home, and why are they doing it? Perhaps the<br />

person driving the wedge can be questioned or stopped and their strength or determination<br />

may fail. At least they are a human agent, morally responsible and culpable, not a morally<br />

neutral or inevitable force of nature. This image at least gives us something that we can fight<br />

against. We might also wonder what the wedge is being driven between, or into. In a culturally<br />

diverse society such as ours it is not plausible to suggest that morality is a smooth and solid


ock, homogenous and offering no natural splits or faults. While wedge drivers might exploit<br />

these splits, they ma be doing society a favour in exposing the weaknesses that are already<br />

present.<br />

Floodgates are a thing of which relatively few people in most modern urban cultures will have<br />

much experience, and so it lacks the immediate and personal impact of the slippery slope. The<br />

image of a flood also lacks the subtle notion of progression that the gentle but unstoppable and<br />

ever accelerating slide down a slope suggests. It is implausible in many cases because it is<br />

overly dramatic. If one stands before the floodgates one is soaked, swept away and maybe<br />

drowned within moments of their opening: unless it is obvious that an immediate progression<br />

will be made directly to ‘the horrible result’ this image is unconvincing. Again, a flood may pass<br />

and gates can be closed, so this image is not one of inevitability or permanent change. It is also<br />

notable that while a flood may leave terrible damage, the evil is an external one – those who<br />

speak of floodgates may be warning us against foolhardy haste which might lead us into a<br />

situation that we do not like but they are not suggesting that we will become irrevocably bad<br />

people.<br />

My favourite image to substitute is that of ‘letting the camel’s nose under the flap of the tent.’ It<br />

lacks seriousness. No doubt it is a serious thing to have a camel in your tent, and for those<br />

desert nomads who coined the ancient proverb it was a real danger, but in our modern lives it<br />

lacks the emotional impact that the Slope argument can deliver. It is more likely to raise a smile<br />

than to produce grave nods of agreement. It also has an old fashioned ring to it, sounding like<br />

the sort of thing a retired military man who once served in the Raj might say in his club. We<br />

would understand that this is the sort of person who would be typically a natural conservative<br />

(perhaps not in tune with the times). If the argument still seems credible, despite the humour of<br />

the image, I think it must be worth considering seriously, but any lasting credibility is to be<br />

found in the unpacked version, not the clichéd image by itself. It is notable also that the camel’s<br />

nose argument lacks the impersonal inevitability that sliding on a slippery slope suggests.<br />

Camels are wilful and curious, and not known to be forward thinking or concerned for the<br />

welfare of human beings: the same is not necessarily true of the principles, actions or actors<br />

against whom the slope argument is deployed. Camels can be driven back, or at least out of<br />

the tent, so we are not fated to have to share our life with them forever after. This is in sharp<br />

contrast to the image of slopes that are so slippery that our slide is irreversible, and which<br />

presumably cannot be climbed once the bottom has been reached.<br />

Of course arguments using images of acorns, wedges, floodgates or camels may also fail for<br />

logical reasons: but they are at least not covertly emotive, and they do not rely on a<br />

manipulative and misleading image. It is time for us to tear down the image of the slope, and<br />

expose its undeserved reputation, for if we acquiesce to it we are surely letting the nose of a<br />

camel of nonsense under the tent flap of rational debate.<br />

John <strong>Catherwood</strong> was one of the speakers at the Annual Conference held in March 2005 focusing on<br />

the Ethics of Stem Cell Research.<br />

References<br />

[1]. Jonas, H, 1974 Against the stream: comments on the definition and redefinition of death. In<br />

Philosophical essays - from ancient creed to technological man, 132-140. Prentice Hall.<br />

[2]. e.g. we now take organs from brain dead donors, and think it right to do so, despite Hans<br />

Jonas warnings in “Against the stream: comments on the definition and redefinition of death.”<br />

Philosophical essays - from ancient creed to technological man, 132-140, Prentice Hall, 1974.


[3]. Like a SETI@Home screensaver graphic

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!