30.10.2012 Views

Zeit und Geschichte Time and History - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein ...

Zeit und Geschichte Time and History - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein ...

Zeit und Geschichte Time and History - Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

means of conventions <strong>and</strong> designating it by a single name.<br />

At this first step of concept formation, the relation of<br />

concepts to experiences remains a close one: our definitions<br />

are tied to qualitative experiences <strong>and</strong> identifying<br />

an object designated by a concretely defined concept<br />

implies having recourse to specific sensory experiences.<br />

The second step then consists in devising purely<br />

conceptual definitions. Concepts are defined solely by<br />

means of other concepts. As a consequence, the structure<br />

of knowledge consists in purely conceptual relations <strong>and</strong> is<br />

insofar freed from qualitative experience: it has a status of<br />

its own, essentially distinct from intuition. This idea of a<br />

breach between the formal <strong>and</strong> the experiential, meaning<br />

that the first doesn’t enter in the determination of the<br />

second, is also to be fo<strong>und</strong> in Einstein’s writings, as we<br />

have already seen. Thus both Schlick <strong>and</strong> Einstein agree<br />

that the conceptual system of knowledge has a specific<br />

status insofar as it is formal. This is a constant idea in<br />

Schlick’s thinking, which remains primordial during his<br />

Viennese period: Einstein’s later critics against Schlick’s<br />

thinking having become too positivistic should be<br />

tempered by this fact.<br />

The question of the determination of the system of<br />

knowledge <strong>and</strong> the one of its constitution should however<br />

be distinguished here. If Schlick <strong>and</strong> Einstein agree on its<br />

specific formal character, they disagree regarding the way<br />

we arrive at it <strong>and</strong> its relation to sensory data. We have<br />

outlined that Einstein sees the f<strong>und</strong>amental concepts of a<br />

theory as pure theoretical constructions, <strong>and</strong> that for him<br />

the question of the relation between experience <strong>and</strong> the<br />

theoretical system of science arises only after the latter<br />

has been fully developed. For Schlick on the contrary the<br />

purely formal system of knowledge is not something we<br />

begin with: it is rather the result of an evolution from a<br />

concretely defined system of concepts <strong>and</strong> it presupposes<br />

this former state. To be more precise the more advanced<br />

state of knowledge corresponds to theoretical physics,<br />

where physical magnitudes are conceptually defined without<br />

any recourse to qualitative experience (cf. Schlick<br />

1925 as well as Schlick 1932).<br />

Moreover Schlick maintains that even if the scientist<br />

seeks to define concepts by eliminating qualitative<br />

experience from his definitions, he nonetheless has in<br />

mind the idea of preserving the link between the formally<br />

determined system of science <strong>and</strong> experience. Theory,<br />

even if formal, is not developed at the purely abstract level<br />

of mathematics but at the level of theoretical physics,<br />

meaning that the physical concepts are always defined so<br />

as to designate objects in nature. Now it is a specific kind<br />

of experience which warrants that the concepts belonging<br />

to the system of knowledge actually designate real objects,<br />

it is namely the observation of spatio-temporal<br />

coincidences. Verifiable statements which predict the<br />

occurrence of measurable events must indeed be<br />

derivable from the formal definitions of physical concepts if<br />

they are to designate real objects. Every measurement<br />

finally ends up in the observation of the coincidence of two<br />

points: one on the measured body, the other on the<br />

measuring rod. Thus point-coincidences alone can warrant<br />

the link between the formal system of concepts <strong>and</strong> the<br />

real objects.<br />

It must be noticed that the observed coincidences<br />

have nothing in common with the qualitative experiences<br />

delivered by one particular sense. Observation of<br />

coincidences exemplifies a kind of experience which<br />

retains nothing of the qualitative <strong>and</strong> subjective<br />

characteristics of ordinary sensory experience as defined<br />

by Schlick. This explains that the recourse to this kind of<br />

42<br />

What is Physically Real? Schlick vs. Einstein - Delphine Chapuis-Schmitz<br />

experience doesn’t threaten the objectivity of knowledge<br />

nor its specific status towards intuition.<br />

The difference between Schlick <strong>and</strong> Einstein’s<br />

conception of the status of physical concepts can be further<br />

exemplified by the way each of them conceive of the pointcoincidence<br />

concept. As Einstein himself explains (see<br />

Einstein 1963 for instance) the defining of points of the<br />

space-time manifold as coincidences of world-lines is the<br />

result of a conceptual inquiry. Formulating the general<br />

covariant equations which form the general theory of<br />

relativity implied to redefine the concept of point in the<br />

space-time manifold so as to be able to individuate<br />

univocally the points of this manifold. In the special relativity,<br />

a point of the manifold is determined by his coordinates in a<br />

specific system of coordination. But <strong>und</strong>er the general<br />

relativistic postulate, the system of coordination itself is not<br />

invariant <strong>und</strong>er the class of general transformations: the<br />

determination of a point of the manifold in terms of its<br />

coordinates in a particular system is then not sufficient<br />

anymore to individuate it univocally. These formal<br />

considerations finally led Einstein to redefine the point of the<br />

manifold as the coincidence of two world lines. Only such a<br />

definition permits an invariant determination of a point <strong>und</strong>er<br />

any general transformation. It is furthermore devised by<br />

purely conceptual means <strong>and</strong> without being primarily guided<br />

by the requirement of a possible experiential interpretation: it<br />

therefore designate specifically physical objects.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong> Schlick takes the idea of observed<br />

coincidences as a f<strong>und</strong>amental one. After explaining in 1922<br />

that space <strong>and</strong> time are not themselves objects of<br />

measurement but rather a schema we can set up <strong>and</strong> use to<br />

order physical objects, he locates the requirement of<br />

preserving the coincidences that we observe in every<br />

measurement at the very beginning of our building of the<br />

spatio-temporal schema in physics (see Schlick 1922, <strong>and</strong><br />

also Schlick 1925, § 31). This doesn’t prevent him from<br />

recognizing rightly the specificity of the physical definition of<br />

point-coincidences in terms of coincidences of world lines.<br />

But the physical objects thus defined are not different from<br />

what is observed when measuring: it is the same objects<br />

which are conceptually defined in physics <strong>and</strong> grasped<br />

through observation. Coincidences thus st<strong>and</strong> at the<br />

interface between the physical (conceptual) <strong>and</strong> the<br />

psychological (intuitive) apprehension of reality.<br />

The identification of the physically defined pointcoincidences<br />

<strong>and</strong> the coincidences apprehended by<br />

observation exemplifies a f<strong>und</strong>amental idea of Schlick’s<br />

epistemology, namely that the way we relate to reality<br />

doesn’t interfere in what reality is. Knowing by means of<br />

concepts <strong>and</strong> experiencing through intuition are two ways of<br />

relating to the same reality (see Schlick 1932 for a clear<br />

statement of this idea). Against Einstein, Schlick makes a<br />

clear distinction between reality itself <strong>and</strong> our knowledge of it<br />

by means of concepts.<br />

Moreover, if the epistemological distinction between<br />

conceptually defined objects <strong>and</strong> the objects of sensory<br />

experience doesn’t lead Schlick, as opposed to Einstein, to<br />

distinguish between two kinds of reality, it’s finally thanks to<br />

his particular use of the coincidence concept which, lying at<br />

the interface between the physical <strong>and</strong> the psychological,<br />

warrants that both refer to the same reality. Coincidences<br />

are absolutely necessary to bridge the gap between the two<br />

kinds of access to reality that Schlick identifies. This doesn’t<br />

mean that for him our knowledge of reality is entirely<br />

determined by real facts, since conventions also have a role<br />

to play in the formation of scientific systems; but this means<br />

that they do not play a constitutive role in the einsteinian<br />

sense of the word.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!