26.03.2014 Views

The Role of Techne in the Authenticity-Inauthenticity Distinction

The Role of Techne in the Authenticity-Inauthenticity Distinction

The Role of Techne in the Authenticity-Inauthenticity Distinction

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

KRITIKE VOLUME ONE NUMBER TWO (DECEMBER 2007) 82-96<br />

<br />

Article<br />

<strong>The</strong> <strong>Role</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>Techne</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

Au<strong>the</strong>nticity-Inau<strong>the</strong>nticity Dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

Krist<strong>in</strong>a Lebedeva<br />

I<br />

n this paper I propose to do <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g: I will discuss <strong>the</strong> notions <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>tentionality and self-understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> as developed <strong>in</strong><br />

Heidegger’s Basic Problems <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology. In do<strong>in</strong>g so, I will try to show<br />

<strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrelation <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s always be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tentionally directed towards<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g and its self-<strong>in</strong>terpretation. As we will see, <strong>the</strong> everyday world has,<br />

for Heidegger, a character <strong>of</strong> “equipmental contexture.” This means that<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> returns to itself from out <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs, equipment, tools, or—quite<br />

differently—<strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> art. In a word, Dase<strong>in</strong> is mirrored back toward itself<br />

from <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs made, from <strong>the</strong> products <strong>of</strong> techne. 1 From this will follow <strong>the</strong><br />

important dist<strong>in</strong>ction between au<strong>the</strong>nticity and <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity. <strong>The</strong>re is a sense<br />

<strong>in</strong> which <strong>the</strong> follow<strong>in</strong>g pair<strong>in</strong>gs could be discerned: tools or pieces <strong>of</strong><br />

equipment l<strong>in</strong>k up with <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity, while <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> art l<strong>in</strong>ks up with<br />

au<strong>the</strong>nticity. I will say more on <strong>the</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> tools a bit later <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> essay.<br />

Both k<strong>in</strong>ds <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs are th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong>y are entrenched <strong>in</strong> techne. <strong>The</strong><br />

common root seems almost <strong>in</strong>explicable <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> light <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> vast difference<br />

between tools and <strong>the</strong> artwork. Moreover, both Dase<strong>in</strong> and techne seem to have<br />

ano<strong>the</strong>r equally enigmatic common root: that <strong>of</strong> temporality. Temporality is<br />

<strong>the</strong> essential bond between Dase<strong>in</strong> and <strong>the</strong> double sense <strong>of</strong> techne, which<br />

suggests <strong>the</strong> double-sidedness <strong>of</strong> temporality itself. It is precisely this doublesidedness<br />

that I would like to have as <strong>the</strong> backdrop to my discussion as a<br />

whole. F<strong>in</strong>ally, I will turn to a few pages <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time and<br />

Bernard Stiegler’s book Technics and Time I <strong>in</strong> order to complicate this notion <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> two senses <strong>of</strong> temporality, <strong>the</strong> owned and disowned, orig<strong>in</strong>ary and<br />

everyday, and its relation to work and techne. <strong>The</strong> overarch<strong>in</strong>g question here<br />

will be: Can <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between au<strong>the</strong>nticity and <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity be<br />

susta<strong>in</strong>ed?<br />

By way <strong>of</strong> stage-sett<strong>in</strong>g, it is important to say a few words about <strong>the</strong><br />

overarch<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong>me <strong>of</strong> Section Fifteen <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Basic Problems, entitled “<strong>The</strong><br />

fundamental problem <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> multiplicity <strong>of</strong> ways <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unity <strong>of</strong><br />

1 However, we should not forget that Dase<strong>in</strong> can also come back to itself from o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong>. As Heidegger puts it, “Not only is Be<strong>in</strong>g towards O<strong>the</strong>rs an autonomous, irreducible<br />

relationship <strong>of</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g: this relationship, as Be<strong>in</strong>g-with, is one which, with Dase<strong>in</strong>’s Be<strong>in</strong>g, already<br />

is.” On ano<strong>the</strong>r occasion, Heidegger describes be<strong>in</strong>g-with as “thraldom,” which suggests a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> captivity and <strong>the</strong> subsequent release from it. Mart<strong>in</strong> Heidegger, Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time (San<br />

Francisco: Harper San Francisco, 1962), 125-163.<br />

© 2007 Krist<strong>in</strong>a Lebedeva<br />

http://www.kritike.org/journal/issue_2/lebedeva_december2007.pdf<br />

ISSN 1908-7330


K. LEBEDEVA 83<br />

<strong>the</strong> concept <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> general.” 2 Heidegger po<strong>in</strong>ts out <strong>the</strong> somewhat<br />

contradictory character <strong>of</strong> modern ontology by ask<strong>in</strong>g: If <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g subject (res cogitans) is radically different from <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

(res extensa), <strong>the</strong>n is it possible to say that <strong>the</strong>re is such a th<strong>in</strong>g as be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

general? Heidegger’s concern here can be understood as follows: on <strong>the</strong> one<br />

hand, he is be<strong>in</strong>g critical <strong>of</strong> modern ontology <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it understands <strong>the</strong><br />

be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> both res cogitans and res extensa as present-at-hand, which means that<br />

both have fundamentally <strong>the</strong> same way <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g; on <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, he asks<br />

how it is possible to draw such a rigid dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g subject<br />

and o<strong>the</strong>r be<strong>in</strong>gs and yet endorse a unitary concept <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g. If <strong>the</strong> subject is<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed so different from o<strong>the</strong>r entities, <strong>the</strong>n it must have a different mode <strong>of</strong><br />

be<strong>in</strong>g. Thus, <strong>the</strong> radicalization <strong>of</strong> this very dist<strong>in</strong>ction between <strong>the</strong> different<br />

modes <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g is called for.<br />

In order to widen this gap between <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subject and <strong>the</strong><br />

be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r be<strong>in</strong>gs, one needs to work out a more radical conception <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

subject, which is to say that one needs to ask what Dase<strong>in</strong> or human existence 3<br />

means. This is <strong>in</strong> fact what Heidegger proceeds to do <strong>in</strong> Section A by giv<strong>in</strong>g us<br />

<strong>the</strong> “<strong>in</strong>itial preview <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> existential constitution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>.” 4 In giv<strong>in</strong>g this<br />

preview, Heidegger exhibits “<strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> that be<strong>in</strong>g to whose be<strong>in</strong>g (existence)<br />

an understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g belongs and to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> which all <strong>the</strong> problems <strong>of</strong><br />

ontology generally return.” 5 <strong>The</strong> question follow<strong>in</strong>g out from this statement is: how<br />

does Dase<strong>in</strong> understand itself? Heidegger <strong>the</strong>n asserts that Dase<strong>in</strong> is ontically 6<br />

nearest to itself because it is itself <strong>in</strong> each <strong>in</strong>stance and yet ontologically<br />

fur<strong>the</strong>st. 7 What this important statement refers to is <strong>the</strong> difficulty <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

access to itself. Although we certa<strong>in</strong>ly do not mistake ourselves for somebody<br />

else <strong>in</strong> our everyday commerce with <strong>the</strong> world, <strong>the</strong> “da” <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> rema<strong>in</strong>s<br />

most hidden. Heidegger <strong>the</strong>n says that “<strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s comportments have an<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentional character” and that “on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> this <strong>in</strong>tentionality <strong>the</strong> subject<br />

already stands <strong>in</strong> relation to th<strong>in</strong>gs that it itself is not.” 8 One could say <strong>the</strong>n that<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>in</strong>tentionality is relational dialectic with its world.<br />

Yet this should not lead us to believe that Dase<strong>in</strong> is simply a subject<br />

because it is always characterized by <strong>in</strong>tentionality, which means that perceiv<strong>in</strong>g<br />

is always <strong>the</strong> perception <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g, th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g is always th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> someth<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

That is, every act <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> is always a relat<strong>in</strong>g to someth<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong> this sense<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no <strong>in</strong>teriority <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> that underlies all relations. Relat<strong>in</strong>g belongs to<br />

2 Mart<strong>in</strong> Heidegger, <strong>The</strong> Basic Problems <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton: Indiana University<br />

Press, 1988).<br />

3 <strong>The</strong> German “da” (<strong>the</strong>re) and “se<strong>in</strong>” (be<strong>in</strong>g) literally mean “be<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>the</strong>re.”<br />

4 Ibid., 154.<br />

5 Ibid.<br />

6 <strong>The</strong> terms “ontic” and “ontological” describe two ways <strong>of</strong> discuss<strong>in</strong>g Dase<strong>in</strong>’s be<strong>in</strong>g:<br />

<strong>the</strong> one <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> formal ontological structures and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> concrete,<br />

factical way <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g at any given moment. <strong>The</strong> ontic way <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g is always articulated by <strong>the</strong><br />

formal ontological structures.<br />

7 Ibid., 155.<br />

8 Ibid.


84 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

<strong>the</strong> very ontological constitution <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> subjective self. 9 Dase<strong>in</strong> always exists <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r be<strong>in</strong>gs and cannot <strong>the</strong>refore be isolated from <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Heidegger fur<strong>the</strong>r articulates precisely this po<strong>in</strong>t by say<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong><br />

everyday determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> as an ego is <strong>in</strong> and through this relational<br />

comportment or <strong>in</strong>tentionality. 10 This is not to be conflated with <strong>the</strong> idea that<br />

relational acts simply radiate from <strong>the</strong> self, that it is <strong>the</strong> given self who <strong>in</strong>itiates<br />

<strong>the</strong>se acts. <strong>The</strong> given ego is not <strong>the</strong> bearer <strong>of</strong> its own <strong>in</strong>tentional acts because<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is no given ego as such. It seems that Dase<strong>in</strong> does not underlie all its<br />

relational acts but ra<strong>the</strong>r happens <strong>in</strong> and through <strong>the</strong>m. Human existence<br />

“stands out” (<strong>the</strong> literal sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> verb “to exist”) by way <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional acts<br />

and for that reason can never be separated from <strong>the</strong>m.<br />

Phenomenologically speak<strong>in</strong>g, our deal<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world and our<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> ourselves as be<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-world are not marked by any sense<br />

<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ego. <strong>The</strong> question is <strong>the</strong>n: How do we come to know and even<br />

experience ourselves as <strong>the</strong> ego? <strong>The</strong> multiple references to philosophical<br />

tradition <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> chapter under consideration seem to suggest that <strong>the</strong> longestablished<br />

equation <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> with <strong>the</strong> isolated ego is perpetuated by <strong>the</strong><br />

philosophical tradition itself. 11 Accord<strong>in</strong>g to Heidegger, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>sertion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ego<br />

is subsequent to <strong>the</strong> event <strong>of</strong> thought. <strong>The</strong> next question Heidegger goes on to<br />

ask is: How do we experience ourselves, <strong>in</strong> what way are we given to ourselves<br />

phenomenologically? <strong>The</strong> task for Heidegger is to f<strong>in</strong>d an adequate<br />

<strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenal circumstances <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>, i.e., <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> facticity <strong>of</strong> its be<strong>in</strong>g. This means first and foremost tak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to account <strong>the</strong><br />

dictum <strong>of</strong> phenomenology, “to return to <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>mselves,” by free<strong>in</strong>g<br />

ourselves to <strong>the</strong> extent that we can from our conceptual presuppositions.<br />

But what might a phenomenologically accurate account <strong>of</strong> our selfexperience<br />

be? With a view to this concern, Heidegger reaffirms that our<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> ourselves does not arise out <strong>of</strong> a conscious discovery or<br />

th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g. As he puts it, “<strong>The</strong> self is <strong>the</strong>re for <strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> itself without<br />

reflection and without <strong>in</strong>ner perception, before all reflection.” 12 Dase<strong>in</strong> primarily<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ds itself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>the</strong>mselves it is concerned with. 13 <strong>The</strong> self is nei<strong>the</strong>r a<br />

hidden <strong>in</strong>teriority nor is it someth<strong>in</strong>g exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> background <strong>of</strong> all<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentional acts. Dase<strong>in</strong> understands itself from out <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, it is<br />

always <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> midst <strong>of</strong> and assailed (bedrängt) by <strong>the</strong>m, which leads to what<br />

Heidegger terms <strong>the</strong> “associated unveil<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self.” 14 “In everyday terms,”<br />

9 Ibid., 157.<br />

10 Ibid., 158.<br />

11 <strong>The</strong> context <strong>of</strong> this claim is Heidegger’s extensive demonstration <strong>of</strong> his <strong>the</strong>sis that <strong>the</strong><br />

Greeks hastily equated be<strong>in</strong>g with ousia, substance. Interpreted or <strong>in</strong> effect mis<strong>in</strong>terpreted <strong>in</strong> this<br />

way, be<strong>in</strong>g was <strong>in</strong>serted <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> philosophical tradition as be<strong>in</strong>g present-at-hand, constant,<br />

outside <strong>of</strong> time. For details, see, for example, Section Eleven <strong>of</strong> Chapter Two <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> Basic<br />

Problems <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology.<br />

12 Ibid., 159.<br />

13 Ibid.<br />

14 Ibid., 158.


K. LEBEDEVA 85<br />

Heidegger cont<strong>in</strong>ues, “we understand ourselves and our existence by way <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> activities we pursue and <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs we take care <strong>of</strong>.” 15<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong>’s com<strong>in</strong>g back to itself from out <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs br<strong>in</strong>gs us to <strong>the</strong><br />

important notions <strong>of</strong> au<strong>the</strong>nticity (Eigentlichkeit) and <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity. Everyday<br />

self-understand<strong>in</strong>g is not au<strong>the</strong>ntic <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it does not arise from out <strong>of</strong> “<strong>the</strong><br />

most proper and most extreme possibilities <strong>of</strong> our own existence.” 16 For<br />

Heidegger, everydayness (Altäglichkeit) names a dist<strong>in</strong>ct way <strong>of</strong> exist<strong>in</strong>g—<strong>the</strong><br />

one that is characterized first and foremost by pervasiveness and <strong>in</strong>difference. 17<br />

Although it is <strong>the</strong> most common way <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s be<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> everyday Dase<strong>in</strong><br />

becomes <strong>in</strong>dist<strong>in</strong>guishable from its daily concerns. <strong>The</strong> self <strong>of</strong> such<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g dissolves <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>gs. This <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>ntic self-understand<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

however, is nei<strong>the</strong>r ungenu<strong>in</strong>e nor illusory. 18 It is important to realize that<br />

<strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity and au<strong>the</strong>nticity are modes <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self-understand<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong><br />

former is Dase<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g itself from out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> those be<strong>in</strong>gs that<br />

are radically dist<strong>in</strong>ct from it or <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> its absorbed <strong>in</strong>volvement with those<br />

be<strong>in</strong>gs. It is also possible to say that Dase<strong>in</strong> perceives itself as ‘anyone,’ as <strong>the</strong><br />

anonymous ‘<strong>the</strong>y.’ <strong>The</strong> latter is <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g itself <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> its most proper<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g or its most proper possibilities <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong> latter (which will later be<br />

referred to as <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g-towards-death) is what Heidegger understands by<br />

freedom. Inau<strong>the</strong>nticity is <strong>the</strong>n about absorption (Aufgehen) or, accord<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

<strong>the</strong> literal mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German term, go<strong>in</strong>g up <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>gs. 19 It is essentially<br />

characterized by lostness <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self. That is, our <strong>in</strong>terpretative appropriation<br />

<strong>of</strong> ourselves is <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>ntic or simply misguided; it is not ourselves <strong>in</strong> our most<br />

proper be<strong>in</strong>g that we appropriate as what we are. This does not mean that we<br />

do not have <strong>the</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntic experience <strong>of</strong> ourselves <strong>in</strong> this self-absorption <strong>in</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs. It is ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> disjunction between our experience <strong>of</strong><br />

ourselves and our conceptual expression <strong>of</strong> it. It is this lack <strong>of</strong> a<br />

phenomenologically suitable <strong>in</strong>terpretation <strong>of</strong> ourselves that Heidegger draws<br />

our attention to. 20<br />

15 Ibid., 159.<br />

16 Ibid., 160.<br />

17 “Everydayness” is <strong>the</strong> how “<strong>in</strong> accordance with which Dase<strong>in</strong> ‘lives unto <strong>the</strong> day [“<strong>in</strong><br />

den Tag h<strong>in</strong>e<strong>in</strong>lebt”], whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> all its ways <strong>of</strong> behav<strong>in</strong>g or only <strong>in</strong> certa<strong>in</strong> ones which have been<br />

prescribed by Be<strong>in</strong>g-with-one-ano<strong>the</strong>r.” Heidegger goes on to say that “<strong>in</strong> everydayness<br />

everyth<strong>in</strong>g is all one and <strong>the</strong> same, but whatever <strong>the</strong> day may br<strong>in</strong>g is taken as diversification.”<br />

Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time, 370-1.<br />

18 Heidegger, <strong>The</strong> Basic Problems <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology, 160.<br />

19 This is analogous to <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> ‘fallenness’ (Verfallenheit) <strong>in</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time. Indeed,<br />

fallenness <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> world means “an absorption <strong>in</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g-with-one-ano<strong>the</strong>r, <strong>in</strong> so far as <strong>the</strong> latter<br />

is guided by idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity.” Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time, 175.<br />

20 One question that arises here is whe<strong>the</strong>r a phenomenological description <strong>of</strong> reality is<br />

more useful than its normative description. That is, <strong>the</strong>re is no way to tell that someone is act<strong>in</strong>g<br />

au<strong>the</strong>ntically or <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>ntically. <strong>The</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong> two modes exists only for <strong>the</strong> one<br />

who is act<strong>in</strong>g. Perhaps <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>descirnibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> two ‘on <strong>the</strong> outside’ has a greater philosophical<br />

significance than <strong>the</strong>ir <strong>in</strong>visible, private dist<strong>in</strong>ction. One should bear <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, however, that<br />

Heidegger is concerned with <strong>the</strong> most general question <strong>of</strong> ontology—that <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g. An <strong>in</strong>quiry<br />

<strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> way people appear <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> social space would be a specification and <strong>the</strong>refore a deviation


86 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

Heidegger’s guid<strong>in</strong>g concern here seems to be <strong>the</strong> horizon <strong>of</strong> our<br />

projection. Our understand<strong>in</strong>g is, we recall, project<strong>in</strong>g ourselves upon a<br />

particular possibility <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g. In <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntic and <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>ntic<br />

existence <strong>the</strong>re are two radically different horizons <strong>of</strong> projection: one is <strong>the</strong><br />

projection upon this or that possibility as specified by one’s role <strong>in</strong> life, by ontic<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ations; and <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r is <strong>the</strong> projection upon our existence as such, i.e.,<br />

our f<strong>in</strong>itude. For <strong>in</strong>stance, when chooses a certa<strong>in</strong> pr<strong>of</strong>ession, it is possible to<br />

fully identify with <strong>the</strong> chosen role and do everyth<strong>in</strong>g for its sake, that is, to<br />

succeed <strong>in</strong> one’s career as if it were an end <strong>in</strong> itself. What we have <strong>in</strong> this case<br />

is <strong>the</strong> projection onto one ontic determ<strong>in</strong>ation—one’s career. This k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><br />

projection also signifies a closure, a certa<strong>in</strong> bl<strong>in</strong>dness to o<strong>the</strong>r possibilities. If,<br />

however, one realizes that <strong>the</strong> concern for his or her pr<strong>of</strong>essional success<br />

ultimately po<strong>in</strong>ts toward <strong>the</strong> concern for one’s be<strong>in</strong>g as such, no full<br />

identification with this or that ontic particular will be possible. This is to say<br />

that <strong>the</strong> person <strong>in</strong> question will see him- or herself as different from <strong>the</strong> chosen<br />

object, as someone who can never be relieved <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> task to choose <strong>the</strong><br />

possibilities <strong>of</strong> one’s be<strong>in</strong>g. In this case, <strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> difference or <strong>the</strong> space<br />

between <strong>the</strong> one who chooses and <strong>the</strong> object be<strong>in</strong>g chosen ensures an<br />

openness to <strong>the</strong> future, i.e., <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> choos<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g genu<strong>in</strong>ely<br />

anew.<br />

Heidegger adds ano<strong>the</strong>r clarification to “this mysterious reflection <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> self from th<strong>in</strong>gs” by say<strong>in</strong>g that Dase<strong>in</strong> is not “<strong>in</strong>” <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs as someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

extant among <strong>the</strong>m but is ra<strong>the</strong>r “with” <strong>the</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs. 21 An “antecedent<br />

transposition” is <strong>the</strong> condition <strong>of</strong> our be<strong>in</strong>g able to return to ourselves. 22 <strong>The</strong><br />

task is to <strong>in</strong>quire <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> mean<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this transposition and its relationship to<br />

<strong>the</strong> ontological constitution <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> question <strong>of</strong> transposition translates<br />

<strong>in</strong>to that <strong>of</strong> transcendence. 23 Heidegger def<strong>in</strong>es transcendence as a “fundamental<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ontological structure <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>.” 24 <strong>The</strong> subject <strong>of</strong> transcendence<br />

goes hand <strong>in</strong> hand with a problem that he claims is “unknown to all previous<br />

philosophy,” <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> world. His critique <strong>of</strong> Fichte serves as a<br />

passageway to his discussion <strong>of</strong> this problem: <strong>The</strong> Fichtean dictum “Th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong><br />

wall, and <strong>the</strong>n th<strong>in</strong>k <strong>the</strong> one who th<strong>in</strong>ks <strong>the</strong> wall” <strong>in</strong> effect <strong>in</strong>vites us to become<br />

bl<strong>in</strong>d to <strong>the</strong> world. 25 This is <strong>the</strong> case because <strong>the</strong> world is prior to any explicit<br />

cognitive understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> object. 26 What is given to us is never <strong>the</strong> object<br />

from <strong>the</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al <strong>in</strong>quiry. <strong>The</strong> merit <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s description is that it conceptually captures<br />

<strong>the</strong> sense <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g, i.e., <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong> which be<strong>in</strong>g affects our self-understand<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

21 Heidegger, <strong>The</strong> Basic Problems <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology, 161.<br />

22 Ibid.<br />

23 Ibid., 162.<br />

24 Ibid.<br />

25 Ibid.<br />

26 Although I cannot discuss this <strong>in</strong> any detail due to <strong>the</strong> constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>of</strong> space and time, it<br />

should be emphasized that for Heidegger <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between how <strong>the</strong> world is for us and<br />

how it is <strong>in</strong> itself is not a tenable one. Given his commitment to <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>vestigation <strong>of</strong> facticity,<br />

givenness, or <strong>the</strong> ways <strong>in</strong> which one f<strong>in</strong>ds him- or herself <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, it seems that <strong>the</strong>re is no<br />

passageway to any k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> supersensible realm. O<strong>the</strong>rwise put, any such realm would have to be<br />

given for Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> order to fall under <strong>the</strong> scope <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s <strong>in</strong>quiry.


K. LEBEDEVA 87<br />

<strong>in</strong> isolation. Ra<strong>the</strong>r, what is primarily given is a contexture, a contextual whole<br />

<strong>of</strong> equipmentality. 27 “<strong>The</strong> nearest th<strong>in</strong>gs that surround us,” Heidegger tells us,<br />

“we call equipment.” 28 We see this whole from out <strong>of</strong> a practical<br />

circumspection, Umsicht. 29 What is characteristic <strong>of</strong> circumspective see<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

that it always sees th<strong>in</strong>gs from out <strong>of</strong> our specific <strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world.<br />

<strong>The</strong> world that we encounter <strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>volved see<strong>in</strong>g is, literally, <strong>the</strong> world that<br />

surrounds us, Umwelt. This contexture is not someth<strong>in</strong>g we can br<strong>in</strong>g about or<br />

arrive at <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as to see someth<strong>in</strong>g as one determ<strong>in</strong>ate th<strong>in</strong>g is to see it<br />

necessarily <strong>in</strong> relation to o<strong>the</strong>r th<strong>in</strong>gs, to <strong>the</strong> whole that has already been given<br />

to us. Each piece <strong>of</strong> equipment refers to “that for which it is what it is.” 30 It is<br />

thus always anchored <strong>in</strong> a specific for-which or <strong>in</strong>-order-to. 31 None<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong><br />

seem<strong>in</strong>gly endless cha<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> ends and means ultimately po<strong>in</strong>ts back to Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

own be<strong>in</strong>g. It is Dase<strong>in</strong>’s own be<strong>in</strong>g that is first <strong>of</strong> all at stake here and that for<br />

<strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> which <strong>the</strong> referential or relational cha<strong>in</strong> is activated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first<br />

place. But yet it is precisely <strong>the</strong> “for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s be<strong>in</strong>g” that tends to<br />

be forgotten <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s deal<strong>in</strong>gs with <strong>the</strong> world.<br />

Heidegger’s emphasis on equipmentality may at first seem puzzl<strong>in</strong>g<br />

and <strong>the</strong>refore it merits a closer look. It seems that Heidegger wants to<br />

accentuate <strong>the</strong> equipmental character <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> order to disown <strong>the</strong> equation<br />

<strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs with mere objects, someth<strong>in</strong>g that stands before us and leaves us<br />

<strong>in</strong>different. Th<strong>in</strong>gs serve as <strong>the</strong> means to achieve our practical goals. Yet, we<br />

should not hastily conclude that <strong>the</strong> fairly simple contrast between non-useful<br />

and useful th<strong>in</strong>gs is at stake here. <strong>The</strong> key here is that any piece <strong>of</strong> equipment<br />

is always already woven <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> world and, <strong>in</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g used, tacitly illum<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>the</strong><br />

surround<strong>in</strong>g world to <strong>the</strong> extent it is able.<br />

Heidegger’s phenomenological <strong>in</strong>terrogation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> world<br />

is radical because it differs from prior philosophical <strong>in</strong>quiry. At least <strong>in</strong><br />

modernity, philosophical <strong>in</strong>quiry <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> world always started from<br />

<strong>the</strong> relation between <strong>the</strong> subject and a particular isolated object. Such a<br />

formulation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> question is already a fabrication <strong>of</strong> our orig<strong>in</strong>al experience<br />

<strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. Philosophy has always illegitimately redirected <strong>the</strong><br />

problem <strong>of</strong> world to <strong>the</strong> problem <strong>of</strong> nature. 32 In o<strong>the</strong>r words, philosophy has<br />

always seen what was <strong>in</strong> a sense fur<strong>the</strong>st from it, thus fail<strong>in</strong>g to recognize <strong>the</strong><br />

concept <strong>of</strong> world as such. For Heidegger, world is nei<strong>the</strong>r nature nor<br />

presence-at-hand nor a totality <strong>of</strong> present-at-hand th<strong>in</strong>gs. 33 <strong>The</strong> totality <strong>of</strong><br />

Yet, any givenness for human experience would compromise <strong>the</strong> objective ‘purity’ <strong>of</strong> such a<br />

realm. What this means is that we can no longer speak <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> limitation <strong>of</strong> our human faculty <strong>of</strong><br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g, for this would mean that <strong>the</strong>re is a different, experientially <strong>in</strong>accessible world that<br />

we can only speculate about. Part <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s <strong>in</strong>novation here is that he m<strong>in</strong>imized <strong>the</strong> gap<br />

between <strong>the</strong> concept and life.<br />

27 Ibid., 163.<br />

28 Ibid.<br />

29 Ibid.<br />

30 Ibid.<br />

31 Ibid., 164.<br />

32 Ibid., 165.<br />

33 Ibid.


88 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs is, as he writes about it, <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>traworldly, that which lies with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

world. 34 This dist<strong>in</strong>ction is <strong>in</strong> place because for someth<strong>in</strong>g to be an entity<br />

means that it appears with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world. Yet this does not mean that <strong>the</strong> world is<br />

<strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> what is with<strong>in</strong> it. Heidegger’s basic determ<strong>in</strong>ation <strong>of</strong> world is that<br />

<strong>the</strong> “world is not someth<strong>in</strong>g subsequent that we calculate as a result from <strong>the</strong><br />

sum <strong>of</strong> all be<strong>in</strong>gs.” 35 It is ra<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> antecedent horizon that is always ahead <strong>of</strong><br />

us and out <strong>of</strong> which we return when we grasp this or that object. As<br />

Heidegger writes, “We are able to come up aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>in</strong>traworldly be<strong>in</strong>gs solely<br />

because, as exist<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>gs, we are always already <strong>in</strong> a world.” 36 <strong>The</strong> world, he<br />

goes on to say, has <strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>-like mode <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g. 37 If <strong>the</strong> world is Dase<strong>in</strong>-ish,<br />

i.e., subjective, it is precisely <strong>the</strong> phenomenon <strong>of</strong> world that calls for <strong>the</strong><br />

radicalization <strong>of</strong> subjectivity. 38<br />

What is it that <strong>in</strong>extricably b<strong>in</strong>ds Dase<strong>in</strong> and <strong>the</strong> world? It is what<br />

Heidegger calls “projection” (Entwurf). Existence is, <strong>in</strong> addition to o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs, cast<strong>in</strong>g-forth a world. 39 S<strong>in</strong>ce Dase<strong>in</strong>’s essential characteristic was said<br />

to be an understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g (which is <strong>in</strong> each case m<strong>in</strong>e, as we are about to<br />

see) and s<strong>in</strong>ce Dase<strong>in</strong> and <strong>the</strong> world are essentially <strong>the</strong> same, it follows that<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> has an understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, <strong>the</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world that<br />

is prior to a more nuanced understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> this or that phenomenon <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

world. 40 What I would like to note here is a peculiar <strong>in</strong>terlac<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> an<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g and an understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world, that is, Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

self-understand<strong>in</strong>g and its understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong> relations. Heidegger<br />

<strong>the</strong>n writes that s<strong>in</strong>ce “world-understand<strong>in</strong>g is at <strong>the</strong> same time an understand<strong>in</strong>g<strong>of</strong>-itself<br />

by <strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>,” <strong>the</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g that perta<strong>in</strong>s to<br />

<strong>in</strong>tentionality embraces two radically different ways <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> and that <strong>of</strong> extant or <strong>in</strong>traworldly entities. 41 Such general understand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g, Heidegger says a few l<strong>in</strong>es down, is <strong>in</strong>different, bl<strong>in</strong>d to “specific<br />

ways <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g.” Thus, we see that <strong>in</strong>tentionality <strong>in</strong> conjunction with<br />

Heidegger’s “Dase<strong>in</strong>-ish” concept <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world opens <strong>the</strong> way and accounts for<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong>’s essential tendency to become lost <strong>in</strong> entities that are fundamentally<br />

different from it.<br />

In <strong>the</strong> next section, Heidegger po<strong>in</strong>ts out two essential determ<strong>in</strong>ations<br />

<strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> first is that Dase<strong>in</strong> exists for <strong>the</strong> sake <strong>of</strong> its own self or that “it<br />

is occupied with its own capacity to be.” 42 <strong>The</strong> second is that Dase<strong>in</strong> is <strong>in</strong> each<br />

34 Ibid.<br />

35 Ibid.<br />

36 Ibid.<br />

37 Ibid., 166.<br />

38 Ibid., 168.<br />

39 Ibid.<br />

40 I would like to po<strong>in</strong>t out <strong>the</strong> essential <strong>in</strong>terrelation <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world and attunement (Stimmung). This <strong>in</strong>terrelation tells us that Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g is not neutral, unspecific, or colorless. Attunement means be<strong>in</strong>g attuned to <strong>the</strong><br />

world <strong>in</strong> this or that way, be<strong>in</strong>g disposed to one’s be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world one way or ano<strong>the</strong>r. It is,<br />

one could say, an affective color<strong>in</strong>g that is <strong>in</strong>dissoluble from Dase<strong>in</strong>’s understand<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

41 Ibid., 175.<br />

42 Ibid., 170.


K. LEBEDEVA 89<br />

case m<strong>in</strong>e (jeme<strong>in</strong>ig). This “<strong>in</strong> each case m<strong>in</strong>eness” (Jeme<strong>in</strong>igkeit) constitutes <strong>the</strong><br />

s<strong>in</strong>gularity <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it means that Dase<strong>in</strong> belongs to itself <strong>in</strong> its very<br />

mode <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g as act<strong>in</strong>g. In <strong>the</strong> “<strong>in</strong> each case” Dase<strong>in</strong> becomes pla<strong>in</strong>ly<br />

unmistakable to itself. Dase<strong>in</strong>’s concern with its own be<strong>in</strong>g means that it has<br />

<strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> this situation here and now. This task cannot be handed<br />

over to anyone else. Dase<strong>in</strong> can lose or forget itself only and precisely because<br />

it is its own. 43 This lostness <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs is <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>the</strong> first way <strong>in</strong> which Dase<strong>in</strong> is<br />

unveiled to itself <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as “<strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity belongs to <strong>the</strong> essential nature <strong>of</strong><br />

factical Dase<strong>in</strong>.” 44 Heidegger states that “au<strong>the</strong>nticity is only a modification but<br />

not a total obliteration <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity.” 45 At this po<strong>in</strong>t it is possible to br<strong>in</strong>g<br />

<strong>the</strong> problematic <strong>in</strong>to sharper relief. On <strong>the</strong> one hand, we have <strong>the</strong> essential<br />

unavoidability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> “I,” Dase<strong>in</strong>’s <strong>in</strong>eluctable glimpse <strong>in</strong>to its “m<strong>in</strong>eness” and<br />

<strong>the</strong> responsibility associated with it. On <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r hand, we are told that<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> is <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>ntic by its very nature. Indeed, we are enigmatically told that<br />

au<strong>the</strong>nticity is only a modification <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s purposeful comportment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

everyday. <strong>The</strong> three questions that arise here are as follows. Firstly, if Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

reflexivity is about its com<strong>in</strong>g back to itself from out <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs, what k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong><br />

difference must be <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> very be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs to allow for Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

more au<strong>the</strong>ntic return to itself? If directedness to th<strong>in</strong>gs is prior to Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

au<strong>the</strong>ntic self-understand<strong>in</strong>g, what is it that addresses Dase<strong>in</strong> from out <strong>of</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs and, as it were, makes it face ontologically its ownmost be<strong>in</strong>g? In <strong>the</strong><br />

crudest sense, it concerns that which sparks <strong>of</strong>f change <strong>in</strong> self-understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> first place. <strong>The</strong> second question is this: What is it about Dase<strong>in</strong>’s be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

that makes possible <strong>the</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntic return to itself? It is thus about <strong>the</strong> “how” <strong>of</strong><br />

change. <strong>The</strong> third question is: If <strong>the</strong> self is primarily exteriority, <strong>the</strong>re seems to<br />

be no o<strong>the</strong>r place for Dase<strong>in</strong> to return to o<strong>the</strong>r than <strong>the</strong> situation it is already<br />

<strong>in</strong>. Yet <strong>the</strong> focus <strong>of</strong> understand<strong>in</strong>g never<strong>the</strong>less shifts. In what sense? 46 It is<br />

about <strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> change.<br />

Given <strong>the</strong> designation <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs as “<strong>in</strong>traworldly,” it appears that<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> shifts from “<strong>the</strong> world” <strong>in</strong> its richness to concrete th<strong>in</strong>gs with a<br />

remarkable lightness. For Dase<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> world tends to contract <strong>in</strong>to th<strong>in</strong>gs and<br />

grow out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>m aga<strong>in</strong>. Heidegger substantiates such an <strong>in</strong>terpretation with a<br />

reference to childhood where he says that <strong>the</strong> child’s world is charged with<br />

world. 47 This translates <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> notion that <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> world is prior to<br />

any experience <strong>of</strong> selfhood. <strong>The</strong> mention <strong>of</strong> childhood is followed by an<br />

appeal to Rilke’s poem. Poetry or creative literature (Dichtung) is understood<br />

here as <strong>the</strong> manifestation <strong>of</strong> our be<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>in</strong>-<strong>the</strong>-world or someth<strong>in</strong>g like an<br />

au<strong>the</strong>ntic (hermeneutically open) response to <strong>the</strong> world that addresses us from<br />

43 Ibid.<br />

44 Ibid., 171.<br />

45 Ibid.<br />

46 Although I will not address this question explicitly, I hope we will be able to see that<br />

<strong>the</strong> content <strong>of</strong> change is essentially about <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong> which Dase<strong>in</strong> takes up its facticity or<br />

thrownness. Differently put, as was said before with regard to au<strong>the</strong>nticity, it is about Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

self-<strong>in</strong>terpretation.<br />

47 Ibid.


90 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

out <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs. This reference to poetry seems <strong>the</strong> presage <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s work<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> 1930s marked by <strong>the</strong> explicit concern with <strong>the</strong> poetic word. One <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

possible questions is: Where does poetiz<strong>in</strong>g end and philosophy beg<strong>in</strong> if both<br />

are about lett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> world speak to us? Ano<strong>the</strong>r question we ask is: Do we<br />

need to be temporally distant from th<strong>in</strong>gs (ru<strong>in</strong>s or Rilkean walls) <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

see <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong>ir unfamiliarity, <strong>in</strong> order to be captivated by <strong>the</strong>ir estrang<strong>in</strong>g<br />

power? If we do and if <strong>the</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> our hav<strong>in</strong>g-been <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world is<br />

uncanny, <strong>the</strong>n is it because <strong>of</strong> our always com<strong>in</strong>g too late, that is, our <strong>in</strong>ability<br />

to be where we have been and even where we are now—<strong>in</strong> short, because <strong>of</strong><br />

our mortality? Is it techne that discloses to us <strong>the</strong> fact that we as humans are<br />

necessarily unable to be at home <strong>in</strong> any moment or at any site?<br />

Now I would to complicate matters fur<strong>the</strong>r by shift<strong>in</strong>g my discussion<br />

to Stiegler’s Time and Technics. Stiegler writes, “Concern is always <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> a<br />

complex <strong>of</strong> tools, and a tool is always <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> a f<strong>in</strong>ality that itself stems<br />

from a mode <strong>of</strong> temporalization <strong>of</strong> temporality.” 48 To br<strong>in</strong>g this closer to <strong>the</strong><br />

language <strong>of</strong> my paper, concern or care is what guides Dase<strong>in</strong> through <strong>the</strong> lattice<br />

<strong>of</strong> references or relations. Even <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self-forgett<strong>in</strong>g, care is <strong>the</strong> s<strong>in</strong>gular<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> its exist<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>in</strong> its multiple ways <strong>of</strong> pass<strong>in</strong>g through <strong>the</strong> whole <strong>of</strong><br />

relations. A piece <strong>of</strong> equipment is lodged <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> “for-<strong>the</strong>-sake-<strong>of</strong>” and hence <strong>in</strong><br />

a k<strong>in</strong>d <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>ality. This f<strong>in</strong>ality orig<strong>in</strong>ates <strong>in</strong> a mode <strong>of</strong> temporalization <strong>of</strong><br />

temporality, which is, Stiegler goes on to add, a forgett<strong>in</strong>g. 49 At this po<strong>in</strong>t we<br />

may wonder whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>jection <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> language <strong>of</strong> temporality <strong>in</strong>to Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

transactions with<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> referential framework adds anyth<strong>in</strong>g new to <strong>the</strong> already<br />

<strong>in</strong>troduced notions <strong>of</strong> projection and horizons. What seems to be at stake here<br />

is <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong> which Dase<strong>in</strong> endures through <strong>the</strong> everydayness and <strong>the</strong> way <strong>in</strong><br />

which <strong>the</strong> everydayness is essentially repeatable or selfsame. Be<strong>in</strong>g absorbed <strong>in</strong><br />

and permeated by its everyday concerns, Dase<strong>in</strong> acquires a certa<strong>in</strong> duration, a<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> time that is selfsame, undifferentiated. <strong>The</strong> neutral, everyone’s<br />

temporality is, as it were, communicated to Dase<strong>in</strong> by <strong>the</strong> entities it deals with.<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>of</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g this would be that Dase<strong>in</strong>’s disowned temporality and<br />

hence <strong>the</strong> seem<strong>in</strong>g constancy <strong>of</strong> its be<strong>in</strong>g as such are “held toge<strong>the</strong>r” by <strong>the</strong><br />

th<strong>in</strong>gs it is concerned with, not <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r way around. It is this temporality that<br />

is synonymous with Dase<strong>in</strong>’s forgett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> its radical s<strong>in</strong>gularity, its<br />

“m<strong>in</strong>eness.” 50<br />

48 Bernard Stiegler, Technics and Time, 1: <strong>The</strong> Fault <strong>of</strong> Epime<strong>the</strong>us (Stanford: Stanford<br />

University Press, 1998), 264.<br />

49 Ibid.<br />

50 For <strong>the</strong> Heidegger <strong>of</strong> Contributions to Philosophy, this will translate <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

Ereignis, i.e., <strong>the</strong> event <strong>of</strong> appropriation or enown<strong>in</strong>g. Dase<strong>in</strong> becomes a self <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>the</strong> self is<br />

given to it historically <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> moment <strong>of</strong> enown<strong>in</strong>g. In enown<strong>in</strong>g, be<strong>in</strong>g determ<strong>in</strong>es Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

historical projection, which is to say, Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self-understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> terms <strong>of</strong> its own historical<br />

situation. More precisely, enown<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>dicates belong<strong>in</strong>g-toge<strong>the</strong>r <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> and be<strong>in</strong>g. It also<br />

br<strong>in</strong>gs Dase<strong>in</strong> “before <strong>the</strong> pass<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> last god.” Here we can say that <strong>the</strong> last god, just like<br />

f<strong>in</strong>itude <strong>in</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time, is an <strong>in</strong>dication <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> experience that be<strong>in</strong>g is given to Dase<strong>in</strong>. It is<br />

<strong>the</strong> experience that Dase<strong>in</strong> can never be <strong>the</strong> master <strong>of</strong> its own be<strong>in</strong>g that, as it were, discloses<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g itself. See Heidegger, Contributions to Philosophy (From Enown<strong>in</strong>g) (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton: Indiana<br />

University Press, 2000), 286-7.


K. LEBEDEVA 91<br />

Stiegler <strong>the</strong>n asks, “But is not this forgett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Self salutary,<br />

referr<strong>in</strong>g to a more orig<strong>in</strong>ary temporality?” I will attempt to del<strong>in</strong>eate <strong>the</strong> sense<br />

<strong>in</strong> which this forgett<strong>in</strong>g can be said to be salutary at all, <strong>the</strong> way Stiegler sees it.<br />

But first a few words need to be said about <strong>the</strong> temporality <strong>of</strong><br />

au<strong>the</strong>nticity, <strong>the</strong> way Heidegger writes about it <strong>in</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time. It was po<strong>in</strong>ted<br />

out earlier that <strong>the</strong>re are two senses <strong>of</strong> horizon at work <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s projection<br />

or understand<strong>in</strong>g: <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first case, Dase<strong>in</strong> projects itself upon particular ontic<br />

possibilities that are given to it and <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r case it understands itself from<br />

out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> its ownmost be<strong>in</strong>g, which is to say, its f<strong>in</strong>itude. In<br />

what way can we align Dase<strong>in</strong>’s own be<strong>in</strong>g as possibility with f<strong>in</strong>itude at all?<br />

We could approach <strong>the</strong> complex and ample discussion <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

be<strong>in</strong>g-towards-death laid out <strong>in</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time by first draw<strong>in</strong>g two<br />

observations on what has been discussed so far <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> course <strong>of</strong> present essay.<br />

First, <strong>the</strong> language <strong>of</strong> projection, antecedent horizon, and transcendence calls<br />

attention to Dase<strong>in</strong>’s existence as equivalent to possibility. In its be<strong>in</strong>g directed<br />

toward <strong>the</strong> future and com<strong>in</strong>g back to itself from out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> future, <strong>the</strong><br />

ontological realm <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> is <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possible. Yet, this realm <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

possible is not <strong>in</strong>f<strong>in</strong>ite, for <strong>in</strong> this case Dase<strong>in</strong> would never return to itself. In<br />

o<strong>the</strong>r words, Dase<strong>in</strong> would glide over its possibilities without ever hav<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

choose one or <strong>the</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r and without look<strong>in</strong>g back to itself. Given <strong>the</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>like<br />

character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> world and <strong>the</strong> world as <strong>the</strong> site <strong>of</strong> disclosure <strong>of</strong> all<br />

possibilities, we can conclude that <strong>the</strong> complex <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s possibilities is as<br />

f<strong>in</strong>ite as Dase<strong>in</strong> itself. What necessarily circumscribes <strong>the</strong> realm <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

possibilities is noth<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r than its own death. Second, we saw that Dase<strong>in</strong><br />

relates to its ontic possibilities by th<strong>in</strong>gs qua tools, which means that at <strong>the</strong><br />

level <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> everydayness, Dase<strong>in</strong> sees its possibilities as essentially realizable or<br />

achievable. <strong>The</strong> def<strong>in</strong>itional purity <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s ontic possibilities is<br />

compromised by <strong>the</strong>ir realizable character, <strong>the</strong>ir tendency to dissolve <strong>in</strong>to<br />

actuality. If <strong>the</strong>re is one possibility that can never be actualized, it is death. For<br />

<strong>the</strong> Heidegger <strong>of</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time, be<strong>in</strong>g-towards-death is <strong>the</strong> qu<strong>in</strong>tessential<br />

relation to <strong>the</strong> possible. Dase<strong>in</strong> is <strong>the</strong>re as long as its death is as a possibility.<br />

He writes, “<strong>The</strong> closest closeness which one may have <strong>in</strong> Be<strong>in</strong>g towards death as a<br />

possibility, is far as possible from anyth<strong>in</strong>g actual.” 51 In this way, death assumes <strong>the</strong><br />

character <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> most extreme possibility, possibility <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> fullest sense <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

word. Heidegger <strong>the</strong>n elaborates <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> unrealizable possibility by<br />

say<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>in</strong> question is “<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong> any<br />

human existence at all.” 52 This is ano<strong>the</strong>r way <strong>of</strong> say<strong>in</strong>g that for Dase<strong>in</strong>, its death<br />

can only be precisely as possible. <strong>The</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> death, Heidegger goes on<br />

to say, “reveals itself to be such that it knows no measure at all” and “<strong>of</strong>fers no<br />

support for becom<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>tent on someth<strong>in</strong>g, ‘pictur<strong>in</strong>g’ to oneself <strong>the</strong> actuality<br />

which is possible.” 53 Before <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> death, all o<strong>the</strong>r possibilities that<br />

are present for Dase<strong>in</strong> become unfamiliar and mean<strong>in</strong>gless and for this reason<br />

51 Heidegger, Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time, 262.<br />

52 Ibid.<br />

53 Ibid.


92 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

require someth<strong>in</strong>g like a revaluation. S<strong>in</strong>ce this possibility also turns out to be<br />

“one’s ownmost and uttermost potentiality-for-Be<strong>in</strong>g,” it is now seen as <strong>the</strong><br />

source <strong>of</strong> any mean<strong>in</strong>gful recast<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s circumstantial givenness. 54 It is<br />

<strong>the</strong> openness that is first disclosed <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s shatter<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st its f<strong>in</strong>itude<br />

that allows Dase<strong>in</strong> to be free, i.e., to be different from how it was before and<br />

<strong>the</strong>refore to take on its facticity <strong>in</strong> a creative, recontextualized way.<br />

<strong>The</strong> question that emerges from this is: How does Dase<strong>in</strong>’s relation to<br />

its most extreme possibility affect its self-understand<strong>in</strong>g? To put it <strong>in</strong> ano<strong>the</strong>r<br />

way, what happens to Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self-understand<strong>in</strong>g after it comes up aga<strong>in</strong>st <strong>the</strong><br />

limit <strong>of</strong> all <strong>of</strong> its ontic possibilities? Heidegger’s discussion <strong>of</strong> guilt and <strong>the</strong> call<br />

<strong>of</strong> conscience <strong>of</strong>fers us some help <strong>in</strong> answer<strong>in</strong>g this question. He strips <strong>the</strong><br />

notion <strong>of</strong> guilt <strong>of</strong> its moral connotations and def<strong>in</strong>es it <strong>in</strong>stead as “Be<strong>in</strong>g-<strong>the</strong>-basis<br />

<strong>of</strong> a nullity.” 55 What does it mean to say that Dase<strong>in</strong>’s be<strong>in</strong>g is grounded <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

noth<strong>in</strong>g, a nullity or a lack? <strong>The</strong> ground <strong>of</strong> an entity is identical with <strong>the</strong> entity’s<br />

reason or cause. <strong>The</strong> groundlessness <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> has everyth<strong>in</strong>g to do with <strong>the</strong><br />

fact that it is not self-caused. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, Dase<strong>in</strong> has not been thrown <strong>in</strong>to<br />

its “<strong>the</strong>re” <strong>of</strong> its own accord. 56 S<strong>in</strong>ce Dase<strong>in</strong>’s facticity or thrownness is<br />

saturated with negativity, two th<strong>in</strong>gs follow. First, its own be<strong>in</strong>g was, as it<br />

were, handed over to it. <strong>The</strong> event <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s orig<strong>in</strong>ation always precedes it<br />

and is <strong>the</strong>refore beyond its grasp. Thus, Dase<strong>in</strong> is guilty first <strong>of</strong> all to itself<br />

<strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it constantly falls beh<strong>in</strong>d its own be<strong>in</strong>g. Second, as Heidegger tells<br />

us, Dase<strong>in</strong> is this thrown ground “only <strong>in</strong> that it projects itself upon<br />

possibilities <strong>in</strong>to which it has been thrown.” 57 Dase<strong>in</strong>’s co<strong>in</strong>cidence with its<br />

facticity, its rootedness <strong>in</strong> a particular set <strong>of</strong> circumstances and an array <strong>of</strong><br />

particular possibilities that stems from it, is also <strong>in</strong> reference to <strong>the</strong> possibility<br />

<strong>of</strong> no-longer-exist<strong>in</strong>g, to <strong>the</strong> negativity <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s mortal horizon which<br />

shatter<strong>in</strong>gly echoes <strong>the</strong> negativity bound up with its orig<strong>in</strong>ation. Be<strong>in</strong>g out for<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> death discloses that <strong>in</strong>to which Dase<strong>in</strong> has already been<br />

thrown. Hence, Dase<strong>in</strong>’s au<strong>the</strong>ntic relation to <strong>the</strong> future recoils upon its<br />

relation to its past <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as <strong>in</strong> anticipat<strong>in</strong>g death, Dase<strong>in</strong> is free to<br />

appropriate—that is, to repeat or retrieve—what is already given to it. In a<br />

sense, Dase<strong>in</strong> au<strong>the</strong>ntically chooses what is already its own. It comes to be<br />

ontologically itself by virtue <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividuat<strong>in</strong>g force <strong>of</strong> f<strong>in</strong>itude. 58 That is, it is<br />

with a view to its f<strong>in</strong>itude that Dase<strong>in</strong>’s is ‘<strong>in</strong>troduced’ to <strong>the</strong> true nature <strong>of</strong> its<br />

cares or concerns <strong>in</strong> its world <strong>in</strong> that it realizes that its cares center around its<br />

own be<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Yet, as we saw throughout this paper, Dase<strong>in</strong> is for <strong>the</strong> most part<br />

absorbed <strong>in</strong>to its everyday world <strong>of</strong> plans and concerns. It <strong>the</strong>refore seems<br />

that <strong>the</strong>re must be someth<strong>in</strong>g that pulls Dase<strong>in</strong> away from its daily affairs and<br />

summons it to its groundlessness. It seems, however, that this “someth<strong>in</strong>g”<br />

54 Ibid., 263.<br />

55 Ibid., 284.<br />

56 Ibid.<br />

57 Ibid.<br />

58 Heidegger writes that “Dase<strong>in</strong> can be au<strong>the</strong>ntically itself only if it makes” its ownmost<br />

potentiality for be<strong>in</strong>g “possible for itself <strong>of</strong> its own accord.” Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time, 263.


K. LEBEDEVA 93<br />

cannot come entirely from <strong>the</strong> outside, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is Dase<strong>in</strong>’s ownmost be<strong>in</strong>g that<br />

is at stake here. Or at least, <strong>the</strong> summons cannot be issued forth by <strong>the</strong> outside<br />

as everydayness, s<strong>in</strong>ce it is precisely <strong>in</strong> it that <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> is conflated<br />

with <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r entities unlike it. Keep<strong>in</strong>g up with <strong>the</strong> language <strong>of</strong><br />

guilt, Heidegger terms this phenomenon “<strong>the</strong> call <strong>of</strong> conscience.” What is this<br />

call like and whose call is it?<br />

Heidegger asserts that “conscience discourses solely and constantly <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> mode <strong>of</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g silent.” 59 Silence is speak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>s<strong>of</strong>ar as it gives someth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to understand, but yet silence is opposed to all ontic discourse. When Dase<strong>in</strong><br />

falls under <strong>the</strong> spell <strong>of</strong> silence, it is transported <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> midst <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> uncanny,<br />

not-be<strong>in</strong>g-at-home, or, to put it ano<strong>the</strong>r way, <strong>the</strong> unbridgeable difference<br />

between itself and everyth<strong>in</strong>g around it, <strong>the</strong> difference between <strong>the</strong> ontological<br />

and <strong>the</strong> ontic. <strong>The</strong> call <strong>of</strong> conscience summons Dase<strong>in</strong> to its ownmost<br />

potentiality for be<strong>in</strong>g, which means that Dase<strong>in</strong>’s be<strong>in</strong>g becomes an issue for it<br />

<strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> highest degree. <strong>The</strong> call differentiates Dase<strong>in</strong> from whatever it is<br />

ord<strong>in</strong>arily <strong>in</strong>volved with and it makes room for Dase<strong>in</strong>’s look<strong>in</strong>g at its lifecontext<br />

anew by precisely highlight<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> fact that Dase<strong>in</strong> as potentiality could<br />

have been or could yet be o<strong>the</strong>rwise than it is. What this amounts to is that <strong>the</strong><br />

call animates <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> a genu<strong>in</strong>e change or transformation <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>.<br />

<strong>The</strong> call and <strong>the</strong> caller, Heidegger goes on to say, are paradoxically one. He<br />

writes, “<strong>The</strong> call comes from me, and yet from beyond me and over me.” 60 Dase<strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong>n splits <strong>in</strong>to a command to au<strong>the</strong>ntically choose itself and <strong>the</strong><br />

accomplishment <strong>of</strong> that command. Dase<strong>in</strong> simultaneously rem<strong>in</strong>ds itself and is<br />

rem<strong>in</strong>ded that it <strong>in</strong>evitably has <strong>the</strong> task to be, that <strong>in</strong> not com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to existence<br />

<strong>of</strong> its own accord, Dase<strong>in</strong> is not quite co<strong>in</strong>cident with its be<strong>in</strong>g and is always<br />

yet to catch up with it by assum<strong>in</strong>g its hav<strong>in</strong>g-been.<br />

What <strong>the</strong> preced<strong>in</strong>g paragraphs attempted to br<strong>in</strong>g to light is <strong>the</strong><br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g: Dase<strong>in</strong> can appropriate its own be<strong>in</strong>g as that which is shot through<br />

with negativity and because <strong>of</strong> that. Dase<strong>in</strong> has to pass through its own nullity<br />

<strong>in</strong> order to make an au<strong>the</strong>ntic choice about its be<strong>in</strong>g. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, Dase<strong>in</strong><br />

has to allow negativity to work a change upon its self-understand<strong>in</strong>g by<br />

sever<strong>in</strong>g it from <strong>the</strong> ontic, everyday context. Such a passage through <strong>the</strong><br />

noth<strong>in</strong>g is possible only when Dase<strong>in</strong> is called upon or addressed by<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g. Yet <strong>the</strong> identification <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> with both <strong>the</strong> call and <strong>the</strong> caller<br />

makes <strong>the</strong> situation all <strong>the</strong> more enigmatic, s<strong>in</strong>ce we have already seen Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

<strong>in</strong>separability from <strong>the</strong> world or, <strong>in</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong> blurr<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>teriority and<br />

exteriority. <strong>The</strong> question is <strong>the</strong>n: What is <strong>the</strong> role <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s everyday world<br />

when it comes to <strong>the</strong> disquiet<strong>in</strong>g call <strong>of</strong> conscience or <strong>the</strong> call <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> noth<strong>in</strong>g?<br />

Now we are prepared to return to and assess Stiegler’s claim about<br />

self-forgett<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> relation to temporality and <strong>the</strong> aforesaid question. Stiegler<br />

purports to <strong>in</strong>troduce <strong>the</strong> question <strong>of</strong> work <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> equation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> outside<br />

with <strong>in</strong>strumentality, techne. He refers to Maurice Blanchot’s example <strong>of</strong> a<br />

writer to illustrate his po<strong>in</strong>t. A writer is a contradiction because someone who<br />

59 Ibid., 273.<br />

60 Ibid., 275.


94 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

wants to write must know that he or she possess <strong>the</strong> gift to write, yet one does<br />

not know whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> gift is <strong>in</strong> fact <strong>the</strong>re, until someth<strong>in</strong>g is written by that<br />

person. <strong>The</strong> writer is <strong>in</strong> this sense posterior to his or her work and is <strong>the</strong>refore<br />

def<strong>in</strong>ed by it.<br />

Stiegler transfers <strong>the</strong> situation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> writer to that <strong>of</strong> humanity <strong>in</strong><br />

general by say<strong>in</strong>g that <strong>the</strong> “question <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g is noth<strong>in</strong>g but a radicalization <strong>of</strong><br />

that <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> memory <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human.” 61 Human be<strong>in</strong>gs recognize or, more<br />

precisely, remember <strong>the</strong>mselves as hav<strong>in</strong>g-been <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> traces <strong>of</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g. It is<br />

however <strong>the</strong> task <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>g to first produce <strong>the</strong>se traces and <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to do that it must forget itself. To forget <strong>the</strong> self means to “let one’s o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

be—but ano<strong>the</strong>r who is not a self, not one’s own, but quite o<strong>the</strong>r.” 62<br />

Disappropriation, lett<strong>in</strong>g go <strong>of</strong> that which is one’s own is <strong>the</strong> prerequisite for<br />

work as such. Yet, <strong>the</strong> loss <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self that is qu<strong>in</strong>tessential for work is<br />

countered by <strong>the</strong> recognition <strong>of</strong> ourselves <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> work produced, <strong>the</strong><br />

recognition <strong>of</strong> ourselves precisely as new to or not ourselves. Accord<strong>in</strong>g to <strong>the</strong><br />

example <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> writer, <strong>the</strong> effects produced <strong>in</strong>vest <strong>the</strong> person who is writ<strong>in</strong>g<br />

with a crucially new self-understand<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

An important po<strong>in</strong>t follows. If <strong>the</strong> self is somehow renewed <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> process <strong>of</strong><br />

work, <strong>the</strong>re can never be atta<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> presence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self. To put this <strong>in</strong> more<br />

Heideggerian language, we could say that Dase<strong>in</strong> returns to itself precisely <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> moment <strong>of</strong> differentiation from itself. For Stiegler, <strong>the</strong> essential<br />

<strong>in</strong>tertw<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g and <strong>in</strong>separability <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> human be<strong>in</strong>g and <strong>the</strong> world is best<br />

<strong>in</strong>stantiated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> phenomenon <strong>of</strong> work. In a certa<strong>in</strong> sense, <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

work br<strong>in</strong>gs to <strong>the</strong> fore <strong>the</strong> malleability <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self and is <strong>the</strong>refore <strong>in</strong><br />

perfect accordance with Heidegger’s decisive critique <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> ego as constant<br />

presence. Work, however, is possible only on <strong>the</strong> basis <strong>of</strong> self-forgett<strong>in</strong>g. <strong>The</strong><br />

destabilization <strong>of</strong> any present or given self and <strong>the</strong> affirmation <strong>of</strong> its perpetual<br />

self-surpass<strong>in</strong>g, its renewal, seems to be what motivates Stiegler’s ascription <strong>of</strong><br />

a highly positive valence to dissolution <strong>in</strong> work and <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> work as such.<br />

What Stiegler attempts to do <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g such arguments, <strong>the</strong> way I understand<br />

it, is noth<strong>in</strong>g o<strong>the</strong>r than an <strong>in</strong>tensification <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s idea that Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

au<strong>the</strong>ntic self-<strong>in</strong>terpretation always arises out <strong>of</strong> and cannot be separated from<br />

its <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>ntic absorption <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> everydayness. Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self-understand<strong>in</strong>g is<br />

constituted <strong>in</strong> its return to itself from out <strong>of</strong> th<strong>in</strong>gs or <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> work,<br />

which is to say that <strong>the</strong> everyday comportment is <strong>the</strong> basel<strong>in</strong>e for Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

au<strong>the</strong>ntic access to itself. However, it rema<strong>in</strong>s unclear how Stiegler’s analysis<br />

can account for any genu<strong>in</strong>e change <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s self-understand<strong>in</strong>g. One<br />

question should suffice to show this: If, as was said earlier, <strong>the</strong> temporality <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> everydayness is essentially constant and undifferentiated, if this temporality<br />

permeates Dase<strong>in</strong>’s everyday absorption <strong>in</strong> techne, and, f<strong>in</strong>ally, if Dase<strong>in</strong> is<br />

<strong>in</strong>formed by its everyday world, <strong>the</strong>n where—methodologically speak<strong>in</strong>g—<br />

does <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> change come <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> picture? <strong>The</strong> problem with<br />

Stiegler’s claims <strong>the</strong>n seems to be his <strong>in</strong>sistence on <strong>the</strong> change-<strong>in</strong>duc<strong>in</strong>g value<br />

61 Stiegler, Technics and Time, 1, 264-5.<br />

62 Ibid., 265.


K. LEBEDEVA 95<br />

<strong>of</strong> techne as such, which precludes differentiation with<strong>in</strong> it. If just any <strong>in</strong>stance<br />

whatsoever <strong>of</strong> techne <strong>of</strong>fers a possibility <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s au<strong>the</strong>ntic return to itself,<br />

<strong>the</strong>n <strong>the</strong> phenomenon <strong>of</strong> such a renewal rema<strong>in</strong>s unexpla<strong>in</strong>ed. Moreover, it<br />

appears questionable to me whe<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong> assertion <strong>of</strong> techne <strong>in</strong> its homogeneity<br />

as well as an anonymous dispersion <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world m<strong>in</strong>us <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

“m<strong>in</strong>eness” 63 (it is, after all, uncerta<strong>in</strong> what exactly allows <strong>the</strong> writ<strong>in</strong>g person to<br />

identify with <strong>the</strong> writer brought <strong>in</strong>to existence by writ<strong>in</strong>g) <strong>of</strong>fer us <strong>the</strong><br />

conceptual means necessary to address <strong>the</strong> transformation <strong>of</strong> experience and—<br />

I am tempted to add—temporal unfold<strong>in</strong>g as such. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, if it is <strong>the</strong><br />

case that <strong>the</strong> analysis <strong>of</strong> temporality as such h<strong>in</strong>ges upon a rigorous notion <strong>of</strong><br />

change, <strong>the</strong> fully-developed understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> temporality and, by extension, <strong>of</strong><br />

historicality, <strong>the</strong> analysis that lacks such a notion does not seem to be<br />

particularly vital.<br />

Never<strong>the</strong>less, <strong>the</strong> emphasis on <strong>the</strong> outside may be appreciated <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

early Heidegger’s own th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> au<strong>the</strong>nticity and <strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity. We can see<br />

that this is <strong>the</strong> case by pay<strong>in</strong>g attention to <strong>the</strong> troubled aspects <strong>of</strong> his notion <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> call <strong>of</strong> conscience. It is not clear how we are to th<strong>in</strong>k about <strong>the</strong><br />

simultaneity <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s call<strong>in</strong>g itself and be<strong>in</strong>g called upon and <strong>in</strong> fact why we<br />

may want to assert <strong>the</strong> simultaneity <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> first place. In o<strong>the</strong>r words,<br />

Heidegger—his resistance to such traditional notions <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> self as <strong>in</strong>teriority<br />

or self-subsist<strong>in</strong>g entity notwithstand<strong>in</strong>g—does not tell us why <strong>the</strong> call has to<br />

have <strong>the</strong> double orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world and Dase<strong>in</strong>. <strong>The</strong> suspicion that th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong> as <strong>the</strong> partial orig<strong>in</strong> <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> call is haunted by <strong>the</strong> remnants <strong>of</strong> traditional<br />

subjectivity is fortified by Heidegger’s abandonment <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> language <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> call<br />

<strong>of</strong> conscience altoge<strong>the</strong>r and <strong>the</strong> shift<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> his focus to <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> art <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

1930s. Heidegger’s discussions <strong>of</strong> art and <strong>the</strong> poetic word specifically could be<br />

seen as a formal explanation <strong>of</strong> how Dase<strong>in</strong> can be called upon by <strong>the</strong> world <strong>in</strong><br />

such a way that it enables a genu<strong>in</strong>e modification <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>’s selfunderstand<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

That is to say, Heidegger articulates and develops <strong>the</strong><br />

differentiation with<strong>in</strong> techne itself to allow for <strong>the</strong> possibility <strong>of</strong> change without<br />

any pronounced sense <strong>of</strong> agency. <strong>The</strong> change happens to Dase<strong>in</strong> not because<br />

<strong>the</strong>re is some hidden <strong>in</strong>teriority <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> that wills it, but ra<strong>the</strong>r because <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong><br />

qualitative differences <strong>in</strong>herent <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> effects <strong>of</strong> techne itself and Dase<strong>in</strong>’s<br />

fundamental ability to be affected and <strong>in</strong>formed by techne as it is woven <strong>in</strong>to<br />

Dase<strong>in</strong>’s surround<strong>in</strong>g world. Heidegger thus sees that <strong>the</strong> world itself has to<br />

address Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> two emphatically different ways <strong>in</strong> order to say that <strong>the</strong>re is<br />

more than one way <strong>of</strong> liv<strong>in</strong>g (I use <strong>the</strong> verb <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> transitive sense) temporality.<br />

<strong>The</strong> world as ord<strong>in</strong>ary techne addresses Dase<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> a way that does not <strong>in</strong>troduce<br />

it to <strong>the</strong> essential difference between <strong>the</strong> be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong> and that <strong>of</strong> o<strong>the</strong>r<br />

63 See, for <strong>in</strong>stance, Stiegler’s repeated references to Maurice Blanchot who, <strong>in</strong> his turn,<br />

suggests that <strong>the</strong> absorption <strong>in</strong>to and <strong>the</strong> experience <strong>of</strong> language is <strong>in</strong>compatible with any<br />

discourse on subjectivity—which means that <strong>in</strong> its go<strong>in</strong>g out <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong> world, Dase<strong>in</strong> does not<br />

come up aga<strong>in</strong>st any <strong>in</strong>dividuat<strong>in</strong>g phenomenon such as its f<strong>in</strong>itude (252, 262, 264, 266 <strong>in</strong> Technics<br />

and Time, 1). Indeed, Blanchot writes <strong>of</strong> “not proper but featureless death,” death that has “no<br />

relation to me” and “no power over me” (quoted <strong>in</strong> endnote six to Part Two, Chapter Three <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> Stiegler text).


96 THE ROLE OF TECHNE<br />

entities. <strong>The</strong> world that is call<strong>in</strong>g Dase<strong>in</strong> from out <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> extraord<strong>in</strong>ary techne <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> art allows Dase<strong>in</strong> to return to itself <strong>in</strong> a restorative way or,<br />

differently put, to convert Dase<strong>in</strong>’s circumstantial limitations <strong>in</strong>to an<br />

acknowledged dist<strong>in</strong>ctiveness out <strong>of</strong> which someth<strong>in</strong>g new is born. In a sense,<br />

this is exactly where Stiegler stops <strong>in</strong> his analysis: he <strong>in</strong>tensifies <strong>the</strong> notion <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> outside qua techne, but yet he does not elaborate on any dist<strong>in</strong>ction with<strong>in</strong><br />

techne that would br<strong>in</strong>g about any change <strong>in</strong> Dase<strong>in</strong>. I <strong>the</strong>refore f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>the</strong> later<br />

Heidegger’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs on art critically important <strong>in</strong> th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g through <strong>the</strong> issue <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> self and <strong>the</strong> outside under <strong>the</strong> rubric <strong>of</strong> temporality without slid<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to <strong>the</strong><br />

language <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>teriority. To return to <strong>the</strong> question I raised at <strong>the</strong> beg<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g <strong>of</strong><br />

<strong>the</strong> essay, it seems to me that <strong>the</strong> dist<strong>in</strong>ction between au<strong>the</strong>nticity and<br />

<strong>in</strong>au<strong>the</strong>nticity—however subtle—is an <strong>in</strong>tegral part <strong>of</strong> Heidegger’s notion <strong>of</strong><br />

temporality as such. Whe<strong>the</strong>r it is possible to collapse this dist<strong>in</strong>ction and yet<br />

present a viable account <strong>of</strong> change is <strong>the</strong> question that rema<strong>in</strong>s to be critically<br />

exam<strong>in</strong>ed elsewhere.<br />

References Cited<br />

Department <strong>of</strong> Philosophy, DePaul University, United States<br />

Heidegger, Mart<strong>in</strong>, Be<strong>in</strong>g and Time (San Francisco: Harper San Francisco, 1962).<br />

__________, Contributions to Philosophy (From Enown<strong>in</strong>g) (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton: Indiana<br />

University Press, 2000).<br />

__________, <strong>The</strong> Basic Problems <strong>of</strong> Phenomenology (Bloom<strong>in</strong>gton: Indiana<br />

University Press, 1988).<br />

Stiegler, Bernard, Technics and Time, 1: <strong>The</strong> Fault <strong>of</strong> Epime<strong>the</strong>us (Stanford:<br />

Stanford University Press, 1998).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!