04.03.2014 Views

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

7 4 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

In this regime, democracy’s small-souled ‘mass man’ becomes a capable, selfgoverning<br />

citizen. Tocqueville’s political science discovers <strong>and</strong> encourages this<br />

human type. “Tocqueville can be said to have desired to restore politics, <strong>and</strong><br />

therewith greatness, to the political science of liberalism” (96).<br />

Self-government enables citizens to secure their rights by<br />

“obey[ing] without being submissive <strong>and</strong> comm<strong>and</strong> without being arrogant”<br />

(97). That is, self-government makes the theoretical rights of the Declaration of<br />

Independence real in practice as well as in speech, <strong>and</strong> exemplifies Aristotle’s<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of politics as ruling <strong>and</strong> being ruled in turn. The three innovations<br />

of Tocqueville’s new political science for a world altogether new each shows<br />

how this can be possible. His concept of “the social state,” seems to combine the<br />

modern desire to reduce society to pre-political elements with Aristotle’s insistence<br />

on the importance of regimes, inasmuch as the two kinds of social state are<br />

characterized by the political terms, ‘democratic’ <strong>and</strong> ‘aristocratic.’<br />

America has a “point of departure”—the Puritans—rather than a<br />

deliberate founding. A founding is imposed, but a social state causes<br />

the society without ruling over it. That is why an aristocracy, which<br />

is the rule of a part imposing itself on the whole is less of a social<br />

state than is a democracy. (98)<br />

(To this, Aristotle might reply: democratic public opinion does in fact reflect<br />

the imposition of a part, albeit the majority, over the whole, <strong>and</strong> as for the<br />

Puritans, their founding had already occurred, in Engl<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> their presence<br />

in America meant that they had lost a regime struggle there. Tocqueville might<br />

not altogether disagree with that.)<br />

The second innovation of Tocqueville’s political science consists<br />

in seeing that individuals in democracies are sembables—equal not only in<br />

the sense of having rights but in the sense of being alike in seeing themselves as<br />

equals. Democracies frustrate Hegelians because ‘the other’ does not exist in<br />

them, insofar as they truly are democratic. Those who try to agitate such societies<br />

with stories of racial <strong>and</strong> class conflict will finally lose; not enough of the<br />

citizens will quite believe them because, although such conflicts will exist, they<br />

will not often predominate. If at some point they do predominate, the majority<br />

will win them decisively. Although this seems to mean that “aristocracy <strong>and</strong><br />

democracy are successive eras in history, not constant possibilities for human<br />

beings to choose between or to mix, as Aristotle had argued” (100), Mansfield<br />

<strong>and</strong> Winthrop immediately mention that the few still exist in democracies—<br />

the intelligent <strong>and</strong> the rich, for example. They can make little headway by<br />

appealing directly to their own virtues as such. There is not enough ‘fewness’

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!