04.03.2014 Views

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6 4 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

of another state. Second, states must submit themselves to a “minimal world<br />

state” (199). The grounding of these two duties follows the same argument as<br />

above, based on the conditions for the possibility of state coexistence.<br />

However, Höffe addresses two differences between state <strong>and</strong><br />

cosmopolitan justice which could undermine the possibility of peace. First,<br />

unlike individuals in a state of nature, we have no reason to expect that states in<br />

the international state of nature will come to realize the value of peace. Kant’s<br />

philosophy of history, Höffe suggests in chapters 9 <strong>and</strong> 10, provides an account<br />

of how states will become peaceable in the long run: like Hegel, Kant argues<br />

that the “cunning of reason” is at work in human activity (162): the egoism of<br />

economic activity unaffected by political competition generates economic<br />

benefit for all, competition <strong>and</strong> war tend toward a balance of power <strong>and</strong> equilibrium,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the development of the arts <strong>and</strong> sciences leads to a more moral<br />

populace (160–74).<br />

The second difference is that, unlike individuals who must<br />

submit themselves to a rule of law in a state, the states of the world ought not to<br />

form a world state. Kant argues that such a world state would destroy the possibility<br />

of future freedom if it turned toward despotism because it would have<br />

no rivals to balance or question its authority. Yet, Höffe suggests, parting ways<br />

with Kant (notably rare in this text), neither should the states embrace a very<br />

loose federation of states, in which each state retains its absolute sovereignty,<br />

because the world state would then not have any coercive power to enforce justice<br />

among the member states. Höffe rejects the either/or of “either full<br />

sovereignty or none” (197), <strong>and</strong> argues that a federal world republic characterized<br />

by subsidiarity would promote peace more effectively than the Kantian<br />

loose federation (200–201).<br />

Such a division of sovereignty, however, faces theoretical <strong>and</strong><br />

practical difficulties. The Hobbesian theoretical objection is that sovereignty<br />

cannot be divisible because there must be a final decision in any particular case,<br />

which rests either in the member states or in the world state. Even if this theoretical<br />

objection can be overcome by a detailed exposition of the scope of<br />

sovereignty according to the principle of subsidiarity, a practical objection<br />

arises on the grounds that such a careful delineation of the limits of authority<br />

would likely break down when a conflict would occur. The balance of power<br />

would shift either to the world state, which would become more robust <strong>and</strong><br />

far-reaching, or to the member states, forcing a slide into a loose confederation.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!