04.03.2014 Views

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Book Review: Kant’s Cosmopolitan Theory of Law <strong>and</strong> Peace<br />

6 3<br />

in their external behavior, <strong>and</strong> in doing so, their private wills become the general<br />

will.<br />

Kant’s argument also allows for criticism of the scope of legitimate<br />

governmental power, so that Höffe can escape the “practical antinomy”<br />

discussed above. Höffe explicates Kant’s argument by first claiming that coercion<br />

is primarily “protective in nature” (114) in that it restores justice when one<br />

pursues one’s private will at the expense of the general will. However, the government<br />

cannot affect one’s internal self-legislation by legislating virtue; it can<br />

only regulate the external activity of citizens by maintaining the integrity of the<br />

private spheres of non-interference <strong>and</strong> the impartial rule of law. In short, Kant<br />

replaces the philosopher-king with the kingly people: each individual is a sovereign,<br />

autonomous individual unto himself. The liberal state is constructed by<br />

these kingly people to maintain the integrity of this individual sovereignty <strong>and</strong><br />

stave off the encroachment of authoritarian governmental power.<br />

Höffe’s reconstruction of Kant’s moral grounding of politics<br />

is impressive <strong>and</strong> ambitious, but not immune to criticism, especially on the<br />

matter of the source of rights. In chapter 7, Höffe insists that “right is not naturally<br />

given, but must be created” (130). Kant rejects the Lockean grounding of<br />

natural right on self-ownership. He claims instead that basic rights come from<br />

fulfilling an original duty to oneself, the duty to “assert oneself as a legal equal”<br />

(121). Individual rights, then,“depend on one’s own achievement <strong>and</strong> [are] not<br />

granted by others” (122). Höffe does not consider, however, the following questions:<br />

what happens when someone fails to attend to the basic duty of legal<br />

self-assertion? Does this person not enjoy rights? Further, if this unassertive<br />

person is bound by the moral law, does this not mean that this person is already<br />

entitled to his autonomy, so that he should be treated as an end of another’s<br />

action, rather than as a means? The Kingdom of Ends from Kant’s Groundwork<br />

already contains “naturally given” rights, so the idea of legal self-assertion, in<br />

addition to being problematic, also seems superfluous.<br />

In part III, Höffe shows how, for Kant, the moral law necessarily<br />

extends beyond national borders to concern itself with the relationship<br />

among states. Specifically, Kant called for “perpetual peace” among nations,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Höffe applauds Kant for st<strong>and</strong>ing apart from his successors such as Hegel,<br />

who eschew this desideratum. The conditions for peace require the fulfillment<br />

of two duties placed on all states by the moral law. First, just as individuals have<br />

a duty to leave the state of nature, states must also seek peace, particularly by<br />

abolishing st<strong>and</strong>ing armies <strong>and</strong> refraining from interference in the constitution

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!