04.03.2014 Views

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Book Review: Kant’s Cosmopolitan Theory of Law <strong>and</strong> Peace<br />

6 1<br />

larities, according to Kant, morality is separable from, <strong>and</strong> logically prior to,<br />

happiness, whereas for Aristotle, happiness encompasses moral action as the<br />

object of moral striving (34–39). Höffe finds Kant victorious over Aristotle in<br />

the description of moral action: for Aristotle, all action is performed for the<br />

sake of happiness, whereas for Kant, some actions aim at one’s happiness,<br />

whereas some actions are performed simply because one must do the right<br />

thing. According to Höffe, Kant’s description of moral action fits our moral<br />

vocabulary better than Aristotle’s, because sometimes we must do the right<br />

thing at the expense of our happiness.<br />

Höffe’s discussion of the similarities between Aristotle <strong>and</strong><br />

Kant is illuminating <strong>and</strong> insightful, but his judgment of the superiority of Kant<br />

over Aristotle is made too hastily. Höffe appeals to a distinctively modern<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of happiness as a purely personal, conscious state. Aristotle, by<br />

contrast, defines happiness as the “active exercise of the soul’s faculties in conformity<br />

with virtue” (Nicomachean Ethics, 1098a15). One of these virtues is<br />

justice, which involves doing the right or lawful thing. Aristotle thus would<br />

reject the modern underst<strong>and</strong>ing of happiness as a base view of the good akin<br />

to the bovine “life of enjoyment” (ibid., 1095b15). Thus to answer the question—Aristotle<br />

or Kant?—we must not remain where Höffe leaves us, at the level<br />

of better <strong>and</strong> worse descriptions of modern moral phenomena, but we must<br />

delve into the differences between ancient <strong>and</strong> modern views of happiness.<br />

Höffe takes up in chapter 3 a second caricature of Kant’s<br />

moral philosophy, the view that Kant’s ethics precludes common sense or prudential<br />

judgment, unreasonably dem<strong>and</strong>ing that rigid abstract laws be<br />

mechanically applied to particular situations (45–47). Kant’s insistence on a<br />

pure theory of morals seems to rule judgment out of court, since the latter<br />

takes experience as its object. However, Höffe argues that we encounter moral<br />

situations not immediately as instances of universal laws; rather, individual<br />

instances must be made intelligible as “an instantiation of the universal” moral<br />

law with practical judgment (51). Experience, then, is essential to moral <strong>and</strong><br />

political situations in order to refine our ability to deploy the right law at the<br />

right time, place, <strong>and</strong> setting, but we must not allow the complexities of experience<br />

to obstruct our duty to the moral law.<br />

With this defense <strong>and</strong> refinement of Kant’s moral philosophy,<br />

Höffe paves the way for grounding political right on the moral good in part II.<br />

A cursory glance at the Metaphysics of Morals <strong>and</strong> his political essays reveals<br />

that Kant explicitly connects political right with the categorical imperative, the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!