04.03.2014 Views

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

5 4 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

risk of being glib, suffice to say that he under-appreciates the dignity of natural<br />

goodness because he neglects the importance of strength vs. weakness in<br />

Rousseau’s thinking on morality. Both goodness <strong>and</strong> virtue are legitimately<br />

“moral”, but the latter implies moral strength whereas the former does not.<br />

Cladis needlessly complicates matters by using terms <strong>and</strong> categories<br />

which are not Rousseau’s. This is most obviously so when he replaces<br />

nature vs. convention with private vs. public, <strong>and</strong> gives the latter a significance<br />

it does not have for Rousseau. It is also so vis-à-vis his above-mentioned<br />

“Weberian ideal types.” Whatever limited assistance “The Flourishing City,”<br />

“The Garden,”“The Solitary,” etc. may provide in the good fight against rightstalk,<br />

in the attempt to underst<strong>and</strong> Rousseau, they obscure much more than<br />

they clarify. Again, Cladis freely admits they are made up, <strong>and</strong> they do not all<br />

represent grievous misunderst<strong>and</strong>ings of Rousseau, but, for one simply interested<br />

in what Rousseau thinks, they mislead. Cladis fears he will be accused of<br />

systematizing the fundamentally unsystematic thought of Rousseau, but the<br />

problem is much simpler: his types combine things which do not belong<br />

together <strong>and</strong> separate things which do. As we know from contemporary experience<br />

with postmodern scholars <strong>and</strong> as the early moderns knew from their<br />

experience with the scholastics, inventing new terms without giving adequate<br />

justification for their necessity is usually unsound policy in philosophy.<br />

To his credit, Cladis recognizes the importance of the superficial<br />

contradictions in Rousseau’s thought (9–10). He underst<strong>and</strong>s that, not<br />

only are they intentional, part of a larger teaching, but also that they show the<br />

way to Rousseau’s most valuable insights. But one need not conclude from this<br />

that, at his deepest level, Rousseau is fundamentally unsystematic (xii, 9, 230),<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus a partisan of dividedness, not wholeness. Another approach is possible,<br />

such as is pursued by Arthur Melzer in his remarkable book The Natural<br />

Goodness of Man: On the System of Rousseau’s Thought (Melzer 1990). Melzer,<br />

too, appreciates the pedagogical <strong>and</strong> rhetorical purpose of Rousseau’s contradictions,<br />

but he makes discoveries Cladis does not because he stresses the<br />

fundamentally “systematic” character of Rousseau’s thought (such as, for<br />

example, the absolute centrality of the sweet sentiment of existence for<br />

Rousseau). In our jaded, postmodern times, we forget that it is not such an easy<br />

task to develop a system, a theory of the (human) whole convincing in its unity<br />

<strong>and</strong> comprehensiveness. Eighteenth-century systematizing undoubtedly had<br />

its excesses, but without some sort of systematic spirit, philosophy runs the risk<br />

of being inconsistent, parochial or both.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!