04.03.2014 Views

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

Beyond Struggle and Power: Heidegger's Secret ... - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Book Review: An Islamic Philosophy of Virtuous Religions<br />

4 3<br />

seem to be included as a demonstration that Plato <strong>and</strong> Aristotle agree with<br />

each other <strong>and</strong> that both concur with Alfarabi. Parens believes this is a ruse.<br />

What Alfarabi is actually offering is a demonstration that all three of the<br />

philosophers fail to apprehend theoretical knowledge; each of the three intentionally<br />

shows the limits of human knowledge <strong>and</strong> the resulting absence of<br />

grounds for philosophers’ ruling society. I like the way Charles Butterworth<br />

<strong>and</strong> Thomas Pangle describe this as a “charade of speaking as if it were the serious<br />

purpose of political philosophy to rule directly over a (new) political<br />

order…He has intended to arouse the shocked wonder <strong>and</strong> hence thought of a<br />

few readers while allowing most to believe, in self-congratulatory fashion, in<br />

political philosophy as a wildly impractical castle-building-in-Spain” (Alfarabi<br />

2002, xi). This conclusion is the basis of Parens’ first <strong>and</strong> second “waves,” <strong>and</strong><br />

here Parens agrees with Christopher Colmo’s conclusions in Breaking With<br />

Athens (Colmo 2005)—absolute truth is inaccessible, the virtuous city is pie in<br />

the sky, <strong>and</strong> the important quality in real life governance is prudence or practical<br />

wisdom. There is a difference, though. While Colmo convincingly draws<br />

our attention to the force of practical wisdom, Parens reminds us that Alfarabi<br />

also values the quest for wisdom. “Alfarabi’s persistent shattering of our hopes<br />

for certainty is not intended to destroy our love of wisdom” (118).“We must be<br />

careful to avoid falling into an unlimited form of skepticism. At a minimum,<br />

political philosophy is up to the task of recognizing the limits of human knowledge.<br />

It is fully capable of warning us of the dangers of presupposing greater<br />

knowledge than we possess” (115). This aspect of Parens’ argument is perhaps<br />

best supported by Parens’ own description of his interpretation of Alfarabi’s<br />

intention as “a cross between a st<strong>and</strong>ard <strong>and</strong> a cautionary tale” (11).<br />

One of the intriguing aspects of Alfarabi’s writings is his penchant<br />

for ranking. Souls, causes, beings, religions, <strong>and</strong> cities are sorted from<br />

first to last, highest to lowest, most true to least true, most virtuous to most<br />

base. But if, as Parens’ Alfarabi contends, there is no certainty of the “First<br />

Cause” or of the most virtuous regime, then causes or regimes cannot be<br />

ranked in descending order from them. So why bother? It is possible that rankings<br />

are there to demonstrate the arrogance behind such an exercise. But it is<br />

also possible that Alfarabi is saying what he claims to be saying (granted, this<br />

would be unusual for Alfarabi), i.e., that there are some qualitative differences<br />

among personal lives <strong>and</strong> regimes (existing <strong>and</strong> theoretical). Only a relativist<br />

would not see at least some degree of qualitative difference between Hitler’s<br />

regime <strong>and</strong> Winston Churchill’s, for example, <strong>and</strong> Parens has argued that<br />

Alfarabi is a promoter of wisdom in spite of its limitations <strong>and</strong> not a relativist.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!