04.03.2014 Views

May 1983 - Interpretation

May 1983 - Interpretation

May 1983 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

A JOURNAL OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY<br />

<strong>May</strong><br />

<strong>1983</strong> Volume 1 1 Number 2<br />

139 Arlene W.<br />

Saxonhouse<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War<br />

171 Mary Pollingue<br />

Nichols<br />

The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition:<br />

Aristotle's Introduction to Politics<br />

1 85 Catherine Zuckert Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of<br />

Political Life<br />

207 Timothy Fuller<br />

Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice<br />

in The Tempest<br />

225 Jeffrey Barnouw<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, and<br />

its Background in Bacon and Hobbes<br />

249 Robert Sacks<br />

The Lion and the Ass: a<br />

Commentary<br />

on the Book of Genesis (Chapters 35-37)


JL JL A i^\to^ JL<br />

w*~J JL \*^f i^C^L l^JL v_^JL JL<br />

Volume ii J number 2<br />

Editor-in-Chief<br />

Hilail Gildin<br />

Editors Seth G. Benardete Hilail Gildin Robert Horwitz<br />

Howard B. White (d.1974)<br />

Consulting<br />

Editors John Hallowell Wilhelm Hennis Erich Hula<br />

Arnaldo Momigliano Michael Oakeshott Ellis<br />

Sandoz Leo Strauss (d.1973) Kenneth W.<br />

Thompson<br />

Associate Editors Larry Arnhart Patrick Coby Christopher A. Colmo<br />

Maureen Feder Joseph E. Goldberg Pamela<br />

Jensen Will Morrisey Bradford Wilson<br />

Assistant Editors Marianne C. Grey Laurette G. Hupman<br />

Design & Production<br />

Martyn Hitchcock<br />

Authors submitting manuscripts for publication in<br />

interpretation are requested to follow the MLA<br />

Style Sheet and to send clear and readable copies<br />

of their work. All manuscripts and editorial correspon<br />

dence should be addressed to interpretation,<br />

Queens College, Flushing, N.Y. 11367, U.S.A.<br />

Copyright <strong>1983</strong><br />

<strong>Interpretation</strong>


guest."'<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War<br />

Arlene W.<br />

University of Michigan<br />

Saxonhouse<br />

The Gorgias has since Hellenistic times had the subtitle Peri Rhetorikes.<br />

The dialogue has thus stood as the classic Platonic analysis of rhetoric, specif<br />

ically rhetoric as contrasted with and sometimes similar to philosophy. My<br />

argument is that the analysis of the dialogue must be extended to what I call<br />

its unspoken theme, that which lies behind the action and the discourse of the<br />

dialogue, war. In the background of this dialogue stands the Peloponnesian<br />

War and particularly Thucydides' account of that war. Within the dialogue,<br />

the central character, Callicles, stands for Athens, giving<br />

expression to the<br />

assumptions behind Athenian politics and revealing at the same time the inherent<br />

inconsistencies of her politics of international expansion. Both rhetoric and war<br />

express the search for domination which comes from the erotic longing for<br />

more.<br />

Philosophy as practiced by<br />

Socrates is also an eros driven activity.<br />

The dialogue contrasts the search for fulfilment and in the process offers the<br />

Platonic response to Thucydides'<br />

history of the war,<br />

as it forces us to reflect<br />

upon the relationship between rhetoric, war and philosophy. The following<br />

analysis of the Gorgias will thus of necessity interweave Socratic discourse<br />

with Thucydidean narrative and speech.<br />

"Of war and of battle, they say, so is it necessary to have a share, O<br />

Socrates."<br />

These are the first words of Gorgias. They are spoken by Callicles<br />

to Socrates and Socrates' companion, Chaerephon, as they<br />

arrive after<br />

Gorgias'<br />

rhetorical display has ended. Socrates recognizes the adage and responds: "But<br />

then, as the saying goes, we have come after the feast and arrive late" (447a).<br />

The sentiments here expressed, as numerous editors of the Gorgias have let us<br />

know, are worthy of Shakespeare's Falstaff, who in Henry IV, Part I, expresses<br />

much the same thought: "The latter end of a fray and the beginning<br />

of a feast /<br />

Fits a dull fighter and a keen<br />

Unlike Falstaff, however, whose trepi<br />

dation in the face of battles can provide much comic counterpoint to the story<br />

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 1980 American Political Science Asso<br />

ciation Meetings in Washington, D.C. I am indebted to the reviewers for this journal for several<br />

helpful points and to a most thoughtful letter from Robert Eden.<br />

1. Act IV, scene 3. While it may make sense to arrive late for a battle, it hardly makes sense<br />

to arrive late for a war. Thus, the appearance of this word right at the beginning of the dialogue<br />

in a somewhat awkward usage should immediately<br />

alert us to its significance. Newhall Barker of<br />

The Dramatic and Mimetic Features of<br />

the<br />

"Gorgias"<br />

of Plato (Baltimore: Isaac Friedenwald,<br />

1891), p. 31, comments on the "artistic placing of the first word, polemou, which indicates the<br />

nature of the dialogue" but does not proceed to tell us in what way it does so.


agora,"<br />

140 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

of kings, Socrates is neither fearful of battles nor overanxious for feasts. The<br />

Symposium, for one, records his reluctance to hasten to feasts (174a, d)2 and,<br />

through the medium of Alcibiades' speech, Socrates' courage in battle. As be<br />

comes evident later in the Gorgias, Socrates neither avoids battles, sparring<br />

with words, nor eagerly<br />

to offer<br />

him.3<br />

awaits the verbal feasts which Polus and Gorgias are<br />

ready<br />

The ostensible cause of Socrates' tardy arrival is Chaerephon,<br />

friend. "He is responsible (aitios); he forced us to spend time in the<br />

Socrates'<br />

explains Socrates (447a). What Socrates does not explain is how Chaerephon<br />

could have forced Socrates to do anything. Had Socrates been eager to hear<br />

Gorgias, it is unlikely he would have allowed Chaerephon to restrain him. But<br />

Chaerephon as the cause of his late arrival has other connotations ,<br />

if we<br />

keep<br />

in mind the story told in the Apology about Chaerephon's trip<br />

to the oracle at<br />

Delphi. We do know, however, that Chaerephon is given to great enthusiams.<br />

In the Charmides, his welcome to a Socrates just returning from the battle at<br />

Potideia is described by Socrates as reaching<br />

almost manic proportions<br />

(153b).4<br />

In the comedies of his time, his anemia and squeaky voice are intended to<br />

study.5<br />

reflect a man<br />

overly<br />

addicted to However, Chaerephon's enthusiasm for<br />

Socrates and for study does not preclude an interest in political things. In the<br />

Charmides, with great enthusiasm, he inquires of an indifferent Socrates the<br />

details surrounding the battle of Potideia, and indeed it is he who seats Socrates<br />

in the dialogue next to the future tyrant Critias. Nor does Chaerephon's en<br />

thusiasm for Socrates preclude other friends or prospective teachers. Though<br />

Philostratus records the insolent questioning<br />

of Gorgias by a Chaerephon,6 in<br />

the Gorgias, Chaerephon describes himself as<br />

friendly (philos)<br />

with Gorgias<br />

(447b). For this reason he will be able "to heal" the situation, the missed per<br />

formance, and have Gorgias for friendship's sake give Socrates a demonstra<br />

tion, if not today, then tomorrow.<br />

While Chaerephon is friendly with Gorgias, his association does not equal<br />

that of Callicles, for it is with Callicles that Gorgias is staying while in Athens.<br />

Callicles is gracious, and he invites Socrates and Chaerephon to visit him at<br />

any time to talk with Gorgias. But we do not wait for "whenever" (447b) for<br />

Socrates to talk with Gorgias. Rather, Socrates is eager to begin the questioning<br />

2. At the beginning<br />

of the Republic the promise of a feast is not enough to bribe Socrates to<br />

stay in the Piraeus. There must be as well the promise of discourse with young<br />

novel torch race (328a).<br />

men and of a<br />

3. Throughout the dialogue there is the leitmotif of Gorgias' and Polus' speeches as feasts<br />

(e.g., 447a and the elaborate comparison of a rhetor with a cook in Socrates' speech, 46^-4656).<br />

4. See Christopher Bruell, "Socratic Politics and Self-knowledge: An <strong>Interpretation</strong> of Plato's<br />

Charmides,"<br />

<strong>Interpretation</strong>, 6 (1977), 142; also<br />

Apology 21a.<br />

5. Philostratus, Lives of the Sophists, 483. E. R. Dodds,<br />

"Introduction,"<br />

Plato's "Gorgias"<br />

(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1959). P- 6, provides a list of the various comedies in which Chaerephon<br />

appears.<br />

6. Philostratus 483.


person.10<br />

When<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 141<br />

immediately. Thus the conversation takes place in an undefined space. All we<br />

are told is that it is within (endon, 447c). It is within this indefinite space that<br />

the interlocutors will try, not always successfully, to speak freely, to exercise<br />

their parrhesia (46ie, 487a, b) and it is within this space that Gorgias sits<br />

oracle-like, promising to answer any questions put to him by<br />

those who are<br />

eager, after Gorgias' display, to hear more and to test the apparent universal<br />

wisdom of this man who could stand in the theater at Athens and have the<br />

courage to say "Do you propose a theme."7 As at Delphi, Chaerephon, ex<br />

plicitly this time at the prompting of Socrates, is to ask the question which leads<br />

to Socrates' subsequent investigations. Thus the Gorgias, through Chaerephon's<br />

initial question and subsequent enthusiasm for the questioning<br />

of a pompous<br />

man before others (485c), becomes in abbreviated form the life which Socrates<br />

led after the fateful questioning<br />

of the oracle of Apollo. The undefined locale<br />

of the Gorgias becomes the setting for the trial of Socrates, where, as in the<br />

Apology, he attacks the values of Athens, its goals and the grounds on which<br />

it bases its actions. At the end of the dialogue, as in the Apology, he will talk<br />

about death, that which gives the final lie to the achievements of politics, a<br />

world of bodies and based on opinion.8<br />

Among the participants in the dialogue, Callicles is the one Platonic char<br />

acter, clearly identified by deme, Acharnia, who remains elusive,<br />

unnoted in<br />

any<br />

other ancient source. The other characters of the dialogue are known.<br />

who believed<br />

Gorgias is the famous orator and teacher from Leontini in Sicily<br />

that because of the limits of human reason, speech had more power over the<br />

soul than physical force or drugs could have over the body.9 Speech properly<br />

employed could be a magical potion capable of<br />

controlling individuals and<br />

cities. As we shall see, it is not the beauty of Gorgias' speech that attracts the<br />

youth who follow him to Callicles' house. It is a desire to learn his craft, not<br />

for its own sake, but for the power which it promises to one who possesses<br />

it. Polus is also from Sicily, but from the most prosperous and fair city<br />

of<br />

Agrigentum. Less famous and younger than Gorgias, he is known in antiquity<br />

as the author of a work entitled Techne, and is the recipient of somewhat<br />

scornful mention in the Phaedrus (267bc). Yet, it is Callicles who begins the<br />

dialogue, whose name signals its conclusion, whose grand speech provides the<br />

central, pivotal point in the dialogue. I myself have no doubt that Callicles was<br />

a real<br />

quite anonymous.<br />

Plato wants characters to remain unidentified<br />

they remain<br />

One can speculate on who Callicles was, as Dodds does, and then why he<br />

remains so elusive to modern researchers. His deme gives us some clues:<br />

7. Philostratus 482.<br />

8. Even Pericles who strives to give his city immortality<br />

historian Thucydides with his words who must do this.<br />

9. Gorgias, Encomium on Helen 11.<br />

10. See Dodds. p. 12.<br />

(Thucydides 11.43. 2) cannot; it is the


142 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Acharnia, a thickly populated area north of Athens, suffered heavily in the first<br />

invasion of the Peloponnesians and the Acharnians "were for that reason deter<br />

mined to fight a war of revenge to a successful He thus conclusion."11<br />

comes<br />

from an area in which the aggressive prosecution of the Peloponnesian war is<br />

approved. His beloved gives us other clues: Demos, the son of Pyrilampos, ties<br />

Callicles to the leaders of Athens and to Plato.12 Dodds suggests an<br />

early death<br />

for this outspoken young man of the dialogue, but his insignificance perhaps<br />

also underscores the inability of the Athenians themselves to accept openly the<br />

expression of the ideas behind their actions in relation to other cities. Such<br />

language could only be part of conversations within houses, in the councils of<br />

government leaders, or in the works of exiled historians.13 Callicles may have<br />

been too ready to exercise his Athenian parrhesia publicly<br />

as well as privately.<br />

But perhaps Callicles is more than a real person who failed to become part<br />

of the standard discourse of the fifth and fourth centuries B.C. I would like<br />

to raise the question of whether Callicles with his grand speech<br />

defending the<br />

right of the stronger could indeed be Athens, Athens from 431 to 404, ex<br />

pressing in words the values which the Athenians try to defend in their deeds<br />

during the Peloponnesian War.14 He shows the same indifference to Socrates'<br />

counter-arguments which the Athenians showed to Socrates' questioning and<br />

similarly refuses to engage in the dialogue Socrates seeks on questions of the<br />

good life and the differences between real and false pleasures.<br />

Athens is at war. In 431, the forty-eighth year of the priestess-ship of<br />

Chrysis at Argos, in the Ephorate of Aenesias at Sparta, six months after the<br />

battle of Potideia, the Lacedaemonians break their thirty-year treaty<br />

with Athens<br />

after only<br />

fourteen years and invade Attica. The war between the two great<br />

powers of Greece has begun. The war will devastate much of Greece and signal<br />

the end of what we know as the glory of Hellas. The Athenians, as Thucydides<br />

has led us to believe, are<br />

fighting to protect the empire they<br />

acquired after the<br />

Persian Wars, while the Spartans fight from a fear of the expansion of Athenian<br />

power. The first year of the war is uneventful. The Thebans attack Plataea; the<br />

Lacedaemonians ravage the farms in the plains of Attica; Pericles speaks words<br />

of praise for Athens as he commemorates the Athenian dead. The next year, the<br />

11. K. J. Dover, Aristophanic Comedy (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University<br />

Press, 1972), p. 79.<br />

12. Plutarch, Lives. Pericles 13.<br />

of California<br />

13. Terrence Irwin, Plato's "Gorgias", translated with notes (Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Clarendon Plato Series, 1979), p.<br />

that aggression by<br />

powerful states is all With<br />

175 asks: "How many would be shocked by Callicles' claim<br />

reference to Thucydides, he makes two<br />

points, "(1) Thucydides may be reporting, not what the Athenians actually say of themselves,<br />

but only what would be rational<br />

it is just and fine to do what<br />

they do."<br />

14. Cf. 492d.<br />

to<br />

say,"<br />

and "(2) Even Thucydides' speakers do not say


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 143<br />

war continues and the plague strikes. Pericles is fined and then voted back<br />

into office.<br />

Shortly afterwards, Pericles is dead (503c).*<br />

Some years later, around 427, while the war still rages, extending<br />

now to<br />

northern and western Greece, and while the Athenian subjects become restless<br />

and some, such as the Mitylenians, begin to rebel, Gorgias from Leontini visits<br />

Athens for the first time.* His mission is not to teach the art of rhetoric nor to<br />

display his talent before the crowds. Rather, he comes to Athens as an envoy<br />

for his city, requesting that the Athenians fulfill their treaty obligations and help<br />

the Ionian Leontines against the threatening Syracusans, allies of Sparta. His<br />

prose speech, of an elegance unheard before in the assembly, fascinates the<br />

Athenians,15<br />

but scholars differ in their assessment of his success.16<br />

In 422, as the war continues in the north and both sides begin to feel warweary,<br />

a young man named Demos, the son of Pyrilampos, was of such an age<br />

and<br />

beauty to become the beloved of an older man.* There follows shortly the<br />

Peace of Nicias, giving both sides in the war several years of respite from<br />

battle. But during this time another young<br />

man who had shown his courage in<br />

the battles of Delium and Potideia comes to dominate the Athenian political<br />

and social world. He secures for Athens alliances with the formerly pro-Spartan<br />

Argos, Mantineia,<br />

and Elis. He wins an unprecedented number of victories at<br />

the Olympic games. He parades adorned<br />

luxuriously through the city<br />

and he<br />

makes Eros with a thunderbolt his heraldic design. He spends time with and is<br />

in the awkward position of<br />

trying to seduce Socrates at the same time as being<br />

his beloved.* He, who speaks with a lisp, so scorned by Callicles (485b),<br />

persuades the Athenians to venture to Sicily and presents them with visions of<br />

great conquests extending even beyond the island of Sicily itself, on to Carthage<br />

and Libya. "We are told that Socrates the philosopher and Meton the astrologer<br />

did not believe that any good would come to the city from this venture. Socrates<br />

may have received a premonition of the future from his familiar guardian<br />

spirit."17<br />

But Alcibiades is not among those who die in the forests or salt mines<br />

of Sicily. He instead uses his artful speech to persuade and enchant the Spartans,<br />

urging them to send help to Syracuse and thus ensure the Athenian debacle in<br />

Sicily.<br />

Meanwhile in Macedonia, Archelaus, a slave to the king's brother, has<br />

murdered his master and his master's son, thrown the king's son down a well<br />

(47ia-d) and taken control of the kingdom.* Soon afterwards Archelaus be<br />

comes an ally of the Athenians, praised by<br />

them as a good man who acted with<br />

*A11 the events marked with an asterisk are described as<br />

having happened recently or being<br />

contemporaneous with the dialogue.<br />

15. Diodorus Siculus, xn.53.<br />

16. Compare for example the assessments in F. E. Adcock, "The Archidamian War, 431-421<br />

B.C.,"<br />

The Cambridge Ancient History (Cambridge: University Press, 1927), V, p. 223, and A. F.<br />

Woodhead, The Greeks in the West (New York: Praeger, 1962), p. 83.<br />

17. Plutarch, Lives. Alcibiades 17.


144 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

enthusiasm to do whatever good he was able to do.18 Poets such as Euripides<br />

and Agathon spend time at his court. Socrates is invited, but refuses the invita<br />

tion.19<br />

Archelaus earns the praise of Thucydides: "On his accession he cut<br />

straight roads, and otherwise put the kingdom on a better footing<br />

as regards<br />

horses, heavy infantry, and other material than had been done by<br />

all the eight<br />

kings that had preceded him" (ii. 100.2). For the Athenians, he supplies the<br />

wood for the ship building on which their naval power is built. By the year<br />

399, the year in which Socrates is to be executed by the citizens of Athens,<br />

Archelaus will be dead, murdered at the hands of one of his countrymen, his<br />

beloved.20<br />

In 411 b.c, with the war now<br />

extending<br />

eastward to the coast of Asia<br />

Minor and Alcibiades back in favor in Athens, Euripides' play Antiope is per<br />

formed.* The twin sons of Antiope and Zeus are brought up by a shepherd and<br />

each turns to a different vocation; Amphion devotes himself to music, able to<br />

move stones with his lyre, Zethus turns to hunting and the care of his flocks,<br />

that is, to the acquisition of more and to the tending of what is already his<br />

own. On stage<br />

they<br />

debate the advantages of each life. Meanwhile, the war<br />

continues, Athens' government changing from democracy to oligarchy and back<br />

again. Aristocrates, a friend of Callicles,* and a member of the oligarchic Four<br />

Hundred, is part of an expedition to Arguinusae in 406 B.C. The Athenians<br />

win, but the generals, hindered by a storm and the confusion following the<br />

battle, fail to pluck the living and the dead from the ocean. The generals, among<br />

them Aristocrates, are tried upon their return to Athens.* Socrates, one of the<br />

prytanes in charge of the assembly on the day that they are to be tried, protests<br />

that the combined trial of all the generals is against the law,* but to no avail.<br />

The generals, including Aristocrates, are executed. Two years later, the war is<br />

over.<br />

The dialogue thus appears to take place<br />

during<br />

the timespan of the entire<br />

war. Some have suggested that the anachronisms give the dialogue a certain<br />

timelessness. Perhaps just the opposite is true. Perhaps they<br />

have the effect of<br />

giving the dialogue a certain timeliness, that is a close association with the war<br />

that dominates Athenian political and artistic life for these twenty-eight years.<br />

An understanding of the characters in the dialogue and their arguments cannot<br />

be disassociated from the political circumstances surrounding the dialogue,<br />

especially considering the frequency<br />

events are made throughout.<br />

with which references to precise political<br />

At the same time the political references tie the dialogue to the time period<br />

of the war, they also underscore the fictitious nature of the dialogue. This<br />

dialogue could never have taken place and perhaps this has something to do<br />

18. Dodds, p. 241.<br />

19. Aristotle, The Art of Rhetoric, I398a24. The excuse which Socrates gave<br />

according to<br />

Aristotle was "hubris." Whose, it is not clear.<br />

20. Alcibiades ii, I4id.


An Unspoken Theme in Plato' s Gorgias: War 145<br />

with Callicles' own elusiveness. Is he or is he not real? But the ahistoricity of<br />

the dialogue is important in itself. Thucydides'<br />

history<br />

of the war was tied to the<br />

events and speeches of the war, the details out of which an understanding of<br />

that war could emerge. Plato, the philosopher, not an historian, offers a fictional<br />

dialogue to explain the war to reveal its premises and underscore its vanity.<br />

The ahistorical dialogue, the dialogue which is impossible, certainly because of<br />

the timing but perhaps also because of the characters involved, suggests the<br />

necessity to diverge from what we would today call the facts of history<br />

to that<br />

truth which lies more fully in the fictions of Platonic dialogues than in the<br />

researches of any history.<br />

Polus comes from a city of such wealth that everyday household articles are<br />

fashioned out of gold and silver, and of such beauty that Pindar describes it as<br />

"glorious", a gods,"<br />

"lofty city lavish above all in the gifts to the "the very<br />

eye<br />

of Sicily."21 Why Polus has joined Gorgias on his mission to Athens we are not<br />

told. His city is not pleading for Athenian aid. His city stands as one of the<br />

glories of Sicily, one of the few cities able to remain neutral during the Sicilian<br />

campaign. But that day<br />

when Athenian ships enter Syracuse's waters is far off<br />

when Gorgias arrives in Athens with Polus tagging<br />

along. And while we do not<br />

known why Polus comes to Athens, we do know why he follows Gorgias; he<br />

is eager for power, for the power which rhetoric gives, and he is assured by<br />

Gorgias that the way to get power in the rhetoric.22<br />

city is to learn the art of<br />

It is Polus' urge for power that drives him to follow Gorgias, that keeps him<br />

in close attendance to Gorgias, so that one day perhaps he may do more than<br />

simply articulate the role of rhetoric, that he may some day indeed exercise the<br />

power which rhetoric promises.<br />

Gorgias tries to define rhetoric for a Socrates eager to discover what pre<br />

cisely is its power, this power which Polus so earnestly seeks. Gorgias says it<br />

is the greatest good (megiston agathon) for human beings (anthropois, 452d).<br />

Presumably he means only some humans, those who know how to use it. It is<br />

good, because it is the cause (aition) of freedom (eleutheria) for humans. Again<br />

we must interpolate "some humans," because the freedom for some as it is<br />

developed in the next phrase by Gorgias does not mean for all, but the freedom<br />

to rule over others in the Gorgias does city.23 not acknowledge that the freedom<br />

21. Kathleen Freeman, Greek City-States (New York: W. W. Norton, 1963), p. 64; Pindar,<br />

Olympian Odes 11.6-10, and in. 2; and Frag. 1922.2.<br />

22. The word for power which runs through the dialogue is he dunamis; it is beyond my<br />

capacity at this point even to count how many times dunamis and rhetoric are conjoined in the first<br />

half of the dialogue. Only a reading of the dialogue with attention to this point would reveal<br />

the intensity of the usage of this term. Cf. Gorgias in the Encomium on Helen (paragraph 8)<br />

where he describes logos as the greatest dunastes, and comments that though logos has the smallest<br />

body<br />

and is least visible, it accomplishes the most divine erga.<br />

23. Cp. Diodotus' speech in Thucydides, in.45. 6.


146 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

for the rhetorician which he and Polus so praise means in turn slavery for<br />

someone else. The free person in Greece is not only<br />

the one who is not ruled<br />

over<br />

by others, but the one who rules over others, who turns others into slaves.<br />

Gorgias, confirming the power (dunamis) of rhetoric to Socrates, shows how<br />

the rhetorician can make slaves of other artisans. "With this dunamis, you<br />

will be able to make the doctor into a slave (doulon), the trainer into a slave<br />

(doulon)"<br />

(542e). Gorgias envisions that such a power to enslave others will<br />

be used for benign purposes, to persuade a sick man to listen to medical ad<br />

vice, or an assembly<br />

of Athenians to listen to the advice of a Pericles or a<br />

Themistocles, that the slave, whoever he or she may be, will benefit from the<br />

control of his or her master.<br />

ing<br />

Polus is not so benign in his visions of the power of rhetoric,<br />

which accord<br />

to him has the greatest power in the cities (megiston dunatai en tais<br />

the artisan<br />

polesin, 466b). He, unlike Gorgias, does not talk about enslaving<br />

to do good deeds. The man he envies, after whom he wishes to model himself,<br />

is the tyrant of Macdeonia. Archelaus is indeed free and powerful now, a master<br />

rather than a slave. Once he was the mere son of a slave to a king. Now he<br />

as king has achieved complete liberty to do as he wishes. Yes, he committed<br />

many crimes to acquire this freedom, killed many people, deceived others, but<br />

now he must be truly happy, having exchanged slavery for freedom. If Socrates<br />

does not admit that he too envies Archelaus, he is simply being obstreperous.<br />

Surely, Archelaus can do whatever he wishes in the city, he can take away his<br />

subjects'<br />

property, he can send them into exile, he can kill them, all without<br />

the fear of punishment. He has moved from a slave himself to one who makes<br />

slaves of others. Archelaus did not acheive this status through the art of rhetoric,<br />

but the effective use of speech can accomplish as much. Polus wishes to follow<br />

Archelaus'<br />

example; now, Polus is no more than a servant to Gorgias, answer<br />

ing Gorgias' questions for him when Gorgias is tired. Polus yearns for a life<br />

very different, when he no longer answers questions addressed to other people,<br />

when he has power, that is when he is free to do what he wants, when he wants<br />

and how he wants.<br />

Polus'<br />

vision is limited in many ways but the one which concerns us most is<br />

that it is limited by the walls of the city. The power he and indeed Gorgias as<br />

well search for is a power that remains within the city.24<br />

envision is a mastery over fellow citizens, a mastery<br />

The mastery they<br />

possible through words.<br />

They do not deal with mastery over other states, nor the mastery which Gorgias'<br />

mission is intended to avert from Leontini. As Thucydides' history so vividly<br />

shows, in this realm the most elegant speeches have no effect. When Gorgias<br />

had talked about the greatest power, rhetoric, he had talked about Pericles' and<br />

24. Despite the fact that Gorgias is on a mission<br />

concerning relations between states, he<br />

ignores the power of speech to influence cities as a whole. He sees only<br />

parts within a city.<br />

Could this be a sign that those scholars who assess his mission as a failure are correct? See pre<br />

ceding n. 16.


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 147<br />

Themistocles'<br />

feats: they<br />

persuaded the Athenians to build walls and to build<br />

the harbor. What Gorgias leaves out in reference to both of these men is, of<br />

course, their role in the incredible expansion of Athenian hegemony, of the<br />

freedom Athenians exercised after the Persian Wars to enslave the islands of<br />

the Aegean, to take their resources in order to build up the free Athens, the<br />

dunastes or tyrannos of the Aegean. The power which Polus envies is rather a<br />

power which is exercised exclusively<br />

within the<br />

city.25<br />

Polus ignores those<br />

activities of Archelaus which strengthened the status of Macadeonia vis-a-vis<br />

the cities of Greece, his success in expanding Macedonian trade, in increasing<br />

Macedonia's allies, and in Hellenizing the barbarian state.<br />

Because Polus' understanding<br />

of power and political events is confined to<br />

relationships within the city, he can be, as Callicles points out so well, manipu<br />

lated by Socrates into confusion over what is natural and what is conventional.<br />

He functions within the city and his values are those of men within the city. He<br />

envies the actions of Archelaus, but he cannot call them good (kalon); he must<br />

call them shameful (aischron). He is trapped by the conflict between nature<br />

and convention, arguing that Archelaus' actions make him as an individual<br />

happy, but admitting that by convention, by the traditional values of the city,<br />

they are not good. Because he is limited by the perspective of the city, he<br />

cannot separate what exists by<br />

nature and what exists by convention; it is only<br />

once he leaves the city, once he can break away from the laws of the city that<br />

he can distinguish between the two. Within the city nomos is the same as physis;<br />

the laws of justice and injustice are not<br />

easily disregarded or dismissed (474cd).<br />

The praise of the person who disregards the nomoi flounders under Socrates'<br />

questioning which does indeed shift back and forth, as Callicles claims, from<br />

nomos to physis and back to nomos again.26<br />

Gorgias and Polus both become ashamed, as indeed they should when talking<br />

before men who are citizens, of their rejection of the traditional values of justice<br />

and virtue on which the city is built and according to which the city must<br />

function. Gorgias cannot take responsibility if rhetoric is used unjustly; Polus<br />

would use rhetoric to achieve unjust ends, but would not call the ends good.<br />

Callicles is the one who is willing to look outside the city, who is willing to<br />

disregard the traditional values totally and to look to a nature unlimited by the<br />

demands of the political community. He can envision a new meaning for justice,<br />

he can uphold a vision of inequality<br />

and the taking<br />

of what is not one's own.<br />

Callicles can look to the relationships between cities for the unconditioned<br />

motivations of human beings.27 Callicles sees himself as rising<br />

above the conflict<br />

between nature and convention so much so that he can unite the two concepts<br />

25. The use of the phrase en tais polesi is strikingly frequent in Polus' speech: 466a, b, d;<br />

467a (two times). Also Gorgias at 452d.<br />

26. E.g., 474c and the introduction of aischron (shameful) and 478a, b, d.<br />

27. See Arlene W. Saxonhouse. "Nature and Convention in Thucydides' History," Polity 10<br />

(1978), 461-487-


to,"<br />

148 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

in a startling<br />

new phrase "the law of<br />

nature"<br />

(nomos tes physeos, 483c), a<br />

law of inequality supported by nature herself, as seen among<br />

animals and most<br />

significantly among nations where the question of right (dike) is only<br />

spoken<br />

of, but not followed. The relations between cities and the inclination to war<br />

among states become the model which Callicles will use to justify the actions<br />

he would like to take within the city if he could. This is why Callicles within<br />

the structure of the dialogue must expand the limited perspective of the earlier<br />

interlocutors beyond the city walls and why<br />

as his own person he must cast<br />

aspersions on those who have succumbed to the verbal power of the Socratic<br />

dialectic .<br />

Polus, the skittish young colt, has arrogantly<br />

praised the life of the tyrant.<br />

He envies Archelaus' power, assumes that Socrates must too, and yet has just<br />

agreed that rhetoric must be used to bring the malefactor, whether he or she<br />

be friend or family, to justice and punishment and<br />

help the enemy<br />

who has<br />

committed an injustice escape punishment. Callicles asks Chaerephon as one<br />

who knows Socrates well: "Is Socrates serious or is he<br />

playing?"<br />

(481b).28<br />

Chaerephon who may be an enthusiastic follower of Socrates, but who is not<br />

necessarily known for his wit, believes (emoi men dokei) that Socrates is in<br />

deed very<br />

Callicles'<br />

most eager<br />

serious.29<br />

"Ask him<br />

yourself,"<br />

he urges Callicles, repeating exactly<br />

advice to Socrates earlier in the dialogue (447c). "By the gods, I am<br />

and so he does, adding that if what Socrates has said and Polus<br />

has agreed to is true, life would be turned upside down (anatetrammenos ,<br />

481c). Socrates does not at once answer the question posed to him. Instead, he<br />

talks of<br />

suffering and of love.<br />

"O Callicles, if people had not the same<br />

suffering (pathos), but there was<br />

a certain<br />

suffering for some men and another for others, and one of us suf<br />

fered (espaschen) a private suffering (idion ti pathos) different from others it<br />

would not be easy to demonstrate (epideixasthai) to another one's own suf<br />

fering (pathema). I say this knowing that I and you now happen to be suf<br />

fering (peponthotes) the same thing, both being in love with two beloveds. I<br />

Alcibiades the son of Clinias and Philosophy, you the demos of Athens and<br />

[Demos] the son of Pyrilampos" (48icd). The discourse between Callicles and<br />

Socrates is to begin from a similarity of experiences, from a<br />

companionship in<br />

suffering. The epistemic basis for the dialogue between Socrates and Callicles<br />

is not reason, but the pain which will<br />

keep surfacing in the subsequent dialogue.<br />

Their common pain or suffering is love, the sense of lack, of needfulness.<br />

The Symposium is the locus classicus for the relationship between suffering<br />

28. At the beginning of the dialogue, Callicles had also turned to Chaerephon to learn Socrates'<br />

state of mind. "Is Socrates eager (ephithumei) to hear Gorgias?" he asks (447b). Callicles appears<br />

to have difficulty confronting Socrates directly.<br />

29. This does not Callicles'<br />

necessarily mean that Chaerephon is correct. One cannot answer<br />

question without further consideration of the attempt<br />

by Euthyphro to bring his father to justice.


Symposium."<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 149<br />

and love.30 Surrounding Socrates' famed speech, there are the speeches of Ari<br />

stophanes and Alcibiades. While Socrates talks, through the person of Diotima,<br />

also of pain and of a<br />

longing to be satisfied, he envisions a final satisfaction,<br />

which, however, can only be reached by the separation of the soul from the<br />

needs of the body, by the soul's ascent to a vision of true beauty<br />

which exists<br />

independently of the body and provides the lover with a nonphysical immor<br />

tality (212a). The satisfaction of true love can occur only<br />

when the human<br />

being ceases to be bounded by the needs of the body; political life focused<br />

on human beings in their cities is centered on the activity<br />

of bodies in relation<br />

to one another bodies organized in varied units in the city, bodies which fight<br />

to preserve the existence of the city, bodies which must be housed, clothed and<br />

fed.31<br />

The suffering of the body which feels love, a lack of what is outside it,<br />

can only cease with the abstraction from body, not before. The suffering, in<br />

other words, can only cease when the human being becomes divine.<br />

The speeches of both Aristophanes and Alcibiades refuse to deny the needs<br />

of the body, refuse to accept a solution which abstracts from body as Socrates,<br />

appearing to be convinced by Diotima, seems willing to do. They emphasize<br />

the longing of the body, the pains which dominate the body as it tries to fulfill<br />

itself, to attain a physical<br />

immortality<br />

or at least a physical completion. Both<br />

speeches<br />

by Aristophanes and Alcibiades emphasize the relationship between<br />

love and suffering. Aristophanes' halves search, often fruitlessly, for their other<br />

half.<br />

Alcibiades'<br />

satisfaction with his life before the Athenian demos is ques<br />

tioned, made to seem<br />

lacking by the presence, the words, the music of his<br />

Socrates. Eros is disruptive. It does not let the lover live in happy self-satisfac<br />

tion; it forces her to seek to possess what is outside her, be it the demos of<br />

Athens, the Demos of Pryilampos, or the true beauty capable of perception<br />

only through the mind. Eros creates longing and the pain so evident in the<br />

language of Aristophanes and Alcibiades. Only Diotima offers a way out of that<br />

pain in the state of<br />

unity with the beautiful. But at that point, the lover is<br />

no longer human, no longer distinct from that which she longs after, from<br />

that which she loves. The lover in a sense has died and become one with her<br />

beloved, has become a god. To be human is to desire, to lack, to have eros.<br />

Callicles and Socrates are driven by these human desires; they both love and<br />

both suffer.<br />

they<br />

It is philosophy<br />

which will stand at the end of Socrates' speech as the test<br />

for the political Callicles. Callicles must respond to the consistency of philos<br />

ophy (482a), but he cannot. He makes arguments from politics, while Socrates<br />

makes arguments from philosophy, from the vision which Diotima held before<br />

him of an eternal, unchanging beauty, an eternal, unchanging truth. However,<br />

30. The analysis in this section owes a great deal to the article<br />

by Martha Nussbaum, "The<br />

Speech ot Alcibiades: A reading of Plato's<br />

131-172.<br />

31. Cf. Republic u.369-374d.<br />

Philosophy and Literature 3 (1979),


others.32<br />

150 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

the solution which Diotima offers takes humans away from their bodies and<br />

thus rejects the political. Aristophanes and Alcibiades, the consumately political<br />

men, each in their own way are tied to the body<br />

yearnings can never be satisfied.<br />

They continue engaging<br />

and thus tied to politics. Their<br />

in activities of the<br />

city<br />

as each searches for a physical completion which can never be achieved.<br />

Thus, the polis and the political<br />

being strike out on new ventures. If one of<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

halves does not find its mate in one person, it continues its<br />

search to the next hemisphere of appropriate sex, reaching forever to others for<br />

an unattainable completion. Alcibiades does not<br />

stay by Socrates; he is drawn<br />

by the love of praise, of wealth and other bodies. Athens, the tyrant of the<br />

Aegean, does not stay satisfied with power over her empire. She pursues more,<br />

drawn by the wealth and challenge of Sicily; she does not herself rest, nor does<br />

she give rest to<br />

Pericles tried during the war to make her whole, to<br />

have her cease her endless search for more, for the unattainable completion.33<br />

But the wholeness Pericles offers, as we shall see, is a completion which rises<br />

out of "human flesh and color and other mortal nonsense to a divine beauty"<br />

(21 1 e). Political men, the citizens and leaders of Athens, do not desire the<br />

satisfaction of nonphysical wants alone. Neither Callicles nor Polus wants the<br />

power to persuade in speech alone, the power over the opinions of others.<br />

They<br />

want that power so that they may have power over men's and women's bodies.<br />

They want to be able through their power in the city to satisfy<br />

and longings of their physical being.<br />

the varied wants<br />

Thucydides'<br />

History traces the effects of human passions on the relation<br />

ships between and within cities. The fear of Athens is what starts the war<br />

(whatever the prophases, excuses, may be). The desire for more drives the<br />

Athenians on to invade Sicily. Eros is there as well, not always<br />

fully articulated,<br />

yet motivating the actors in this greatest of upheavals. Pericles, praising Athens<br />

as he commemorates her dead, exhorts her citizens to become lovers (erastes) of<br />

Athens. "Feast your eyes on her each<br />

her lovers" (11.43. 1).<br />

Pericles'<br />

day,"<br />

he says to them, "until you become<br />

beautiful speech is intended to make Athens<br />

beautiful, capable of creating a longing, a passion for her, a passion which will<br />

make the Athenians forget themselves and think only of her, their beloved.34 It<br />

is through her that they will reach a condition of immortality, that they will be<br />

defined not<br />

by their bodies which die, but by the memories which will be their<br />

immortal sepulchres (11.43. 3). For Pericles, the city is what the beautiful is<br />

for Diotima. They both lift the individual out of her body and tie her to that<br />

32. Thucydides 1.70.9.<br />

33. Thucydides 11. 65.7).<br />

34. See Nussbaum, p. 156, on the role of the eromenos, the beloved, as an unmoving object<br />

to be desired, in Greek homosexuality. She effectively applies here the analysis of K. J. Dover,<br />

Greek Homosexuality (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1978), to the study of Platonic<br />

thought.


eromenos.^<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 151<br />

which will last forever; they both give human beings an immortality<br />

which was<br />

previously reserved for the gods; they both defy the limitations of the body, one<br />

through the political devotion of the citizen, the other through the inquiries of<br />

the philosopher.<br />

They<br />

stand in opposition in their struggle for the same goal.<br />

However, both Thucydides and Socrates show this love to be ultimately<br />

impossible. The Athenian erastes does not survive<br />

long beyond Pericles' speech.<br />

The abstract love of Athens, of her beauty, is hard to sustain once the plague<br />

strikes the bodies of the men and women in Athens. Pericles must make clear<br />

in his next speech why Athens is to be loved. It is no longer for the beauty of<br />

her politeia and the life she creates. These fade quickly before the physical<br />

traumas of war and illness. She is to be loved because she protects and satisfies<br />

the needs of the bodies of the individuals who comprise the city, because<br />

without her welfare the individual's welfare would be sacrificed. Individual<br />

good fortune is meaningless without the city to protect that fortune. The beauti<br />

ful Athens of the funeral oration becomes no more than a<br />

tyranny (11.63. 2)<br />

balancing hazardously<br />

between the complete domination of others and the po<br />

tential subjection to others. Eros for Athens the city, despite all of Pericles'<br />

verbal and physical efforts to beautify her, fails to provide the motivating force<br />

for the Athenians, and eros disappears from Thucydides' history. That is, it<br />

disappears until Book VI, until both Sicily<br />

desired, to become the<br />

Sicily]"<br />

and Alcibiades stand there to be<br />

"And eros fell on all alike to set sail [for<br />

(vi.24.3). The citizens, no longer pressed to love and desire some<br />

thing so abstract as a politeia, can desire something tangible, something which<br />

relates to their bodies and not to their minds alone: the wealth of Sicily and,<br />

indeed, the body of Alcibiades. The static condition of contemplation, or the<br />

eros satisfied, asked for by Pericles did not lead anywhere. Rather, the eros for<br />

bodies, for more, does; it leads to Sicily, the home of Polus and Gorgias.36<br />

It is precisely the eros for particulars that moves polities along. The Spartans,<br />

characterized by their hesuchia, their quiet, their moderation, their freedom<br />

from longing, stay within, become mired in their ways, lack adventure and<br />

allow others to grow while<br />

they remain still. The pain or suffering, the wanting<br />

of more which drives the Athenians to become an empire is what leads to their<br />

greatness, what makes their defeat worthy<br />

of the attention of the greatest his<br />

torian as the greatest event ever. The eunomia and passivity<br />

of the Spartans<br />

leaves them as still as stones or as dead as corpses (49e).37<br />

When Callicles speaks violently and forcefully in the middle of the Gorgias,<br />

35. It is interesting to note that it is in the same book as the decision to go to Sicily that<br />

Thucydides includes, totally out of context, the love story of Harmodius and Aristogeiton and<br />

shows how eros here influenced political events (vi. 55-59). (Words derivative from eros recur<br />

through these passages.)<br />

36. The relationship between Gorgias and Sicily is underscored in the dialogue by the Sicilisms<br />

used by Gorgias. I must rely here on the interpretation of others, e.g.. Barker, p. 3, who cites<br />

450b as an example pointed to by the scholiast Olympiodorus. Dodds, p. 196, is skeptical.<br />

37. For the above analysis, see the Corinthians' speech in Thucydides, 1. 68-71.


152 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

he speaks not of Athens, nor of Sparta; he speaks not of Potideia nor Corcyra,<br />

but of nature and the natural drive for more, for more than what one has, a<br />

drive which can only be restrained by the enchanting words of the weak, of<br />

the passive, those who do not have the strength of character to acquire more,<br />

to seek constantly to satisfy never-ending<br />

needs and desires. These are the<br />

many<br />

who for their own preservation must praise temperance. Callicles does<br />

not mention Sparta or Sicily or Athens, but the views he expresses remind us<br />

of the relationships between such states,<br />

relationships which have gone unnoted<br />

in the discourse of the earlier speakers and which now rise to the surface as<br />

the city is seen not only from within its walls, but as part of a larger world<br />

where the possibilities of wholeness and completion are even more limited.<br />

Callicles"<br />

grand speech in the middle of the dialogue bears a careful exami<br />

nation. It is complex, divided into two parts, and not at all times coherent or<br />

consistent. It comes in response to Socrates' speech about love; Socrates has<br />

talked about the suffering of the lover, the variability of the beloved (that<br />

is, all except philosophy) and the consequent variety<br />

and often irreconcilable<br />

demands beloveds place on their lovers. Only philosophy, Socrates claims, does<br />

not ask him to be discordant (asymphonon) with himself (482c). Callicles<br />

does not respond directly, just as Socrates did not respond to Callicles directly<br />

when Callicles had asked whether Socrates was serious in his arguments with<br />

Polus. Callicles ignores the speech about love. Perhaps here he thinks that<br />

Socrates is playing, whereas in fact, it may be here that Socrates is indeed<br />

most serious,<br />

since until we understand the nature of our loves and passions as<br />

human beings, and particularly<br />

of our sufferings which come from a sense of<br />

what is lacking; we shall never know whether our lives are to be turned upside<br />

down or not. Callicles instead focuses on two different kinds of suffering, not<br />

those that come from the physical lack of what one yearns for, but those that<br />

come from shame, from a shame derived from what Callicles sees as a false<br />

dichotomy between nature and convention, and the enslaving of free men.<br />

Callicles begins with an accusation: "O Socrates, you act like an insolent<br />

youth, but really you are not more than a demagogue" (482c). Socrates makes<br />

speeches to appeal to the many, to the demos which is the beloved of Callicles.<br />

Socrates is trying to subvert Callicles and transfer the demos to himself. Three<br />

times in the next few lines Callicles is to call Socrates a demagogue, but four<br />

times he accuses Socrates of making others suffer, of being the cause for pain.<br />

Callicles seems here, as indeed elsewhere in this speech, confused. The dema<br />

gogue strokes the beast so as to make it satisfied, happy, willing<br />

to perform<br />

whatever task the demogogue asks of it. It is the demagogue, according to<br />

Socrates, who is pained<br />

by the disharmony within himself, disharmony caused<br />

by the variability of the many, by the constantly changing whims of those<br />

he seeks to please. But Callicles sees it otherwise; he paints the demagogue


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 153<br />

Socrates as the one who makes others suffer. Does Callicles know what he is<br />

talking about? Is his grand speech flawed, as suggested by<br />

this initial equation<br />

of<br />

demagoguery and the suffering of the listeners, rather than demagoguery and<br />

the pleasing, soothing phrases Gorgias teaches? This is not the only problem<br />

in his grand and central speech.<br />

Many more are to come.<br />

According to Callicles, the suffering<br />

which Socrates causes comes from<br />

shame. The political, the public man is driven on<br />

by shame, by how he appears<br />

to others, by how the many view him. His value comes not from himself, but<br />

from the opinions of others. To be ashamed in front of others leads to suffering<br />

because it suggests a denial of However, esteem.38 while<br />

suffering<br />

from shame may lead to a withdrawal,<br />

which comes<br />

a removal of the self from public view<br />

as both Gorgias and Callicles try to do (458b, 497bc, 505d), the suffering<br />

which comes from eros, which Socrates and Callicles share, leads to action<br />

the action of pursuit of power or the beautiful. The suffering<br />

which Socrates<br />

causes to others comes, on Callicles' account, from Socrates' refusal to allow<br />

others to distinguish between nature and convention, to confuse the two and<br />

thus force others to say what they do not believe and cannot defend, for<br />

example, that justice and equality are noble. What public man needing to<br />

appeal to the many for his power would dare to say that justice is not noble,<br />

that virtue is not good? What public man in a<br />

democracy<br />

would dare to so of<br />

fend the many by openly acknowledging a doctrine of injustice and inequality?<br />

The Athenians, speaking to the Spartans before the war started, could not do<br />

it. The Corinthians had come to speak before the Spartans to urge them into war<br />

against Athens. The Corinthians had turned traditional words of commendation<br />

into words of condemnation. Sophrosune, moderation, has led to an inability to<br />

deal with affairs outside (ta exo pragmata, 1 .68.<br />

activity, makes them responsible for the slavery<br />

1).<br />

Spartan hesuchia, in<br />

of their friends and allies<br />

(1.69. 1). The Spartans are trampled on, punched in the face, and leave their<br />

friends unaided in situations of danger. Because they do not act to stop the<br />

movements of the enslaving Athenians, the Spartans are the true enslavers.<br />

They sit back, nursing their traditional values while the Athenians actively<br />

pursue more, that is, harm for Sparta's allies and for all of Greece. But even<br />

after this speech<br />

by the Corinthians, questioning<br />

and suggesting the danger of these virtues when one is talking<br />

the value of traditional virtues<br />

about relation<br />

ships between cities, the Athenian envoys who happen to be in Sparta at the<br />

time find it impossible to isolate their actions from traditional values. Rather<br />

they must argue: "Not unreasonably (oute apeikotos) do we possess what<br />

we<br />

have"<br />

(1.73. 1). The history<br />

saviour of Greece by providing<br />

of the Persian Wars where Athens was the<br />

the three most important elements in the de<br />

feat of the Persians (troops, leadership, and the most unhesitating enthusiasm,<br />

1.74. 1 ), gives them the honor and the prestige, the pride to stand where<br />

they<br />

38. Cf. Thrasymachus'<br />

blush, Republic 350d.


1<br />

submi<br />

154 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

do with regard to the empire<br />

they have. "We are worthy (axioi), O Lacedae<br />

monians, because of the enthusiasm shown then. .<br />

hostility<br />

(epiphthonos)"<br />

of their strength<br />

they<br />

(i .75.<br />

). They<br />

not to deserve so much<br />

did not act from the view that because<br />

should rule over Greece. Rather the blame must lie on<br />

the shoulders of the Spartans who let the allies fall under Athenian domination<br />

and forced the Athenians to rule. And while it may be a necessity<br />

lesser (hesso) are controlled by the more powerful (dunatoterou) ,<br />

are worthy (axioi) of their position (1.76.2)<br />

justice and<br />

equality<br />

would be.<br />

that the<br />

the Athenians<br />

and indeed more eager to show<br />

in their dealings with their subjects than the Spartans<br />

In this public speech the Athenians, despite the opening given them by the<br />

Corinthians, show their deference to the conventional values of good and bad,<br />

virtue and justice. They are ashamed before the public to say what is true by<br />

nature. This they can do only in the privacy of a meeting<br />

with the leaders of<br />

Meios. There the language of values is discarded. Don't talk to us of right and<br />

wrong. You know as well as we that right "in human speech is judged from<br />

an equal<br />

necessity while the strong do what they<br />

can and the weak<br />

(v. 88). There the necessity<br />

of nature dominates and the strength of the Athen<br />

ians alone justifies her conquest. In the confines of the meeting room in Meios,<br />

the Athenians do not speak as public men concerned with the effect of their<br />

words on others or with the shame that may<br />

come to them for their praise of<br />

injustice, for their praise of inequality, for their exclusive concern with selfinterest.<br />

Thus, they do not have to hide their ambition for power and domination<br />

with fancy<br />

phrases of worth and recollections of noble deeds of the past. The<br />

demands of nature are<br />

starkly stated: the strong<br />

rule over the weak. And this<br />

is not<br />

only necessary, but approved<br />

by the gods (v.105.1). Right is not what<br />

appeals to the many, but what physis demands.<br />

Both Gorgias and Polus are like the Athenians at Sparta, unable to give<br />

up<br />

noble<br />

sounding phrases of justice and virtue, of equality and goodness. They<br />

are trapped by a Socrates words"<br />

"working evil with (483a), who sees in<br />

their reasons for studying<br />

rhetoric the same aims which the Athenians had as<br />

they expanded their empire, the desire for domination over others, to become<br />

dunastai, to be free men who enslave others, and to be unjust rather than<br />

suffer injustice. Callicles shakes off the chains of traditional values which limit<br />

the perspectives of Gorgias and Polus; he speaks as the Athenian leaders at<br />

Meios do, within the walls of some undefined space, given the freedom to speak<br />

by Socrates and which the Athenians took upon themselves as they<br />

talked to<br />

the leaders of Meios. He openly declares what others could not; perhaps they<br />

held back because of fear, but more likely they<br />

were restrained because they<br />

were unable to articulate the assumptions which<br />

underlay their statements con<br />

cerning good and bad, just and unjust.<br />

These traditional values cited in the earlier sections of the dialogue belong<br />

not to the real man, the aner, the one who can take more (483b). the one who


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 155<br />

according to Callicles is able to bring to completion whatever he thinks about<br />

(491b).39<br />

They belong to the slave (andrapodos, 483b), the weakling, the one<br />

who cannot act whatever he "may think, for whom it is better to die than to live<br />

and who must call greediness (to pleonektein) unjust (483c). Callicles ap<br />

pears certain that it is better to live than to die. Only<br />

a slave would crave<br />

death. Life for Callicles is the passionate life, a life of constantly seeking more;<br />

it is the Hobbesian life where one's desires can never be fully satisfied, only<br />

briefly met and then instantly<br />

reignited. Not to have passions is to be dead.<br />

The real man is the eternal consumer. He seeks to satisfy his passions constantly<br />

and is unconcerned about the absence of an end to those passions, a final<br />

resting place, a finis ultimus. The slave seeks death because he seeks cessation<br />

from passions which can never be satisfied and thus never afford him any<br />

pleasures.<br />

We must not forget that this speech was prefaced by Socrates' speech on<br />

love and the suffering of the lover. Socrates the philosopher does not stop<br />

searching; his passion for truth and<br />

beauty do not come to an end either, so<br />

long<br />

as he lives as a human being. The end to the philosophic eros, as Diotima<br />

describes it (and indeed as it could be inferred from the Republic), w is a death<br />

to the life which both Callicles and Socrates know of as eternal searching. For<br />

Socrates death may be a resolution, a completion, though his possibly comic<br />

vision in the Apology (4oe-4ic) suggests that his life of eternal questioning<br />

would not<br />

necessarily end with death. For Callicles death can only<br />

be a sign<br />

of defeat, of benefit only to those who do not know how to live well, to<br />

satisfy<br />

their own passionate desires at the expense of others. Not to be able<br />

to control and dominate the activities of others, not to be able to defend one<br />

self or those one loves, to allow oneself to be trampled in the mud, such a life<br />

cannot be worth living.<br />

The importance of domination for human happiness, this Callicles knows;<br />

this he asserts declaratively. When Callicles analyzes the conditions and causes<br />

of freedom and slavery, he begins to speculate; he begins to hesitate. Oimai,<br />

I<br />

believe, he says (483b). He no longer knows. The weak are the ones who<br />

establish the nomoi, the traditions and the values which limit and enslave the<br />

actions of strong<br />

men. The Athenians declare to the Spartans who stand in a<br />

position of weakness vis-a-vis Athens: "Calculating what is in your interest,<br />

now you make reference to the language of justice, which has never turned<br />

anyone away from getting more (pleon echein)<br />

who had the strength to ac<br />

quire it" (1.76.2). The language of justice, in other words, is the discourse<br />

of those who are weak. The weak fear the stronger (erromenesterous<br />

kai dunatous, 483c); they fear that the strong<br />

will take more than their fair<br />

share, as indeed the Athenians did in Greece. And so the weak, for example<br />

39. Cf. the strikingly similar language in the Corinthians' speech: epitelesai ergoi ha an<br />

gndsin. 1.70.2.<br />

Callicles'<br />

40. vi.5o6e; vn.533a.<br />

strong men are hikanoi ontes ha an noesosin epitelein.


156 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

the Spartans (1.86. 1-5), say that the Athenian actions are evil, that they are<br />

unjust and not in accordance with the nomoi. To want more than one's fair<br />

(equal) share is condemned by those who are weak, by<br />

the slaves who cannot<br />

city. It<br />

satisfy their passions and who envy the truly strong man or the strong<br />

is the weak and worthless, or so Callicles believes (oimai, 483c), who love<br />

equality.<br />

Callicles appears here as no friend to democracy. But we must be careful.<br />

Just moments before, Socrates had described Callicles' dual love, the two<br />

"demoses",<br />

them. Certainly<br />

rejection of equality<br />

and how Callicles must alter his views and his language to please<br />

the Athenian demos could not be gratified to hear<br />

Callicles'<br />

or could they? If we focus on the relationships beween<br />

states rather than the relationships within states, then Callicles' arguments do<br />

indeed please the Athenians, who enslaved the rest of Greece and rejected the<br />

enchanting language of dike as they<br />

enlarged their empire. Pericles admits to<br />

the disheartened Athenians: the taking of the empire which they hold like a<br />

have been unjust (adikon), but to let it go would be dangerous<br />

tyrant may<br />

(11. 63. 2). The city<br />

must be viewed from two perspectives. Within, the demo<br />

cratic politeia demands equality among its citizens, isonomia; its unity derives<br />

from this equality binding all citizens together into a coherent whole. Without,<br />

the city stands in unequal relationship to her neighbors; the city<br />

stands as<br />

deficient, desirous of more, eager to take what is not its own, pleon echein,<br />

to affirm a condition of<br />

inequality<br />

rather than equality. Callicles reveals in the<br />

early part of his speech the incompatibility between the ground rules of action<br />

within the city and the ground rules which apply outside. He appeals to the<br />

demos, as does the beloved of Socrates, not<br />

by approving of their democratic,<br />

egalitarian principles, ones which Pericles conjures up when trying<br />

to make<br />

Athens whole and beautiful (11.37. 1-2), but rather<br />

by encouraging<br />

the<br />

demos'<br />

vision of itself as comprising the citizenry<br />

of the<br />

super-city.41<br />

When Callicles describes the enslaving of the real man by the many, the<br />

chains to which he refers serve as a metaphor for language, words of praise<br />

and words of blame. Words,<br />

Socrates'<br />

words, the words of the many, can<br />

make the strong feel shame, can restrain a Polus or an Alcibiades and make<br />

even a master of language such as Gorgias flustered. Words have the capacity<br />

to affect actions, to enslave the powerful. Gorgias is right. It is the power of<br />

words from which Callicles tries to break away in the first half of his speech<br />

and yet to reassert in the second half when he turns to relations within the city,<br />

where a common language and the common values associated with a common<br />

language are crucial. To break away from the power of words Callicles turns<br />

to nature, first to animals (en wis allois zoiois, 483d) tor whom there is no<br />

language of justice and injustice, to whom the dictates of nature speak directly,<br />

without the intervention of morals and virtues, and demand that the stronger<br />

41. Cf. Alcibiades' speech to the Athenians, esp. vi. 18.3-7.


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 157<br />

have more than the weaker, that the lion in all his generosity takes all. After<br />

suggesting that this is true as well in whole cities and races, Callicles turns for<br />

his examples to barbarians, those who for the Greeks represent the uncivilized,<br />

animal-like beings who do not speak Greek, saying only bar-bar-bar, who have<br />

no language of justice and virtue. "With what right (poioi dikaidi) did Xerxes<br />

march against Greece, or his father against the Scythians? Or one would be<br />

able to mention myriad other cases of the<br />

sort"<br />

(483de). But Callicles does not<br />

provide us with more examples. Is it because he has realized the inappropriateness<br />

of his two examples, both of whom were defeated by<br />

the weak native<br />

inhabitants in Scythia and Greece? Or is it because he suddenly remembers the<br />

historian of those wars, Herodotus, who often makes clear that those who invade<br />

with no right, those who take more than their share and overstep their bounds,<br />

are punished<br />

by the gods whose jealousy (phthonos)<br />

can never be escaped?<br />

Callicles avoids the issue but has not Plato played with Callicles' speech, given<br />

him a set of false examples to prove his central but dubious point? Has not<br />

Plato undercut Callicles' purpose<br />

by making him appear foolish?<br />

Callicles ignores the issue of the defeats faced by Darius and Xerxes by<br />

turning next to the gods, to swearing by Zeus (traditionally the distributor of<br />

justice) that there is (or so he believes, oimai, 483c) a nomos tes physeos<br />

which the Persian tyrants followed in their invasions of weaker lands. But this<br />

nomos tes physeos may be quite different from what Callicles envisions, since<br />

in neither case did Zeus smile on the adventures of the invaders,<br />

of those who<br />

tried to take more than their share. The unmentioned example behind this out<br />

burst is, of course, Athens. The Athenians, like the barbarians and like the<br />

animals, are not restrained as they<br />

assert their dominion over others. Concern<br />

with one's fair share does not matter as<br />

they subdue one state after another, as<br />

they satisfy their desire for more. They are acting<br />

on the principles which<br />

Callicles suggests are endorsed<br />

by the gods, which the Athenians themselves,<br />

as the war recorded by Thucydides progresses, also suggest are santioned<br />

by<br />

the gods (v. 105. 1-3).<br />

But Callicles turns quickly from nations to men, to individuals. He does<br />

not stay long in the realm of relationships between states where his examples<br />

have raised doubts about the validity of his beliefs, about the future expansion<br />

of Athenian hegemony. Rather, he considers the fate of one caught within<br />

the structure of the city, within a city<br />

justice is used, where the strong men among<br />

(katadouloumetha. 483c) by our saying that equality<br />

where the language of justice and in<br />

us are charmed and enslaved<br />

is good and just. The<br />

real man, the man having a strong enough nature (physin hikanen, 484a), would<br />

flee our charms, (or so Callicles believes, oimai, 484a), and our words (gram<br />

mata) and laws which oppose nature (para physin, 484a). He would stand<br />

forth revealing himself as our ruler and us as his slaves; there the justice of<br />

nature would shine forth. Callicles here chooses to talk about a man, but he<br />

describes again the actions of the Athenians, who in their relations with other


[Pindar]<br />

truth"<br />

158 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

cities of Greece have shown this independence of the old values, who have<br />

rejected the idea that equality<br />

is good and just in relationships between states,<br />

and who stand forth revealing the true justice of nature.<br />

Callicles next adds to the evidence from nature (animals) and history the<br />

words of the pious poet from Thebes, who proclaimed that Nomos, the king<br />

of men and of gods, turns violence into justice, that nomos, presumably the<br />

nomos tes physeos which Callicles had just proclaimed, supports the actions of<br />

Heracles as he steals the cattle of Geryon, without payment and without sale<br />

(484b). However, as Martin Ostwald has pointed out in but one of several<br />

attempts to discover the meaning of this cited passage, the "interpretation bears<br />

the stamp of the nomos-physis controversy,<br />

which did not flourish until several<br />

decades after Pindar's death, and it is hazardous to retroject into Pindar' s poem<br />

views which were articulated<br />

only by Nor<br />

a later generation. .<br />

is it likely<br />

that Pindar wrote the poem to support the view that heroic morality is law unto<br />

itself makes a special point of .<br />

emphasizing<br />

Heracles and of stressing the arete of his opponent Diomedes."42 Callicles,<br />

unheroic qualities in<br />

though, does not catch this subtlety. He does not see the alternative reading<br />

which would suggest that the strong only declare what is just, or as another<br />

Platonic character phrased it, justice is the interest of the stronger.43<br />

Callicles<br />

does not know the poem well, neither the words, he admits (484b), nor, we<br />

may surmise, the meaning<br />

of the poem. He must thus turn to paraphrasing. He<br />

does not spend his time memorizing poems, the activity for the affected, the<br />

effete, those who do not act. He knows as little about<br />

poetry<br />

at this point as he<br />

does about philosophy,<br />

to the second half of his speech.<br />

which he now urges Socrates to abandon as he moves<br />

Callicles is eager to reveal the truth, his truth, to Socrates as he starts this<br />

second half. He had called Socrates "in<br />

(482c) a demagogue at the begin<br />

ning of the first half of his speech, but he did not understand the meaning of<br />

the word demagogue, much less the truth. Again he claims he is going to<br />

turn to the truth (484c), but his two truths are irreconcilable. One truth, that<br />

Socrates is a demagogue, hardly conincides with the second truth that Socrates<br />

as a philosopher will be unable to defend himself before the many.<br />

Callicles'<br />

understanding of what is true is not consistent from one moment to the next,<br />

unless we were to see him as equating philosophy and demogoguery, but this<br />

he does not do. His argument is that the philosopher does not understand how<br />

to function before the masses, to control the many rather than be controlled by<br />

them.<br />

Callicles is inconsistent precisely because he makes a fundamental shift as<br />

he moves from one part of his speech to the next. In the first part, he had<br />

42. "Pindar, Nomos, and Heracles," in Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 69 (1965), p.<br />

123. See also the references in A. E. Taylor, Plato: The Man and His Work (Cleveland and New<br />

York: World Publishing, 1956), p. 117, n. 2; and Dodds, pp. 270-272.<br />

43. Republic, 1.338c.


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 159<br />

dealt with the superman or supercity, the Athens of Greece. He had talked there<br />

about the relationship of one city to another, the law of power and of force, the<br />

realm in which force and fraud are The virtues.44 second half of the speech deals<br />

with relationships within the city a city based on an equality<br />

which had been<br />

denied in the first half. The second half deals with the survival of individuals<br />

within the set of political relationships among<br />

equal citizens survival,<br />

not<br />

leadership, is the topic of the second part of Callicles' speech. What is neces<br />

sary between states is different from what is needed within states. The opposi<br />

tion in the first half of the speech was between dike, justice, the battle cry<br />

of<br />

the weaker, and those who are strong, who deny equality. Within cities, how<br />

ever, as it is posed<br />

by Callicles, there is a conflict between philosophy<br />

which<br />

assumes an<br />

inequality between better and worse individuals, between better and<br />

worse pleasures, and politics which assumes an equality of all citizens, good<br />

and bad, before the law.<br />

Callicles does not refer<br />

immediately<br />

to politics as he downgrades philosophy;<br />

rather the phrases he uses suggest the level of politics, that of reputation, of<br />

seeming, of appearance. One must have the reputation of<br />

being kalos kagathos<br />

or being an eudokimos aner (a respected man, 484d), and one must know<br />

the pleasures and passions of others, what appeals to them and what will repel<br />

them. Philosophers remain not<br />

only nomon aperioi (inexperienced in the laws)<br />

but unable to manipulate the opinions of the many.<br />

They<br />

are thus laughable,<br />

worthy of such scorn as Polus heaps on Socrates (462e), rather than esteem.<br />

They are laughable whether they<br />

participate in private or in public affairs, just<br />

as or so Callicles believes (oimai, 484c) are hoi politikoi when<br />

they spend<br />

time in the activities of the philosophers, as indeed Callicles becomes by the<br />

end of this dialogue.<br />

The inconsistency is transparent and has been frequently pointed out. First,<br />

Callicles encourages the total disregard of the opinions of the many, their<br />

enchanting phrases, their enslaving nomoi, and<br />

subsequently<br />

he encourages<br />

attention to the opinions of the many, the weak who have enslaved the superheroes.<br />

How can we reconcile these two views? We can do so only<br />

if we<br />

recognize that Callicles is distinguishing, albeit not clearly, between relation<br />

ships within and relationships without the city. The city<br />

cannot endure<br />

easily<br />

the individual who stands over all, the Alcibiades, the Themistocles, even the<br />

Pericles.45<br />

It cannot survive the superhero and the praise of<br />

inequality<br />

first part. The Archelaus, so admired by Polus, is to be killed by<br />

own men.<br />

of the<br />

one of his<br />

Callicles quotes more lines of poetry;<br />

this time he turns to a more contem<br />

porary author, Euripides, an Athenian. Now that he talks about relationships<br />

within states, he turns to a poet from his own<br />

city<br />

rather than to a poet who<br />

44. Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Michael Oakeshott (Oxford: Blackwell, i960), p. 83 (Ch. XIII).<br />

45. Socrates makes a point later in the dialogue of emphasizing how the great political leaders<br />

of Athens were all badly treated by the demos (515c and 5l6e).


160 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

speaks for all of Greece. He quotes from a passage most likely<br />

spoken by<br />

Zethus the herdsman in Euripides' Antiope. We all praise that which we do<br />

best. It is a plea for individuality, a recognition of the different abilities which<br />

we all have. It is from such natural difference, Socrates assures in the Repub<br />

lic, that the true city<br />

triot Euripides. The most correct approach<br />

is built. But Callicles does not agree with his compa<br />

or so Callicles believes (oimai,<br />

485a) is to partake of two ways of life and then choose one over the other, the<br />

Euripides'<br />

chosen one always being politics. He does not encourage the diversity<br />

Zethus praises and he does not encourage the pursuit of philosophy. The<br />

eudokimos aner is the one who appears to have followed the proper pattern of<br />

growth, the one who no longer engages in the pursuits of a child when he is<br />

old, the one who no longer engages in philosophizing<br />

when he is of an age to<br />

enter politics.<br />

Yes, philosophy is fine when one is a youth, but it is a thing<br />

most laughable<br />

when an old man practices it. The philosopher is different from the many. He<br />

scorns their opinions and their uniformity. He stands aloof, off in a corner<br />

whispering, with two or three other men, not joining in the center of activities,<br />

the varied meetings of the many. He is not a part of the whole and does not<br />

care about the opinions and values of the whole. The individual, independent<br />

of and uninterested in the opinions of the whole, who stood at the center of the<br />

earlier section of Callicles' speech, is now seen as threatening the survival and<br />

freedom of the city<br />

on which Callicles depends.<br />

With the shift in focus from the first half of the speech to the second half,<br />

there is a comparable shift in the meanings of slavery and freedom. At first the<br />

free man is the one who breaks the chains of the nomoi, or the Athens who<br />

subdues other cities and threatens those who do not submit. This is the free<br />

dom Polus and Callicles want. The second concept of freedom is one centered<br />

around the man who submits to his chains, the "liberal" man who is judged by<br />

his peers as noble, who possesses the requisite social graces and who can<br />

help<br />

his friends when<br />

they need his help.46 The slave in the first section is one<br />

held back by the opinions of the many; the slave in the second section is the<br />

one who does not attend to the opinions of the many, the one like Socrates<br />

whose pursuit of philosophy shows him to be illiberal, to lack the graces of a<br />

well educated man, to continue to lisp and to be unable to help<br />

his friends or<br />

harm his enemies. Such an individual is unmanly (anandron), like a slave<br />

(douloprepes), unfree (aneleutheron, 485b-d) such a man deserves a boxing<br />

around the ears, just as does a slave who is too stupid to understand directions.<br />

The free man (eleutheros) is the one trained to earn respect in battle and in<br />

speech, the one trained to participate in the activities of the city.<br />

But once again, as at the beginning of the dialogue, Callicles appears gen<br />

erous. He appears liberal, eager to help<br />

his friends. He makes a speech to<br />

46. See Dodds, p. 274.


. There<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 161<br />

Socrates, one filled with good<br />

feeling (eunoia, 486a), not meant to anger<br />

him. It is a speech modeled again on that of the restless and active Zethus in<br />

Euripides'<br />

Antiope, Zethus whose advice he had rejected moments before. The<br />

conceit is extensive. "I happen to suffer (peponthenai) what Euripides' Zethus<br />

does before Amphion. .<br />

come words to me to speak to you such<br />

as he [Zethus] spoke before his brother" (485c). Don't act like a youth,<br />

Socrates.47<br />

Give up philosophy. Become mature and learn to function in the<br />

city. Don't act shamefully, as do those or so I believe (oimai, 485a) who<br />

pursue philosophy for too long, allowing yourself to be accused and killed,<br />

appearing dizzy with your mouth gaping open in the courtroom, subject to the<br />

power of any<br />

who might wish to harm you. Don't allow others to be rude to<br />

you (as, we might note, was Polus, for example, 461c). Don't lose your power<br />

to help yourself. Be persuaded by me, give<br />

up<br />

music of<br />

affairs,"<br />

encourages Callicles, again quoting<br />

what is called<br />

by the Athenians apragmosune ,<br />

of the city. There is an<br />

irony<br />

the private life. "Practice the<br />

Zethus (486c). Avoid<br />

a noninvolvement in the affairs<br />

in this point; it is Amphion who through his<br />

knowledge of music is able to build the walls of Thebes, whose lyre moves<br />

the stones out of which the wall is built. It is he who by practicing<br />

his private<br />

music most helps the city. Yet Callicles urges: "Don't imitate those men caught<br />

in debates about petty things, but those for whom there is life and opinion and<br />

many other<br />

goods"<br />

(486cd).<br />

Callicles has given his speech to his dear Socrates (o phile Socrates, 486a)<br />

and spoken with warm brotherly feelings. Socrates, though, does not trust<br />

this speech. He questions Callicles' sincerity<br />

(489c). Why does Callicles offer Socrates this friendly<br />

and suggests that it is ironic<br />

advice, which Socrates<br />

does not take seriously? Does this in part explain the shift in the two halves<br />

of Callicles' speech? Is Callicles' speech a cover for his fear of Socrates? Is<br />

not Socrates the superman who does see<br />

clearly the fallibility of the nomoi,<br />

the dependence of the weak on the nomoil Is not Socrates able to rise above,<br />

to shake free from the chains of opinion, to shift most facilely<br />

in his discussion<br />

between nomos and physis, to recognize that dike does not come from the<br />

opinion of the many? Does not this knowledge, this awareness indeed enable<br />

him to become a demagogue? Does he not then pose serious threats for poor<br />

Callicles, the one who because of his eros wishes to appease the many?<br />

Callicles is frightened of the power of Socrates; the second half of the<br />

speech is an attempt to subdue the philosopher, to fit the philosopher into the<br />

city rather than allow him to break away<br />

and stand above the other slaves. The<br />

philosopher is not useless; he is not simply foolish. The philosopher is threaten<br />

ing, threatening to the power and stature of a Callicles. Philosophy does recog<br />

nize the distinction between nature and convention, as Callicles points out in<br />

47. When Callicles quotes the passage from Euripides, he changes one word significantly.<br />

Instead of meirakiodei (youthful, childish) in Callicles' version, there is in the original gunaikomimoi.<br />

Cf. Gonzalez Lodge, ed., Plato,<br />

"Gorgias"<br />

(Boston: Ginn. 1980), p. 147.


another.48<br />

162 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

his initial attack against Socrates. Those men supposedly whispering<br />

in corners<br />

care not a whit about the opinions of the many; the chains and the enchant<br />

paralyze those tied<br />

ments. They<br />

are able, should they want, to enslave, subdue,<br />

up by the nomoi of the many. Indeed, they do not even whisper in isolation<br />

in corners, two or three at a time. They<br />

speak out in the open<br />

agora, as Socrates has informed us right at the beginning<br />

of the dialogue (447a)-<br />

The philosophers thus threaten the survival of the city for they are privy to<br />

out in the<br />

the secrets of Callicles. Socrates is Callicles' enemy. The appeal to give up<br />

philosophy, Socrates recognizes, is not sincere. It is an appeal meant to disarm<br />

Socrates, to fit him into the model of the city, the equality<br />

of the city. It is<br />

an appeal to make him value what the city values, most of all life, but also<br />

reputation and freedom from subjection to<br />

Socrates'<br />

Callicles pretends that<br />

pursuit of philosophy is a mistake rather than a conscious choice. But<br />

because this assumption about<br />

Socrates'<br />

motives is clearly incorrect, he must<br />

try to disarm and subdue Socrates.<br />

Callicles'<br />

speech is divided into two halves, each with its own truth de<br />

pending on whether one looks at the city<br />

from within or from outside. The<br />

speech thus appears to have contradictory<br />

goals. Scholars have debated: is<br />

Callicles a democrat, or is he an oligarch?49<br />

The answer to such a question<br />

must.depend on which half one reads, which must thus suggest the inadequacy<br />

of such an analysis. Let us leave debates concerning<br />

particular political orienta<br />

tions aside and see Callicles as the political man, the man of action, like<br />

Zethus the herdsman, like Athens the city. Whether he be democrat or oligarch,<br />

he is the stone against which the philosopher's life is to be tested and justified.<br />

The philosopher must do this in response to both parts of Callicles' speech; he<br />

must show the deficiencies of both visions<br />

on the one hand, the superman and<br />

the supercity who scorn the opinions of the many, on the other the political<br />

man who is dependent on the opinions of the many, his beloved demos.<br />

Callicles has proclaimed that the better man must have more, that this is just<br />

by nature, that this is the law of nature. What, though, Socrates must ask,<br />

describes the better man? What is this justice that you and Pindar praise'.' This<br />

Callicles clarifies only under Socrates' questioning. The better are the stronger,<br />

the stronger are the many. Suddenly, Callicles, under Socrates' manipulation,<br />

turns into a democrat (458d). Superiority does indeed come from the many,<br />

the unity of large numbers of individuals, in the assembly<br />

and on the battle-<br />

48. Freedom is not<br />

being a slave for Callicles, but Socrates does not in his discourse dis<br />

tinguish between slave and free. Cf. 5l4d and 515a; in 514c he does not speak<br />

differently<br />

or women.<br />

Considering<br />

to men<br />

Callicles emphasis on manliness, this is a significant attack on<br />

Callicles'<br />

vision.<br />

49. G. B. Kerferd, "Plato's Treatment of Callicles in the Gorgias,"<br />

Proceedings of the Cam<br />

bridge Philological Society, 20 (1974), p. 48 and in notes 2 and 3, describes the various arguments<br />

on either side. Kerferd sides with those who see Callicles as a democrat, p. 52.


Forms<br />

ruled?"<br />

war.52<br />

An Unspoken Theme in Plato' s Gorgias: War 163<br />

field. But Callicles will not admit such a simple equation between numerical<br />

superiority and the best. There are those who know how to manipulate assem<br />

blies, the demagogues who use language well, and there are those who know<br />

how to use small numbers of men as if they were many on the battlefields (for<br />

example, the Greeks against the Persians). Callicles clarifies. The better is not<br />

simply the many<br />

"the litter of<br />

those who are stronger only in terms of bodily<br />

slaves"<br />

(doulon, 488c; cf. 489d)<br />

nor is it<br />

strength. The better is the<br />

political ruler, Polus' Archelaus and Callicles' man of affairs, one devoted to<br />

the music of pragmata, that is, those who rule over others, (491b, d) those<br />

who are able to accomplish in deed what<br />

they<br />

have in their<br />

minds.50<br />

The<br />

natural justice of which he had spoken relates to the rulers within the city and<br />

the masters of empires.<br />

But Socrates introduces a new level of interaction which had not been raised<br />

before in Callicles' speech, nor<br />

by<br />

Polus or Gorgias namely<br />

ruling within<br />

oneself. "Come now, my friend, what of themselves? Are they ruling something<br />

or<br />

being (49 id). Callicles has difficulty<br />

with this notion. When at<br />

last he understands, he blurts out offensively, "You are cute (hedus, sweet?).<br />

You call fools moderate<br />

(sophronas)"<br />

(49ie). Socrates, according to Callicles,<br />

is offering<br />

a new or different form of slavery, again the obverse side of mastery.<br />

"How could the happy human being (eudaimon) be a slave (douleuon) to<br />

anything?"<br />

(49id) even, Callicles asks, to himself. No, the one who is to live<br />

correctly (orthos) must release his passions, satisfy his desires, and constantly<br />

fill himself up (apopimplanai). This or so Callicles believes (oimai, 492a)<br />

is not possible (ou dunatonf for the many<br />

and thus, because of their lack<br />

of manliness (anandrian), they find fault with the satisfying of one's desires;<br />

they see it as shameful intemperance. The truth (492bc) is, Socrates, that<br />

freedom is not mastery<br />

over oneself, but the total release of one's passions<br />

along with the power (dunamis) to satisfy those passions. Slavery is being<br />

unable to fill what is empty, unable to find that elusive missing<br />

Aristophanes'<br />

death.<br />

Socrates'<br />

model, and thus being miserable and finding<br />

half in<br />

life worse than<br />

problem, according to Callicles, is that he does not acknowl<br />

edge the importance of the epithumia for happiness and for life (492c). To<br />

be without desires is to be dead<br />

a stone or a corpse.<br />

The foreshadowings of Hobbes are startling. As Hobbes has so vividly shown<br />

us, these desires these insatiable desires must lead to<br />

satisfy one's desires leads one to build up one's strength, to develop<br />

The urge to<br />

the power<br />

50. See preceding footnote 39. We see Callicles here encountering the same problems as<br />

Thrasymachus: for both superiority must be defined with references to the mind, albeit the mind<br />

directed to the satisfaction of desires. It is this which makes them both interlocutors worthy of<br />

Socrates<br />

Socrates'<br />

51 .<br />

and which makes the Athens they both represent and which Pericles extolls worthy of<br />

attention.<br />

of ou dunaton appear three times in 492a.<br />

52. We should not forget at this point that Hobbes' first currently acknowledged published<br />

work is a translation of Thucydides.


164 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

to satisfy those desires, whether that power comes in the form of rhetoric,<br />

military strength, or manipulative wiles; it is the power of conquest,<br />

the denial<br />

of equality, the vision of the world as comprised of masters and slaves. Socrates<br />

accuses Callicles: he does not understand the importance of equality. He does<br />

not pay sufficient attention to geometry (508a). Equality<br />

is a realm which<br />

denies power over others and emphasizes friendship. Callicles, the one with<br />

desires to be satisfied, the one who lives by having power over others, cannot<br />

accept To equality.53<br />

accept equality as an individual or as a city interacting<br />

with other cities is to die. The self-satisfied city and the self-satisfied individual,<br />

happy with their equality, are weak. Sparta had allowed others to trample her<br />

in the mud, to punch her in the face. The Corinthian's advice to Sparta parallels<br />

Callicles'<br />

advice to Socrates. "Be practiced in the music of affairs (pragmata,<br />

486c)"<br />

(cp. Thucydides,<br />

1.72.2-4). Athens the tyrant of the Aegean has been<br />

active in her pursuit of inequality, in her pursuit of the power which will<br />

enable her to fill herself with the wealth of cities outside. There is for Athens<br />

as a city no final resting place; even the one Pericles urges in his funeral oration<br />

is only a temporary resting point, to be moved beyond once the exigencies of<br />

war subside. The city<br />

must always be in a condition of movement because there<br />

are those outside who threaten it. The Sparta that tried to sit still, to practice<br />

its traditional hesuchia,<br />

could not.<br />

Political life within the realm of one<br />

city to another is a life of the constant<br />

pursuit of more. What Callicles cannot understand because of his failure to<br />

study geometry<br />

is that the disharmonious nature of relations between states<br />

cannot be transferred to relations within states, that the tyrannical city pursuing<br />

more outside must ensure an<br />

equality upon which friendships and community<br />

(koinonia) are built within (5070-5083). The tension in Callicles is between<br />

eagerness for power over others, and the desire for friends, causing Callicles to<br />

act graciously so as to build up<br />

time of need should others threaten him (cf.<br />

a store of friends who will protect him in a<br />

487cd).S4<br />

But because he is not<br />

sincere in his professions of friendship, because he does not<br />

really treat others<br />

as his equals, his friends do not protect him. While he pretends that Socrates<br />

is his friend and that he cares for Socrates, he nevertheless tries to control<br />

Socrates and becomes irate and withdrawn when he cannot. It is an<br />

irony of<br />

history that Callicles becomes dependent on Socrates' pupil and friend alone<br />

for his survival in the minds of subsequent generations.<br />

53. Note Hobbes' ninth law of nature with its emphasis on the acceptance of equality as the<br />

way out of the state of nature (Levithan Chap. XV). We must, of course, remember that Socrates<br />

is not the equal of those whom he guides in his discourse with them. On this level Callicles' fear is<br />

Socrates'<br />

justified. However, unlike Callicles, inequality is not for the sake of satisfaction of<br />

private desires by domination over others. On this level Callicles' fear is not justified.<br />

54. Dodds, p. 282, summarized the evidence on the background and character of these men.<br />

He concludes: "The general picture which the evidence suggests is that of a group of ambitious<br />

young men. drawn from the jeunesse doree of Athens It certainly does not support Lamb's<br />

description of Callicles' as 'the typical Athenian Democrat.'"


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 165<br />

Later in the dialogue Socrates is to describe Athens' most powerful and<br />

famous political leaders as ones who gorge the city, will fill her (empeplekasi,<br />

5i8e-5i9a) with harbors and dockyards, with walls and imports, and all<br />

such filth (phluarion). The politicians, Themistocles, Cimon, Pericles, all<br />

try to<br />

make Athens a master over her neighbors so as to fill the city<br />

with such<br />

garbage so that the citizens do not feel a lack or the need to pursue the truly<br />

beautiful. These are the politicians who are praised for what<br />

they give to the<br />

city, hegemony over other Greeks, while those such as Callicles and Alcibiades<br />

will be seized and held responsible should this hegemony or garbage be lost,<br />

should the Athenian demos be deprived of that which fills and satisfies it. The<br />

form of dialogue which Socrates tries to encourage does not profess to fill the<br />

participants and silent listeners with anything. It does not<br />

gratify them. It does<br />

not reach any conclusions or victory point (457a). Thus there is no mastery or<br />

inequality among the interlocutors. The conception of power which Socrates<br />

proposes in this dialogue is not the power to fill another and<br />

satisfy her desires,<br />

nor to make another serve one's own interests. It is a conception of power<br />

which can<br />

only be understood in terms of making one better, and making one<br />

better consists in making<br />

one aware of what one lacks not the dockyards or<br />

imports or other such filth but virtue. The Gorgias is not simply<br />

about rhetoric<br />

vs.<br />

philosophy as a way of life. It is also about different kinds of power.<br />

Rhetoric leads to domination over the opinions of others, war to the domination<br />

over the bodies and wealth of others. The desire for domination comes from a<br />

dissatisfaction with what one has, and a supposition that domination will lead<br />

to the fulfilment of some of those desires. Polus and Callicles give expression<br />

to what is to become the classic twentieth century formulation of politics who<br />

gets what, where, when, and how. Socrates is to question that formulation of<br />

politics and the conception of power implicit in it.<br />

do not make<br />

Because the politicians fill the city with harbors and walls, they<br />

the citizens better. They offer them the satisfaction of ports, walls, and imports,<br />

but the citizens therefore are not made to the feel the lack of what makes<br />

them better<br />

their lack of what is truly beautiful. They are not pricked by the<br />

Socratic irony into a sense of needfulness (cf. Alcibiades'<br />

experience, Sympo<br />

sium 2 1 6a). What lack they do feel comes from a desire for more of what has<br />

already given them pleasure, from the passions which once filled are quickly<br />

reignited. Socrates finds fault with the politicians for not making<br />

citizens<br />

better.55<br />

But we may ask why<br />

should they? To make them better human beings does not<br />

help the politicians, nor the city in its drive for mastery<br />

and domination. To<br />

make them better would be to alert them to what<br />

they truly lack, and that is a<br />

55. Scholars have had difficulty understanding how Pericles made the citizens worse, as<br />

Socrates claims, rather than better. They turn to such points as payment for attendance at the<br />

assembly and for military service. Cf., e.g., Lodge, 237; W. H. Thompson. The Gorgias of Plato<br />

(London. George Bell, 1905), p. 226; and Dodds, pp. 335-356. The problem here is that all<br />

these analyses look at the question from a political perspective, from the perspective of the city,<br />

not from the perspective of the philosopher.


166 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

lack which could never be satisfied<br />

by the city nor by<br />

the politicians who give<br />

them walls and the harbors into which the goods of the world flow.<br />

The politicians, though, can never provide for the city<br />

a state of completion.<br />

Filling the city is like filling the leaky jar (493ab). The walls are never enough,<br />

nor the harbors, nor the ships, and thus there is the need for external conquests,<br />

for domination over others because Athens herself, like the human body, can<br />

never be completely<br />

satisfied. It is the constant need for more, however, that<br />

leads to Athens' stature, and the ambivalence surrounding<br />

her position in<br />

Greece at the end of the fifth century, an ambivalence captured brilliantly by<br />

Thucydides, especially in the speech of the Corinthians at Sparta. Athens is<br />

both enslaver as she acquires more, and model to be envied, hateful and ad<br />

mired,<br />

shameful and glorious. All this is the result of her refusal to be content<br />

with little, to deaden her desires. And yet, of course, she loses the war; en<br />

couraged by politicians such as Alcibiades to desire too much, she tries to get<br />

too much power. The Athenians do not limit or question the nature of their<br />

desires for more.<br />

They refuse to engage in the questioning<br />

Gorgias.56<br />

Callicles during the second half of the<br />

Socrates urges upon<br />

Callicles, eager to please both demoses, refuses to accept<br />

any deadening of<br />

the desires as a necessary result of the dialogue he has with Socrates. He is a<br />

man of action, a man whose first thought on seeing Socrates arrive late for a<br />

display of words is of war and battle. He is a free man, unlimited in his<br />

actions, as far as he understands himself. He is not a slave, subject to the<br />

mastery of another. He is not one to accept the notion of completion, of ends,<br />

of quiet. Nor is Socrates. Callicles is an Athenian. So is Socrates. The dif<br />

ference between the two is Socrates' willingness to distinguish between good<br />

and bad desires, those which have a final even if humanly inaccessible aim<br />

or goal and those which will<br />

only lead to a desire for more. This difference<br />

must also stem from different conceptions of power, power over others as in the<br />

master and slave relationships of Callicles' vision, and power over oneself a<br />

power to distinguish between good and bad passions and to choose the former.<br />

Callicles refuses to participate seriously in the subsequent conversation. He<br />

continues only to be gracious, to please his honored guest Gorgias (497c,<br />

50 1 c). He refuses to engage in Socrates' discussions concerning worse and better<br />

desires, and the relationship between pleasure and pain and cessation of desire.<br />

The subsequent discussion carried on<br />

by Socrates in a comedy of his own<br />

making never resolves these questions. Do pain and pleasure cease at the<br />

moment of fulfilment? The lovers spoken of<br />

by Diotima and Alcibiades and<br />

Aristophanes feel pain as does any passionate being. The lover is thus to pursue<br />

the beautiful, to improve the self because of a sense of lack. Without that lack,<br />

there is no change, no growth, no movement toward the complete or full<br />

human being. Socrates cannot and does not encourage the cessation of desire,<br />

56. Cf. Anytus in the Meno and Socrates' description of his life of questioning in the Apology.


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 167<br />

or eros. He urges the tempering of eros, whether for individual or for city<br />

(507d) and its transformation from what leads to making<br />

some men or cities<br />

masters and free, some tyrants and some subjects and slaves, into an equality<br />

which Callicles cannot<br />

fully understand and refuses to try<br />

to understand as he<br />

withdraws from the conversation and the search for true pleasures.<br />

Callicles'<br />

speech had been fraught with inconsistencies because on the one<br />

hand he had talked about free men and slaves, and then about the city, a city<br />

bound together by friendships, a city populated by others about whom one<br />

cares, a city<br />

in which one survives on the esteem of others. The two perspec<br />

tives clashed. The inequality of the first half clashed with the equality<br />

of the<br />

second half. Socrates tells Callicles that Callicles does not understand equality,<br />

that he focuses on power over others and thus cannot understand power over<br />

himself, and because he cannot distinguish between good pleasures and bad,<br />

he cannot exist in a<br />

community such as Socrates envisions, based on<br />

friendship<br />

and<br />

searching for a whole as it pursues the truly beautiful.<br />

The topic of war does not surface<br />

frequently<br />

in the Gorgias. It would almost<br />

be possible to read the dialogue, and indeed many have, as if the war which<br />

dominated Greece during the twenty-eight-year span of the dialogue were not<br />

going on. But it was. And the war's continuation must influence our under<br />

standing of the conditions which existed within the city<br />

and within the indi<br />

vidual. The city<br />

states of Greece could not exist without an awareness of the<br />

external threats which faced them, both from other Greeks and from the bar<br />

barians on the north and to the east. The Peleponnesian War dominated Athens<br />

at the end of the fifth century<br />

b.c .<br />

suggest some of the responses to this war.<br />

Euripides, Aristophanes, and Thucydides<br />

Socrates'<br />

life was touched by the<br />

war and Plato's understanding of Socrates and<br />

Socrates'<br />

place in the city cannot<br />

be disassociated from that war.<br />

The Gorgias is generally<br />

recognized as a dialogue about rhetoric,<br />

and about<br />

moral choices concerning<br />

what type of life one is to lead. The background of<br />

war, the unspoken theme of the dialogue, gives to this dialogue, as to cities<br />

themselves, a greater depth, where rhetoric is only<br />

a surface activity of the city,<br />

a model with its concern for victory<br />

and conquest, irrespective of dike, of the<br />

war in the background. The moral choices in their turn depend on the existence<br />

of a city striving for its own wholeness within an ordered cosmos (508a). War,<br />

however, raises the question of whether that wholeness for city<br />

or for individual<br />

is ever possible prior to death whether the leaky jar of the Sicilian or Italian<br />

tale is a parable that must apply to the city<br />

as well as to the individual as<br />

long as she/he/it lives. The power which Polus and Gorgias see as deriving from<br />

rhetoric is a limited power though they may call it the greatest good. It is<br />

limited to a power within the city. Callicles, like Athens and her leaders, sees<br />

a greater power, a power over other cities and over other peoples. But that


walls.57<br />

168 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

power is also limited by its never-ending nature. To live is to want; to kill the<br />

passions is to be dead. Neither the city<br />

nor the individual can ever find whole<br />

ness while alive in the human body. The completion sought through power over<br />

oneself which characterizes the philosopher's life may<br />

come closer than the<br />

city's continual search through war for power over others. War becomes the<br />

symbol of the inability of the city to be complete ever so long, at least, as<br />

cities are comprised of bodies and not the bodiless warriors and memories of<br />

Pericles'<br />

funeral oration.<br />

The answer which philosophy in the person of Socrates gives to Athens and<br />

to Callicles is not a wholeness nor a completion never accessible through the<br />

wars of the city, but a transformation of political<br />

activity from one of domina<br />

tion to one of<br />

making citizens better, that is, to lead them into a condition in<br />

which<br />

they<br />

will not be dependent on others either as master or as slaves but<br />

will be wholes in themselves and not controlled<br />

by the opinions, the values and<br />

nomoi of those surrounding them. This is not so that the individual will be able<br />

to dominate others, but so that she can dominate herself, not so that the world<br />

becomes divided into slaves and masters, but so that there is no such concept<br />

and the master over others disappears. Philosophy<br />

abhors the concept of con<br />

quest (457d), of masters and slaves. The best person, made best by the activities<br />

of the true politician, would be a complete whole, not a ruler over others, just<br />

as the best city<br />

would be a complete whole and not need to have hegemony<br />

over other cities.<br />

But, neither the best person nor the best city is possible;<br />

neither the complete<br />

person without needs, at least so long as she is alive, nor the complete city<br />

existing in isolation from other cities can come into being. Philosophers, as<br />

Socrates so<br />

vividly demonstrates in both the Apology and the Crito, is very<br />

much a part of the city. The philosopher is not self-sufficient; the philosopher<br />

cannot exist without the city. Likewise the city<br />

does not exist as a self-sufficient<br />

whole. It exists within a set of relationships with other cities. Wholeness would<br />

exclude an awareness of other cities. The chaos of the Peloponnesian War<br />

reveals<br />

definitively<br />

for the Greeks their participation in a world that goes beyond<br />

the confines of the city<br />

Thucydides'<br />

presentation of war comes from a careful articulation of para<br />

digmatic events. The whole war is understood<br />

by comprehending in detail the<br />

specific events which mark its progress. The Gorgias avoids the details of the<br />

war, the time-bound events which<br />

history records. Nevertheless, for Plato those<br />

events exist in the background. The actions and the motivations of the Athenians<br />

are reflected in Callicles' speech, in the assorted references to the various<br />

political leaders who turn Athens into an empire and a threat to the freedom of<br />

57. Cf. Laws, 626a, "What most men call peace is only a word; in fact there exists<br />

by nature<br />

a state of unproclaimed war between every city and every other<br />

city."<br />

The city of the Laws tries<br />

to escape this fact. The city of the Republic does not. The city of Athens cannot. Political<br />

philosophy cannot be disassociated from wars, from the topic of history.


An Unspoken Theme in Plato's Gorgias: War 169<br />

others, who make Athens part of a society greater than herself. But the war<br />

itself serves to alert us to the limitations of both politics and philosophy. The<br />

political eros for power, for domination over others, suggests the limits and<br />

deficiencies of the city. Pericles had wanted for an instant to treat Athens as a<br />

whole, a beautiful form for all else in Greece to imitate, to raise her above the<br />

activities of every city. But he could not. The city at rest, as Sparta demon<br />

strates, cannot survive in a world that is in motion. Athens was part of the<br />

Greek system of states and Socrates similarly is a part of Athens' activities.<br />

Neither city<br />

nor individual, including the philosopher,<br />

can survive without an<br />

awareness of the deficiencies which make one a part of a larger unit, which in<br />

its turn, comprised of human bodies, is deficient and lacking<br />

completion. The<br />

unspoken theme of this dialogue helps to reveal this underlying dependence<br />

which can never be escaped, neither<br />

by<br />

politicians like Callicles who fail to<br />

recognize that the life as master is also the life as slave,<br />

nor the philosopher<br />

whose life entails the continual search for what one lacks, a search of which<br />

this discourse is but one example.58<br />

58. Leo Strauss, The City and Man (1964; rpt. Chicago and London: University<br />

of Chicago<br />

Press, Phoenix Ed., 1978), p. 239, has written at the end of his essay<br />

on self-<br />

Thucydides: "The<br />

sufficiency of the city as Plato and Aristotle presuppose it excludes the city's dependence on such<br />

a society of cities or its Thucydides'<br />

being essentially a member of it . The lesson of<br />

work<br />

renders questionable a presupposition of classical political philosophy; it excludes the kind of selfsufficiency<br />

of the city which classical political philosophy presupposes. The selfsufficient<br />

nor is it essentially a part of a good or just order comprising many or all cities. The<br />

city is neither<br />

lack<br />

of order which necessarily characterized the "society" of the cities or, in other words, the omni<br />

presence of War puts a much lower ceiling on the highest aspirations of any city toward justice<br />

admitted."<br />

and virtue than classical political might philosophy seem to have<br />

I would argue that<br />

from the evidence of the Gorgias, Plato is very much aware of the limits on human achievement<br />

which the "omnipresence of<br />

War"<br />

imposes. Classical political philosophy<br />

polemos with which the dialogue Peri Rhetorikes begins.<br />

does not ignore the


The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition:<br />

Aristotle's Introduction to Politics<br />

Mary P. Nichols<br />

Catholic University of America<br />

Modern readers of Aristotle's Politics are often embarrassed<br />

by Aristotle's<br />

argument for natural slavery, and perplexed<br />

by his seemingly unqualified con<br />

demnation of commerce.<br />

They often attribute these features of Aristotle's poli<br />

tics to the prejudices of his time.1 I shall argue, in contrast, that Aristotle inten<br />

tionally fails to demonstrate the existence of natural slavery, and that this failure<br />

points to the deeper issue of Book I of the Politics<br />

mankind's dependence on<br />

or slavery to nature. Masters enslave other men not because they<br />

deserve to<br />

rule those who benefit from being ruled, but because masters are naturally<br />

needy.<br />

By satisfying some of man's basic needs, commerce removes the neces<br />

sity of slavery, and therewith its justification. Commerce thus makes possible<br />

political life, which is characterized by political rule, the rule of free men over<br />

free men. Commerce, however, also inhibits political life to the extent that<br />

politics is characterized<br />

by freedom from rule by the bodily<br />

pleasures which<br />

commerce and wealth provide. Aristotle condemns commerce, for while it<br />

helps to free man from his initial dependence on nature, it also inhibits his<br />

actualizing his distinctive natural capacity his capacity for politics, or for<br />

sharing in speech about the advantageous and the just. The freedom from nature<br />

that commerce effects thus has both a good and a bad aspect due to the com<br />

plexity of nature itself. This complexity<br />

choice of a politics that subordinates living to living<br />

the openness of nature,<br />

in nature makes possible Aristotle's<br />

well. Aristotle discovered<br />

which allows him to construct a politics wherein man's<br />

dependence on nature is not slavish and commerce serves political life.<br />

i. Sir David Ross, for example, writes, "It is, though regrettable, not surprising that Aristotle<br />

should regard as belonging to the nature of things an arrangement that was so familiar a part of<br />

everyday Greek life as was."<br />

slavery Aristotle (London: Methuen, 1953), p. 241. Ross finds<br />

Aristotle's condemnation of the commercial class "too much a reflexion of the ordinary Greek<br />

prejudice against trade as an illiberal<br />

p. 243. See also Emest Barker, The Political<br />

Thought of Plato and Aristotle (New York. Dover, 1959), pp. 368, 375-76, and 389. More<br />

recently, R. G. Mulgan explains Aristotle's argument for natural slavery in the following way: "We<br />

must not forget that he is writing within a society which took the existence of slavery for<br />

granted and where slaves, though they did not make up the entire labour force, were<br />

largely<br />

responsible for the marginal surplus of wealth and leisure which made Greek culture and civilization<br />

possible."<br />

Mulgan finds that "no one, in the ancient world, as far as we know, advocated the<br />

abolition of<br />

slavery."<br />

Consequently, "[ajgainst the background of a general acceptance of slavery,<br />

the debate about whether slavery was natural was not, as it seems to us, about whether there<br />

slaves."<br />

should be slaves but about why there should be Hence there were only two alternatives:<br />

slavery is natural, or might makes right. Since the latter justification of slavery is "unthinkable" to<br />

Aristotle, Aristotle is left with the former. Aristotle's Political Theory, An Introductionfor Students<br />

of Political Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977), pp. 43~44-


172 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

I<br />

Near the beginning of the Politics, Aristotle says that "the city<br />

comes into<br />

being for the sake of life, but exists for the sake of the good life" (i252b30-<br />

31).2<br />

Commentators have not given sufficient attention to the problematic char<br />

acter of this What is statement.3 the relationship between the end of a thing's<br />

genesis and the end of its existence?<br />

According to Aristotle, something comes<br />

into being for the sake of its natural end, the realization of its perfection. The<br />

acorn, for example, comes into being<br />

for the sake of the oak tree. It is difficult<br />

to understand how something<br />

can have both an end of its genesis and an end<br />

teleology.4<br />

of its existence, given the common<br />

understanding<br />

of Aristotle's<br />

Moreover, Aristotle speaks even of artificial things as having ends peculiar to<br />

themselves. The shoe has two uses, one "peculiar to itself," the other as an<br />

article of exchange, although the shoe "did not come into being<br />

for the sake<br />

of<br />

exchange"<br />

(1257313). While man produces an artifact for an end peculiar<br />

to itself, he can make it serve a variety of ends. And that variety<br />

of ends<br />

includes ends that are higher than the end peculiar to the artifact. The shoe's<br />

end as an article of exchange is in fact higher than the end peculiar to the shoe.<br />

Man exchanges shoes for other items, and that exchange frees him from having<br />

to provide those items by his own labor. Similarly, the first associations, which<br />

take place naturally rather than by choice (1252326-27), come to have pur<br />

poses higher than those contained in their origins. The association of man and<br />

woman is for the sake of generation (1252326-27),<br />

man's "merely daily<br />

and the household satisfies<br />

needs"<br />

(1252^4-17). By the end of Book I, however,<br />

Aristotle says that the highest concern of the head of a household is the educa<br />

tion of its members in virtue (i259bi8-22). So too do the master and slave<br />

come together for the sake of "security" (1252331), but Aristotle ends his dis<br />

cussion of<br />

slavery by observing that slavery<br />

allows the master to turn to politics<br />

and philosophy<br />

(1255D3). Ends other than those implied in the origins can<br />

control development, since development can be modified<br />

by human choice.<br />

The end of the city<br />

also can be modified in the course of its development.<br />

Nature may<br />

not be so benevolent as to incline men to come together for the<br />

sake of<br />

living well, but nature is flexible enough to allow men to do<br />

so.5<br />

2. All references in parentheses, unless otherwise noted, are to Aristotle's Politics. The trans<br />

lations are mine.<br />

3. Ross, p. 328; Barker, p. 268; Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on the Politics, trans. Ernest<br />

L. Fortin and Peter D. O'Neill, in Medieval Political Philosophy, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin<br />

Mahdi (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1972), p. 308.<br />

4. But see Aristotle's account of two "actualities" in De Anima, 4i2a-b.<br />

5. Aristotle accounts for moral virtue in a similar way in the Nicomachean Ethics: "the virtues<br />

come into being neither by nature nor contrary to<br />

nature"<br />

1103824-25. The virtues are not the<br />

actualization of a potential, as seeing is the actualization of sight; because we have sight, we see.<br />

whereas because we practice the moral virtues, we become morally virtuous. On the other hand,<br />

since we can acquire the moral virtues, they are not contrary to nature. We can train ourselves to


things,"<br />

The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition 173<br />

This conclusion might seem to run counter to Aristotle's argument that man<br />

is a political animal. Nature does nothing in vain, and man possesses speech,<br />

Aristotle argues. Speech is unlike mere voice, which indicates pleasure and<br />

pain. Other animals make one another aware of these sensations through voice.<br />

Only speech, however, can indicate the advantageous and the harmful, and<br />

therefore the just and the The unjust.6 city is the association in which men use<br />

their unique faculty<br />

of speech to indicate these things to one another (1253310-<br />

18). Later in Book I, Aristotle maint3ins that what attracts animals as pleasant<br />

benefits them (1256326-27). Animals do not need speech because their pleasure<br />

is their good. For msn, in contrast, speech about the advsntsgeous is necessary<br />

because the pleasant can be harmful. Man thus cannot be guided simply by the<br />

naturally pleasant, but needs instead speech for his perfection. The teaching<br />

that man is a rational (and hence political) animal implies that nature has failed<br />

to provide man with his good, although it has allowed him reason in order to<br />

discover it. Nature's limited providence becomes man's opportunity.<br />

The question of the providence of nature underlies Aristotle's discussion of<br />

slavery. Before arguing that natural slaves exist, Aristotle reveals that slaves<br />

are advantageous, even necessary, to man. If there are no natural slaves, nature<br />

has not been provident. The beneficence of nature therefore turns on the exist<br />

ence of natural slaves.<br />

Early in the Politics, Aristotle describes the natural ruler as the one who<br />

mind"<br />

"can foresee with his and the natural slave as the one who "can do with<br />

his body" what the ruler foresees with his mind (1252332-33). It is a mistake,<br />

Aristotle argues, to identify the slave with the female, ss the barbarians do.<br />

Nature does not act "in a niggardly way"; it makes "one thing for one [pur<br />

pose]."<br />

Each being has one work rather than many, so that each may be<br />

perfected (125232-4). The barbarians are not fully aware of nature's abundance.<br />

However, in the beginning of his discussion of nstursl slavery, Aristotle ob<br />

served that the head of a family<br />

needs tools to accomplish his work:<br />

Every assistant is as it were a tool that serves for several tools; for if every tool could<br />

perform its own work when ordered, or by seeing what to do in advance, like they<br />

say of the statues of Daedalus and the tripods of Hephaestus, if shuttles wove and<br />

become courageous, but we cannot train a stone to move upwards NE, I I03ai4-H03b7. Thomas<br />

Aquinas also notes the similarity<br />

between the moral virtues "acquired through human<br />

cities "founded by human industry," p. 311.<br />

exercis<br />

and<br />

6. Aristotle's distinction between speech and voice does not depend on a complete disjunction<br />

between the pleasant and the advantageous.<br />

By the advantageous Aristotle might mean pleasure<br />

obtained through restraint and reflection rather than in an immediate sense.<br />

Moreover, how does the just and the unjust follow from the advantageous and the harmful?<br />

Thomas comments: "Human speech<br />

signifies what is useful and what is harmful. It follows<br />

from this that it signifies the just and the unjust. For justice and injustice consist in this, that some<br />

people are treated equally or unequally as regards useful and harmful p. 310. See also<br />

Laurence Berns, "Rational Animal Political Animal: Nature and Convention in Human Speech<br />

and<br />

Politics,"<br />

The Review of Politics 38 (April 1976), pp. 177-78.


174 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

quills played harps of themselves, master craftsmen would have no need of assistants,<br />

and masters no need of slaves [I253b33-i254ai].<br />

Aristotle states here that a slave must perform a variety<br />

slave, if he is to be a good one, has a certain complexity;<br />

of functions. The<br />

even if he has been<br />

made<br />

by nature for one job alone, he is not restricted to one job. Nature<br />

is acting "in a niggardly<br />

way,"<br />

and certain tasks would be peformed more<br />

perfectly if they were man's sole occupation. Nevertheless man has become<br />

flexible; he is able to accomplish more than one task. Moverover, foresight is a<br />

condition of flexibility. Because tools cannot foresee what to do in advance,<br />

masters need slaves.<br />

By implication, a good slave foresees what should be done<br />

in the situation, and acts accordingly. He performs different tasks when he<br />

exercises foresight.<br />

Aristotle lets us see that a useful slave foresees what should be done without<br />

depending on his master, or that he possesses some of the competence that<br />

defines the master. To the extent that a slave is truly useful, he is less a<br />

natural slave. Although Aristotle implies that slaves are useful in production,<br />

for example, weaving, he proceeds to assert that a slave is a tool for action<br />

rather than for production (125438). Tools for action are articles of property,<br />

and articles of<br />

property belong to another (125439-11). In spite of Aristotle's<br />

suggestions concerning<br />

his productive<br />

capacity<br />

master.<br />

the independence of the slave<br />

his foresight as well as<br />

Aristotle refers us to his complete dependence on his<br />

Aristotle next says that although the master is the master of the slave, he<br />

does not<br />

belong to the slave in the way<br />

that the slave belongs to the master<br />

(125439-13). But would anyone suppose thst the msster belongs to the slsve?<br />

In ssserting the contrary, Aristotle brings up the issue of the msster's depen<br />

dence. From time to time in Book I, Aristotle identifies the n3tursl msster with<br />

the free msn (for ex3mple, i254b28-29). Slsve is the opposite of both. But<br />

since the msster needs the slsve, 3S Aristotle indicstes in the course of<br />

defining<br />

the nsture of the slsve, could the msster be simply independent or free?<br />

Hsving defined "the nsture of the<br />

slsve,"<br />

Aristotle ssks "whether there is<br />

snyone who is by nsture 3 slave and whether it is advsntsgeous 3nd just for<br />

slave"<br />

snyone to be s (1254318-19). The 3nswer to the former question would<br />

seem to imply the snswer to the htter: if there is s nstursl slsve, by definition<br />

it is sdvsntageous and just for him to be a slave, since he nsturslly belongs<br />

to snother. Aristotle pursues his question<br />

"by looking to<br />

srgume<br />

snd<br />

"by<br />

lesrning from whst hsppens" (1254321-22).<br />

Aristotle observes that there is ruling snd<br />

being ruled throughout "sllnsture<br />

"In every composite thing, where msny<br />

things combine to mske 3 common<br />

one,"<br />

there is something ruling snd something ruled. Aristotle gives exsmples:<br />

the soul rules the body, the mind the psssions, the msle the femsle, snd msn


theory,"<br />

. are<br />

animal-like"<br />

ruled"<br />

The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition 175<br />

the lower animsls. The observstion about composites, however, cannot decide<br />

the issue, which is whether any<br />

two men form such a composite. Aristotle<br />

ststes thst "sll men, who differ ss grestly as the body from the soul, snd the<br />

bessts from msn,<br />

.<br />

by nsture slsves, for whom it is best to be<br />

(i 254b 1 6-20). Aristotle still does not demonstrate the existence of nstursl<br />

slsves, but he is further elsborating the definition. But the definition is making<br />

the concept of a natural slave all the more problematic. If the master has a<br />

body as well as a soul and the slave has a soul as well as a body, how could<br />

the master differ from the slave as much as the soul from the body? Strictly<br />

speaking, for the master and the slave to reproduce the difference between the<br />

soul and the body, the master would have to be completely soul and the slsve<br />

completely body. If we hsd resson to suspect that the natural slave would not<br />

be useful to his msster, our suspicion is now confirmed: whst could be more<br />

useless thsn s desd slsve for s msster who, hsving no body, hss no needs a<br />

slave could satisfy? Aristotle immediately underlines the difficulty by telling us<br />

that the slave does "share in<br />

possess it (i254b23-25).7<br />

resson,"<br />

but only so ss to perceive it rather thsn<br />

At lsst turning to "whst hsppens," Aristotle ssserts thst nature intends to<br />

make the bodies of free men different from those of slaves, the latter "strong<br />

for necessary<br />

service,"<br />

the former "erect and unserviceable for such things, but<br />

useful for political life." Unfortunately, nature does not "often" (literally, "msny<br />

times") fulfill its intention. Slsves often hsve the bodies of free men, while<br />

free men often have souls but not bodies of free men (i254b33~34). In other<br />

words, if we consider only the type of body required, natural slaves do not<br />

often make good slaves,<br />

while free men often<br />

do.8<br />

In light of the development of the argument, Aristotle's conclusion is over<br />

stated: "It is clear therefore that some are<br />

by nature free men, and others<br />

by<br />

nature<br />

slave"<br />

(125531-2; emphasis mine). It is not surprising thst Aristotle now<br />

7. Barker finds that Aristotle cannot maintain body"<br />

consistently both that "the slave is a mere<br />

and that he possesses "the semi-rational part of the<br />

soul"<br />

and is able to listen to the voice of<br />

reason, p. 365. Barker argues that many of Aristotle's statements about natural slavery vitiate<br />

his theory<br />

of natural slavery. His theory, according to Barker, is like all false theories: "a false<br />

theory must always fall into inconsistency, if it deals with all the facts and data of its subject; and<br />

some of these facts must contradict the assumptions on which it<br />

goes,"<br />

p. 368. Ross comes to a<br />

similar conclusion: "Aristotle's treatment of the question contains<br />

implicitly the refutation of his<br />

p. 242. Mulgan also notes the inconsistency between Aristotle's "seeing the slave as<br />

wholly<br />

physical and<br />

and his granting that "the slave has even the emotional and<br />

desiring<br />

soul,"<br />

part of the human p. 43. See also p. 41. Mulgan observes "If [Aristotle] has given one<br />

of the classic defences of genetic or racial supremacy, he has done it in a way<br />

that makes<br />

refutation easy; not all such doctrines are so refuted,"<br />

readily p. 43.<br />

8. What exactly is the difference between the bodies of free men and those of slaves? When<br />

Aristotle says that the bodies of free men are "useful for political<br />

life,"<br />

he divides the occupations<br />

of political life into service in war and in peace, I254b29~34. Is the body<br />

of the warrior not<br />

useful for ploughing the fields? If the master (free man) subdues the slave in war, must he not be<br />

enough<br />

strong to perform the tasks of a slave ?


willing"<br />

176 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

concedes to the conventionslists thst some slsves 3re so by convention only 3nd<br />

(I25533ff.).9<br />

not by<br />

nsture<br />

We hsve resched the S3me result when considering both the intellectual<br />

C3p3city 3nd the body needed by<br />

the slsve. The most useful sl3ve is the msn<br />

excellent in mind snd body, who slso hsppens to be perfectly loysl. The ststues<br />

of Dsedslus, which Aristotle mentioned earlier, are useless because they run<br />

away. Nature "often" makes men with the souls of slaves, but with bodies<br />

unservicesble for necesssry work, Aristotle ssid. While such s msn might<br />

benefit from being ruled, s master would not benefit from ruling<br />

him. On the<br />

level of the master-slave relationship, there is no common good.<br />

Aristotle spesks of the friendship<br />

thst csn exist between s msster snd a<br />

slave when the slavery is natural. When slsvery is only "by convention snd by<br />

force,"<br />

there can be no friendship (I255bi5-i6). When discussing acquisition,<br />

Aristotle maintains that war csn be justly employed "sgsinst men who sre by<br />

nsture fit to be ruled but who sre not<br />

(i256b25). The friendship<br />

between msster snd slsve therefore seems tenuous. It might sppesr to be pro<br />

moted by the s educstion of the slsve in useful skills snd in virtue, ss<br />

Aristotle recommends (i255b25ff.; i26ob2-3), except thst ss the slsve be<br />

comes more competent snd virtuous he is more obviously<br />

not s nstursl slsve.<br />

Aristotle not only fails to give a conclusive argument for the existence of natural<br />

slavery, he also advises masters to treat their slaves in a wsy thst prepsres them<br />

for freedom.<br />

If indeed there sre no nstural slaves, who both benefit their masters and<br />

benefit from being ruled, nature has failed to provide for msn. Nature is a harsh<br />

master: man is needy by nature, and he cannot satisfy<br />

his needs without violence<br />

and injustice to others. The advantsgeous is not<br />

necesssrily the just. Man is not<br />

simply free to pursue the good life: not only<br />

must he provide the necessities<br />

that nature does not provide for him, but he must do so<br />

by enslaving others<br />

who do not deserve to be enslaved. He cannot pursue the advantageous and<br />

the just, naturally good ends, without violating the one or the other. His nature<br />

therefore cannot lead him simply toward his good. His dependence on nature<br />

recalls Aristotle's description of unnatural slavery. The natural is not simply<br />

the good. Slavery, however, goes some distance toward freeing<br />

man from<br />

merely necessary existence. At the end of his discussion of slavery, Aristotle<br />

mentions how greatly advantageous slavery is: the possession of slaves frees a<br />

man so that he can engage in politics and philosophy (i255b37). Since slavery<br />

makes politics and philosophy possible, the question<br />

implicitly arises whether<br />

politics and philosophy can relieve msn of his unnatural slsvery<br />

to nature.<br />

9. Barker notes that Aristotle's distinction between natural and conventional slaves would<br />

diminish the number of slaves. "Aristotle's doctrine," Barker writes, "may seem to us to defend<br />

slavery: it is quite possible that it struck his contemporaries as also an<br />

attack,"<br />

p. 369.


pleass<br />

The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition 111<br />

II<br />

The lsrgest part of Book I is on scquisition. Aristotle discusses the house<br />

holds, the smallest associations in the city, and the relationships within the<br />

households. He discusses the master's relationship to his slsve, who, as an<br />

article of property, is msn's mesns for sction or life (125432-8). While the<br />

job of the hesd of the family is to use property, is it slso his job to scquire<br />

property? Aristotle thus raises the question of the source or origin of msn's life<br />

or sctivity. Does s msn provide for himself his mesns of living, or is he<br />

dependent on<br />

something external? Aristotle now brings up the possibility that a<br />

beneficent natures provides man with what he needs. The issue underlying the<br />

discussion of slavery, the beneficence of nature,<br />

now becomes explicit.<br />

Book I raises the question of nature, and of man's relationship<br />

Aristotle speaks of what pertains "throughout sll<br />

Aristotle imitstes Hippodamus,<br />

text of "the whole<br />

to nature.<br />

nsture"<br />

(1254333). In this<br />

who also tried to place politics within the con<br />

nature"<br />

(i267b69). Hippodamus apparently applied principles<br />

of mathematics to politics, and neglected the heterogeneity of nature.10 Aristotle,<br />

in contrast, sees not<br />

only<br />

that there are rulers and ruled throughout nature but<br />

also that there are<br />

"many different kinds of ruling and being<br />

But is there some order or<br />

unity<br />

ruled"<br />

(1254325).<br />

that pervsdes the diversity? Thus far in the<br />

discussion of slsvery there hsve appeared men who enslave and others who are<br />

enslaved, but no sssursnce, or even likelihood, thst those who sre enslsved sre<br />

nsturslly inferior to their enslsvers. Hsving<br />

good between master and slsve, Aristotle turns directly<br />

suggested that there is no common<br />

to the question raised<br />

by thst suggestion, the question of the goodness of nsture.<br />

In discussing the scquisition of food, Aristotle gives sn srgument for nature's<br />

providence. Nature provides many different kinds of food, and has differentisted<br />

the wsys of life of the animals by giving them different faculties for obtaining<br />

different foods. Some eat grass, others meat; some are nomadic, others solitary.<br />

So too with men, their lives differ greatly, because they<br />

obtain food in different<br />

ways. There are nomadic herdsmen, hunters of various kinds, and farmers.<br />

This argument for nature's providence indicates man's neediness: man's man<br />

ner of life itself results from the way<br />

in which he acquires the necessities.<br />

And need leads to injustice: Aristotle includes "piracy" among<br />

of acquisition (1256336)." He tells us that men sometimes "live<br />

combining<br />

the natural modes<br />

by<br />

the vsrious pursuits, "supplementing the more deficient life when it<br />

10. Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1964), p. 19.<br />

11. It is difficult to see how piracy could be a just mode of acquisition. Is piracy the violent<br />

taking from others what they have acquired, whether through nature's providence, or through their<br />

own efforts? Or perhaps piracy refers to the enslaving of men. But if there are no natural slaves, as<br />

I have argued, then piracy in this sense also is unjust.


acquired.12<br />

gain."<br />

themselves"<br />

teleology"<br />

moves<br />

178 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

hsppens to fall short in being<br />

how to provide for himself,<br />

self-sufficing"<br />

(I265b3~5). Man must choose<br />

and both his independence and pleasure increase<br />

as he takes less of what nature provides and more of whst he scquires through<br />

his own efforts. Aristotle observes thst nsture bestows food on all, just as<br />

animals bring forth with their young enough sustenance for them "until they are<br />

able to provide for<br />

(I256bn-I2;<br />

emphasis mine). But he never<br />

theless concludes that nature provides for the mature animal as well; moreover,<br />

nature provides "all things for the sake of<br />

mesn that there is no natural barrier to man's<br />

scquiring<br />

subdue, for he immedistely<br />

being<br />

Not only is hunting<br />

wsr, in esses where "those of msnkind designed by<br />

to submit to it" (T256b25-27).<br />

man"<br />

(I256b22). He sppesrs to<br />

whst he is sble to<br />

indicates that man's natural provision might resist<br />

s nstursl mode of acquisition, but also<br />

nature for subjection refuse<br />

Aristotle hss discussed the nstursl modes of scquisition other thsn trade<br />

herding, fsrming, piracy, fishing, snd hunting<br />

(i256bi-2). These do not nec<br />

essarily bring men into association with one another. They may<br />

be undertaken<br />

alone. He concluded his discussion of these natural modes of acquisition<br />

by in<br />

cluding war among them (i256b25-27). Exchange, however, obviously brings<br />

men into contact with one another. Exchange is natural, Aristotle says, for men<br />

must obtain from others what<br />

they happen to lack, while they<br />

grows out of<br />

ex-<br />

they have in surplus (1257328). But the invention of money<br />

chsnge, for it is s more convenient means of<br />

exchanging goods. Along<br />

exchange what<br />

with the<br />

use of money came associstions of men in which men sgreed to 3bide by sn<br />

suthoritstive<br />

stamping<br />

of coins which determine their value (1 2573358".). The<br />

Greek word for money, nomisma, is derived from the word for convention, or<br />

kw, nomos (i257bio; see Nicomachean Ethics, 1133329-32). The invention<br />

of money therefore strengthens the bond between trsders. They<br />

now hsve<br />

sgreements or conventions thst regulste their common sctivity. Trade, slong<br />

with the invention of money, sppesrs instruments! in forming bonds smong<br />

12. Barker takes Aristotle's statement that nature provides all things for man out of context,<br />

and then tries to excuse it: "it was only natural that early thought should indulge itself in such<br />

naivete,"<br />

p. 376. Barker nevertheless notes the distinction between this "external<br />

Aristotle's "fine and internal conception of teleology, in which man is the end of other things, not<br />

as their 'destined<br />

p. 376. See also Ross, p. 126.<br />

eater'<br />

but as the final aim towards the production of which nature<br />

13. Harry Jaffa observes that at the center of natural acquisition is hunting, a species of war,<br />

and at the center of unnatural acquisition is trade, culminating<br />

"Aristotle,"<br />

modes of acquisition.<br />

History of Political Philosophy, ed. Leo Strauss and Joseph<br />

Cropsey (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1963), p. 80. See also Joseph Cropsey, Political Philosophy<br />

and<br />

in usury. War and trade are alternative<br />

and the Issues of Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977), p. 39, on "the transfor<br />

mation of the predation of war into the salutary predation of peace, the mercenary<br />

and<br />

quest for increase


nature<br />

The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition 179<br />

Why does Aristotle nevertheless describe moneymsking<br />

as sn unnstursl mode<br />

of scquisition? In concluding his discussion of nstural acquisition, Aristotle<br />

explained that natural acquisition is limited by its end, living and eventuslly<br />

living well, just as any tool is limited by<br />

its end or function (i256b28-39).<br />

But now Aristotle argues thst men seek to scquire unlimited smounts of money<br />

becsuse they<br />

seek life rather than the good life. And since the desire for life<br />

is unlimited, men desire without limit the means to life (i257b24-30). But is<br />

the desire for life not limited by its end, life, as Aristotle first indicated?<br />

Appsrently, s desire for unlimited life accounts for unlimited moneymaking.<br />

Unlimited moneymaking is premised on the denial of mortality. And to deny<br />

one's mortality is to deny one's corporeality. Aristotle refers to those who think<br />

that money is "entirely a convention, and in no way by nature, because it is<br />

useless for the necessities, snd a man rich in money may lack the necessities<br />

of<br />

subsistence"<br />

(1257b 10-14). And there is the story of Midas, who came<br />

close to dying of hunger due to his insatiable desire for money (1257^5-17).<br />

Moneymaking is an unnatural mode of acquisition, then, because it removes<br />

man from the natural world of necessity, corporeality, and death. Moreover,<br />

with the advent of money,<br />

as articles of exchange.<br />

Money<br />

particular items such as shoes are no longer needed<br />

can take the place of all the particular goods<br />

sought through exchange; it reduces a variety<br />

of goods to a single measure.<br />

Men have invented a universal thst sppesrs to remove them from inss-<br />

nsture,<br />

much ss nsture is composed of s vsriety of entities, irreducible to one snother.<br />

Aristotle gives s second resson<br />

why<br />

men desire unlimited smounts of money.<br />

Men identify the enjoyment of bodily plessures with living well, snd conse<br />

quently<br />

seek sn unlimited smount of the mesns to these plessures (125832-8).<br />

The life of moneymaking thus blinds msn to his nstural neediness st the ssme<br />

time thst it binds him sll the more to his body. It is therefore unnstursl in<br />

this further sense ss well: 3 skve to bodily plessures,<br />

msn does not rise to the<br />

msnly independence of politicsl rule th3t chsrscterizes politics st its best.<br />

Of the forms of moneymsking, usury is "the most contrary to<br />

Money "came into being<br />

for the sake of<br />

but interest increases the<br />

amount of money itself (125805-6). We should not suppose, however, thst<br />

usury is unnstural because it uses money for an end other than the end for the<br />

sake of which money came into being. The shoe, we remember, came into<br />

it was used<br />

being for an end peculisr to itself, but before the advent of money<br />

for the sake of exchange as well as for its original end (1257313). And the<br />

city too comes into being for one end, but exists for a higher one. Aristotle<br />

does not take his bearings entirely from the origins.<br />

Usury is s psrsdigm for<br />

the unnstural evidently becsuse through usury<br />

the srtificisl comes from the<br />

artificisl, snd therefore hss no origin in nature.<br />

Usury even more radically<br />

than money removes man from the limits imposed by nature's heterogeneity,<br />

since everything that naturally comes into being does so from some particular


nothing.14<br />

slone"<br />

180 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

thing. But usury<br />

makes<br />

something While for Aristotle the<br />

origins do not<br />

necessarily completely control development, usury denies the<br />

come from<br />

origins sltogether.15<br />

Hsving "sufficiently distinguished [the forms of scquisition] in order to<br />

understsnd them," Aristotle will discuss them "in regsrd to their<br />

use"<br />

(i258b9-<br />

n). He divides the nstursl mode into its branches. Then, of the mode involving<br />

commerce, there is exchsnge, usury, snd lsbor for hire. The lstter includes<br />

the workers without srts, "who sre useful<br />

by<br />

mesns of their bodies<br />

(i258b28). The nstural slaves by definition (1252334) are now working for<br />

hire. The convention of money has made it possible for men to pay<br />

other men<br />

for necessary<br />

services. In order to pay other men, the head of the family of<br />

course must possess more<br />

money than is necessary<br />

for the purchase of needed<br />

goods. His extra money permits him to employ others to do necessary tasks<br />

and therewith to free himself for other occupations. Aristotle now tells us there<br />

is a third mode of acquisition,<br />

with elements of both the natural and the com<br />

mercial kind. He gives the examples of<br />

felling timber, an activity<br />

that does<br />

violence to nature in order to use it for human purposes, and mining, an<br />

activity that takes from nature what it does not readily provide. I believe that<br />

we should be reminded of Aristotle's political science,<br />

which must do violence<br />

to man's natural inclinations in order to raise him to his place at the peak of<br />

nature.<br />

Aristotle says thst he will lesve s detsiled account of these modes of acquisi<br />

tion to others. He recommends that "someone collect the scattered accounts<br />

of the successful methods used<br />

by<br />

honoring<br />

moneym<br />

which "will benefit those<br />

moneymaking"<br />

(125933-6). One such method is monopoly. Aristotle<br />

gives the example of a man who made one hundred talents out of his fifty.<br />

Far from condemning this making of money out of money, Aristotle emphasizes<br />

that the method can be used politically. While he shows that a private use of<br />

monopoly is harmful to a tyrant's affairs (1259330-32), he concludes that "to<br />

know [how to secure a monopoly] is useful for statesmen slso, for msny cities<br />

need such mesns of money"<br />

scquiring (1259335-37). Whst divorces msn from<br />

is now recommended if it csn be subordinsted to politicsl<br />

nsture 's heterogeneity<br />

ends.<br />

The first psrt of Book I is sbout msn's natural neediness, as it is revealed in<br />

the human institution of slavery. The second part of Book I is about man's sep<br />

arating himself from nature through unnatural modes of acquisition. Aristotle's<br />

suggestion for the politicsl use of commerce, which concludes his discussion of<br />

scquisition, provides a transition to the last part of Book I, in which Aristotle<br />

14. Barker admits that Aristotle objects to usury on the ground that it makes something come<br />

from nothing. But Barker believes that this is a false inference from the peculiarity<br />

of the Greek<br />

word for interest. For his discussion, see pp. 385-387.<br />

15. Jaffa suggests that Aristotle's praise of just war and his censure of trade are due to the<br />

fact that the root of injustice is the abolition of the limits upon<br />

bodily desires. "Perhaps the extreme<br />

of trade, culminating in usury, is more akin to the abolition of those limits than is p. 80.


The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition 181<br />

returns to the family,<br />

s reminder of one's natural origins. He now claims that<br />

the family can be understood properly only<br />

The family remains an integral part of the city, but the city<br />

in the context of political life.<br />

exists for the sake<br />

of the good life. Politicsl life therefore frees man from his dependence on brute<br />

nature without uprooting<br />

him from the natural world.<br />

Before discussing the other relations within the family, Aristotle returns to<br />

the relation between the master and slave. Since the head of the<br />

family is more<br />

concerned about the virtue or excellence of its humsn members thsn of its<br />

insnimste property, the question of the virtue of the slsve arises. Does the<br />

slsve hsve only the virtue of s tool or a servant, or also such virtues as courage,<br />

justice, and moderation (i259b2i-26)? Aristotle has this dilemma: if the slave<br />

can be virtuous in the latter sense, he would be a human being, but Aristotle<br />

has had to describe him as less than human in order to justify<br />

calling<br />

slavery. After<br />

our attention to the advantages of commerce and of the statesman's use<br />

of commerce, Aristotle thus returns to the question of the slave's humanity.<br />

It now appears that the slave is capable of moral virtue, although Aristotle<br />

refrains from undermining his earlier argument altogether by maintaining that<br />

the slave is capable of moral virtue only in a sense. There are different kinds<br />

of courage and moderation. There is the virtue of a slave, and that of a free<br />

man, just as there is the virtue of a msn,<br />

snd that of a woman (i26oa2-28).<br />

But does not the diversity within humanity, and therewith within the concept<br />

of human excellence, call into question the unity of the good life? Book I ends<br />

with Aristotle's inability<br />

to speak of the virtue of women and children without<br />

considering the particular regime in which they live ( 1 260b 10-18). Presumably,<br />

the same applies to the virtue of a man. While virtue appears inseparable from<br />

political life, political life itself assumes a multiplicity<br />

of forms. Virtue varies<br />

from regime to regime. A consideration of politics<br />

evidently<br />

recslls to msn the<br />

irreducible nstursl diversity thst commerce tended to deny. The good life st<br />

which Aristotle ssid cities simed must slwsys be lived within the context of s<br />

particular regime. Aristotle's argument suggests by the end of Book I that there<br />

is a variety<br />

of good lives.<br />

16<br />

16. As we have seen, Aristotle distinguishes the rule of male over female from the rule of<br />

master over slave. CSee p. 173 of this paper.) Nevertheless both kinds of rule are defined as the rule<br />

of the naturally superior over the naturally inferior. Aristotle says, "The male is naturally fitter to<br />

nature"<br />

command than the female, except where there is some departure from (I259b2, emphasis<br />

mine). Aristotle classifies the rule of male over female as political rule, although the male's rule<br />

is permanent and political rule is the rule of equals who take turns ruling. Where equals take<br />

turns ruling, Aristotle observes, rulers try to indicate some sign of their superiority, such as modes<br />

of address or titles of respect, in a way reminiscent of Amasis' footpan (I258b-I259a). According<br />

to Herodotus, Amasis made his golden footpan into a god in imitation of his own situation: a<br />

former utensil had become an object of reverence, just as Amasis, formerly<br />

a subject, had become<br />

king (Herodotus, ii.172). The male's preeminence over the female, it appears, resembles the pre<br />

Amasis'<br />

eminence of footpan. Again nature is improvident, since it fails to provide men with inferior<br />

and obedient wives, just as it fails to provide slaves. If nature's improvidence again could be seen<br />

as man's opportunity, it is only by looking beyond the practical demands of life.


woman,"<br />

observes.17<br />

same."<br />

182 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Aristotle finds support for the diversity<br />

poet said, "Silence gives grace to<br />

of virtues from<br />

Aristotle<br />

Sophocles'<br />

Ajax. The<br />

Yet it is the<br />

maddened Ajax who said this, when his wife Tecmessa questioned his ac<br />

tivities. It is a madman, Aristotle might be saying, who does not listen to<br />

the good advice of a womsn.<br />

Yet Aristotle sppesrs to endorse Ajsx's ststement. When would silence be<br />

sppropriste? At the beginning of Book I, Aristotle tells when speech becomes<br />

sppropriste: the political community is s shsring in speech, for speech re<br />

veals the advantageous and the hsrmful,<br />

snd therefore the just and the unjust<br />

(1253314-16). The conjunction of the advsntsgeous and the just, ss revesled<br />

by speech, is the bssis of the politicsl community. But Aristotle's discussion of<br />

slsvery<br />

revesled the disjunction between the sdvsntsgeous snd the just. In<br />

justices may be unavoidable in establishing civil societies. And commerce, not<br />

simply<br />

advantageous for man because it distsnces him from his nstursl world<br />

at the ssme time it further binds him to his body snd its plessures, makes<br />

relief from the gross injustice of<br />

slavery possible. Until the existence of cities,<br />

the advantageous and the just for man appear to conflict. And past cities have<br />

probably existed for the sake of survival, or wealth.<br />

They<br />

are not ciites that<br />

deserve the name of cities (see i28ob7-8). Could Aristotle have thought that<br />

cities<br />

truly deserving<br />

to bring<br />

the name had not yet existed? And was it his chosen task<br />

such cities into existence through his political science? The grestest<br />

scquisition st issue in the Politics, then, is msnkind's scquisition of Aristotle's<br />

politicsl science. For it is in Aristotle's speech thst the end of the city's<br />

existence, ss opposed to the end of its genesis, mskes its first sppesrsnce<br />

smong<br />

msnkind.18<br />

A womsnly silence msy be sppropriate, especially<br />

if un<br />

womanly speech, like Tecmessa's, attacks a man's pride as he goes about the<br />

business of<br />

defending his honor. Aristotle's politics, after all, centers on political<br />

17. Sophocles, Ajax, 293.<br />

18. It might be objected that the end of the city's existence, the good life, first appeared in<br />

ancient cities that made piety the bond of their union. Such an objection depends on the ends served<br />

by religion. Aristotle associates veneration of the gods with the village stage of human development.<br />

When men were themselves ruled<br />

by a king they worshipped gods also ruled<br />

by a king; they<br />

likened the lives of the gods to their own (1252b). The stories of the gods thus support<br />

kingly<br />

rather than political rule:<br />

they indicate man's dependence and bondage rather than his self-suf<br />

ficiency and freedom. The good life at which the Aristotelian city aims, in this sense at least, must<br />

go beyond piety.<br />

It might be objected also that the end of the city's existence, the good life, first appeared not<br />

in Aristotle's speech but in Plato's. Although distinguishing Aristotle's political science from Plato's<br />

philosophizing about politics is beyond the scope of this paper, the following suggestion, based on<br />

a passage in Book I, is in order. Aristotle begins the politics with a criticism of those who<br />

believe that "political rule, kingly rule, household management, and despotic rule are the<br />

These men also believe that there is no difference between a small city and a large household<br />

(125238-14). It is commonly understood that Aristotle is referring to Socrates and Plato. But for<br />

Aristotle, political rule, as opposed to despotic rule, is essential to the city's aiming<br />

at the good<br />

life. From Aristotle's point of view, then, Plato did not understand the good life for which cities<br />

might exist.


The Good Life, Slavery, and Acquisition 183<br />

rule and freedom, for political rule is that of free men over free men (I277bi6).<br />

Awareness of the degree of mankind's dependence on Aristotle for these things<br />

may not promote the manly independence necessary<br />

life.<br />

for nondespotic political<br />

Ajax commits suicide. Tecmessa tries to prevent his death.19 When she is<br />

unsuccessful, she laments his rashness and<br />

thereby<br />

affirms the goodness of<br />

life.20<br />

Suicide presupposes a distsnce from life, or sufficient detschment from<br />

life to discern that it is not worth living at all costs. Perhaps it is this detachment<br />

thst allows men to try to overcome nstursl necessity, to enslsve others, snd to<br />

found cities. Yet if politicsl life were<br />

simply unsstisfying, if it provided msn<br />

no sccess bsck to s nstursl world, suicide might be s proper response to the<br />

humsn condition. Aristotle intends to bring into existence cities,<br />

or communities<br />

that provide some degree of good living. He is sgsin playing the woman's part,<br />

although with<br />

considerably more insight than Tecmessa, and with a large degree<br />

of manly assertion.<br />

19. When Tecmessa discovers the danger to his life, she asks the chorus to help her find him:<br />

"Come, let's hurry. No time to sit, if we wish to save a man who is eager to die," Ajax, 81 1-12.<br />

20. Ajax, 891-903.


Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life<br />

Catherine H. Zuckert<br />

Carleton College<br />

In The Human Condition, Hannah Arendt attempts to revive the ancient<br />

notion that the distinctively<br />

human lies in political action. She thus reminds<br />

her readers of Aristotle's famous dictum (Politics 125333-5)<br />

that man is s<br />

politicsl animal<br />

and its essentially controversial character at the same time she<br />

explicitly dissociates herself from the ancient philosophic understanding. Unlike<br />

the Latin commentators who reveal their misunderstanding by reducing political<br />

to social, she recognizes, Plato and Aristotle retain a sense of the distinctively<br />

public life of the polis. Nevertheless, these ancient philosophers establish the<br />

tradition which subordinates practice to contemplation or philosophy; and it is<br />

this hierarchy<br />

that she wishes to<br />

challenge.1<br />

As Leo Strauss has brilliantly<br />

shown, Plato does establish both the viability and the superiority of philosophy<br />

as a way of life politics.2<br />

by showing the limits of But the subordination of<br />

politics to philosophy is not so clear in the works of Aristotle. In the Nichomachean<br />

Ethics, he suggests three different peaks of human excellence mag<br />

nanimity, justice, and contemplation. And in the Politics, he presents the life of<br />

the statesman or jzofarixog more or less in its own terms, as a life worth<br />

choosing for its own sake or essentially a self-satisfying one.<br />

The picture Aristotle gives of political life differs, moreover, in important<br />

respects from the action Arendt praises. Although it is true that the Politics<br />

begins by showing that the polis does not emerge until or unless the neces<br />

sities of life are provided by the oikos, it is not true, as Arendt claims, that<br />

the polis is characterized by a<br />

sharp distinction between public and private.<br />

On the contrary, Aristotle shows that the regime (jioXixeia) shapes and so<br />

infuses all aspects of private life, especially the family<br />

not through totalitarian<br />

controls, of course, but rather by<br />

praise and blame expressed either in legisla<br />

tion or mere opinion. Second, political life as depicted by Aristotle is not<br />

"immortality" "distinction"<br />

animated<br />

simply by<br />

the desire for fame,<br />

or as Arendt<br />

clsims. Becsuse humsn life is characterized by<br />

several incommensurable needs,<br />

there is an enduring problem both of compenssting<br />

those who do. Politics essentislly concerns the question, who should<br />

providing the requirements and of<br />

rule, which is a question not merely of recognition or honor but ultimately of<br />

justice. Since this question can be answered only through complex snd con<br />

rationsl activity. The simple dis<br />

tinuing deliberstion, politics is sn inherently<br />

tinction between sction snd reason or theory does not fit: cpgovnoig includes<br />

1. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), pp.<br />

10, 17-18, 155-56.<br />

2. Leo Strauss, The City<br />

and Man (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1963), pp. 50-138.


186 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

both. Finslly, the fundsmentsl pluralism of humsn life thst Arendt herself<br />

stresses mskes it impossible for sll members of s community<br />

to psrticipste<br />

fully in public or politicsl decisions. Man ss a species may<br />

a meaning yet to be fully explained<br />

be political with<br />

but individual distinctions are products<br />

of chance (birth) and plsce (the division of lsbor). Only by<br />

abstraction and simplification can we equate voting<br />

means of a vast<br />

with the negotiations of a<br />

secretary of state as political participation. We do, as Arendt urges, need a<br />

political."<br />

better appreciation of "the<br />

As Aristotle shows, politics is both s<br />

more noble snd s more limited humsn endeavor thsn we generally recognize.<br />

Politics is not merely a "search" for power, according to Aristotle,<br />

nor does<br />

it chsrscterize sll humsn relstions or sssocistions. On the contrary, politicsl<br />

sctivity srises only<br />

sfter humsn beings meet their more fundsmental procreative<br />

and economic needs. Since the members of a polity<br />

must continue to produce<br />

new generations as well as to feed and defend themselves, the requirements of<br />

both family snd economic organization (the division of labor) limit the scope<br />

of political action. Aristotle shows, however, why neither purely<br />

social nor<br />

economic relations<br />

satisfy human beings. And in showing why political activity<br />

is both necessary and desirable, Aristotle reveals the reasons<br />

why every polit<br />

ical association constitutes or involves a "regime" (jzoXltelcx) ,<br />

ing<br />

that is, an order<br />

of disparate groups and activities in which some rule others. Through his<br />

discussion of regime Aristotle thus enables us to understand why political con<br />

flict endures, why<br />

all political activity and association is partisl, why there is<br />

never complete consensus or sgreement, snd thus why force is slwsys neces<br />

sary<br />

to maintain order.<br />

All human beings act from an attachment to their own existence, but they<br />

do not all define their existence in the same way. Msn's bssic concern to<br />

preserve his own life mskes economic considerations powerful in determining<br />

the wsy of life of individusls or communities (i 256329- I256b9), but economic<br />

considerations slone never suffice to explsin sny psrticulsr regime, thst is,<br />

humsn life sbove the level of subsistence, because the distribution of goods<br />

can be altered<br />

by force. The decision as to who rules is s decision ss to whst<br />

is most importsnt; since every human being values his own existence, even<br />

tends to overestimate his own importance, everyone in the community<br />

is not<br />

spt to sgree sbout who should rule. Some men seek honor rather thsn weslth,<br />

moreover; their desires csn be fulfilled only through being<br />

elevsted sbove<br />

others, and these sre the men most apt to engage in politics. Since most humsn<br />

beings hsve to devote most of their lives to scquiring<br />

the necessities of exis<br />

tence, very few will ever psrticipate fully in politics. The nature of any specific<br />

regime thus very<br />

much depends on the character and wisdom of the men who<br />

mske snd enforce the lsws. The fsct thst sll human beings and so rulers in<br />

particular act out of self-love (1267330-35) does not mean that all govern<br />

ment is necessarily oppressive or unjust. It does mean that it is extremely<br />

difficult to construct and maintain a regime which recognizes and gives due


"Aristotle."<br />

man"<br />

Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 187<br />

weight to all the different kinds of contributions or activities necessary<br />

to main<br />

tain a political 3ssociation. It requires deliberation, and such deliberative skill<br />

emerges only<br />

in the context and on the bssis of political experience.<br />

Aristotle's very first claim that the polis constitutes the highest and most<br />

comprehensive form of human association surely flies in the face of the modern<br />

liberal tendency to view the stste ss sepsrate and in some ways subordinate to<br />

society.3<br />

Yet our own experience in one of the least socialistic liberal democ<br />

racies ought to tesch us thst the lsw reaches into virtually all realms of pri<br />

vate endesvor, even when the object of the lsw is to protect freedom, the "right<br />

to<br />

privscy,"<br />

for example. Even before the emergence of the welfsre state,<br />

however, Alexis de Tocqueville showed thst the effects of Americsn democracy<br />

extend far beyond the institutions of government into economic enterprise, reli<br />

gion, all forms of intellectusl snd srtistic endesvor, the fsmily, and even the<br />

individual's conception of himself. If political influence is so pervasive, it is<br />

also fairly clear that it is not primarily or directly<br />

coercive. And Aristotle's<br />

second<br />

sweeping claim is that politicsl rule differs essentislly from both despo<br />

tism and patriarchal authority; the rule of s politikos<br />

(literally "political<br />

but usually translated statesman) is essentially different from that of a master<br />

and that of a father. Our tendency (stemming from Locke) to associate govern<br />

ment<br />

primarily with legislstion lesds us not only<br />

to underestimate the extent of<br />

political influence but also to conceive of political action<br />

primarily<br />

in terms<br />

of command snd enforcement. Since command and force are universal, we<br />

conclude, so is politics. Aristotle suggests, on the contrary, that understanding<br />

politics primarily in terms "power"<br />

of involves a fundamental misconception of<br />

the nature of political order.<br />

Politicsl order represents s compound of several different but equally<br />

neces<br />

sary kinds of association. If there are no people, there will be no polis. Politi<br />

cal order thus includes the male-femsle procrestive relation. If there is no<br />

food, there will be no people,<br />

so the existence of political order also requires<br />

the intelligent organization of labor to provide the necessary goods. Aristotle<br />

describes the intelligent organizstion of Isbor in terms of the msster-slave relation,<br />

becsuse the production of goods at<br />

anything more than individual sub<br />

sistence level requires s division of lsbor. The fact that there are necessary<br />

economic conditions for the emergence of political order also means that politics<br />

is not universal; men are not able to deliberate sbout the best way<br />

of life until<br />

their vitsl needs are met. Under unfavorable circumstsnces, it msy require sll<br />

their time and effort merely<br />

to survive.<br />

Unlike Marx, Aristotle insists that the first form of human sssociation, the<br />

family, consists in the merger of two different natural relations: the erotic,<br />

male-female or procreative relation as well as the master-slave, or economic<br />

in the narrower, modern sense, division of lsbor. Self-preservstion operates<br />

3. Harry V. Jaffa,<br />

in Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, ed.. History of Political<br />

Philosophy<br />

(Chicago: Rand McNally, 1972), PP- 65-68.


188 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

on a species as well as an individual level.<br />

"Barbarians"<br />

make the mistake of<br />

confusing the two distinct relations, Aristotle argues, when they<br />

trest women<br />

ss slsves. Procrestion is not simply snother form of production; the fsmily<br />

does not<br />

develop solely<br />

from the requirements of survivsl or need. On the con<br />

trary, Aristotle suggests, there is slwsys s positive sttrsction to life itself ss<br />

well as to other human beings st the root of every<br />

beings form family groups not merely from necessity<br />

humsn society. Human<br />

but also from desire.<br />

Once formed, however, the association affects both the constituent needs and<br />

desires. To maintain the family, and so give birth to future generations, sex<br />

uality<br />

must be restricted both with regsrd to partner and the number of progeny,<br />

while the need to produce snd provide<br />

grestly expsnds. The interplsy<br />

of the<br />

two roots of the most bssic form of humsn sssocistion is thus instructive ss to<br />

the nsture of the higher, more complex politicsl order. All humsn associations<br />

consist of several, irreducibly different parts or relations. Aristotle's approach<br />

to politics is thus both fundamentally pluralistic and fundamentally hierarchical.<br />

The concept of "regime" is central to his political science, because he understsnds<br />

politicsl order ss s compound or srticulstion of several, irreducibly<br />

different psrts. As sll parts of the household sre sffected or shaped<br />

by the<br />

requirements of raising future generations, so all parts of the political order are<br />

affected<br />

by the particular way<br />

of life the members of the polis seek to preserve.<br />

Once humsn beings meet their needs, Aristotle observes, their desires expsnd.<br />

They do not merely wsnt life, they wsnt s good life, the best life pos<br />

sible; snd in seeking the good life, they form politicsl sssocistions. In con<br />

trast to the formstion of the household order or fsmily, the oikos, which srises<br />

out of the combinstion of instinct snd need, politicsl order is instituted inten<br />

tionally, as a matter of conscious choice. Although men sre nsturslly inclined<br />

to sssociste politically, political associations do not<br />

spontaneously<br />

emerge the<br />

way families do. The greatest benefactor to mankind, Aristotle observes, was<br />

the man who first invented and instituted political order (1253331-34).<br />

At a subsistence level, human life is ruled<br />

by<br />

necessity. Once men produce<br />

more than they need, they also choose a way of life, slmost of necessity, be<br />

csuse instinct is so much wesker in humsn beings thsn it is in other 3nimsls.<br />

Humsn beings hsve to order snd direct their own lives becsuse of the indeter<br />

minacy or openness of human nature. They are able to order their lives by<br />

virtue of their rational<br />

faculty<br />

or logos. But as Jean-Jscques Rousseau later<br />

argued, human beings develop their speech and resson only<br />

in sssocistion with<br />

one another. There is, strictly speaking, no completely individual capacity for<br />

choice or self-rule. Rather than emphasize the openness or<br />

indeterminacy of<br />

human life, Aristotle thus stresses the importance and<br />

difficulty of making a<br />

good choice, that is, of<br />

developing man's practical reason, and its political<br />

foundation.<br />

Although human beings can and clearly do exist without associating politi<br />

cally, Aristotle declares that the polis is prior to the individual, because each


Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 189<br />

develops his "individuality" or particularity as well as his distinctly human<br />

qualities only<br />

in political association. The quslities which most distinguish one<br />

through specislizstion snd s division of lsbor.<br />

msn from snother<br />

develop only<br />

So long ss one man uses all his energy to provide for himself and a family, he<br />

is not apt to develop a talent for geometry, music or painting. Since human<br />

beings csnnot live at<br />

sny level sbove subsistence except in cooperation with<br />

others, the choice of s wsy of life csn be msde only through sssocistion, snd<br />

men sssociste with esch other only on the bssis of the friendship thst arises from<br />

sn sgreement sbout whst is right or just. Men who do not trust esch other do<br />

not deliberate together sbout whst<br />

they should do; they seek to defend them<br />

selves from possible incursions. Humsn beings thus<br />

develop their nstursl<br />

potentisl to order or direct their own lives, their logos, only in politicsl associstions.<br />

and political associations are founded on an sgreement about what is<br />

right or just. Human speech and reason extend beyond the mere animal expres<br />

sion of pleasure and pain to calculations of what is useful or harmful. But<br />

logos is not<br />

merely instrumental, as Aristotle understands it. How can men<br />

calculate what is useful without a standard of measure of what "X" is useful or<br />

hsrmful to? Logos thus includes the ability to articulate, compare and rank<br />

various desires, to determine what is right, ss well ss the cspscity to deter<br />

mine whst is conducive to achieving<br />

these ends. Men thus exercise and express<br />

their full rational potential<br />

only<br />

in politicsl association.<br />

Although individuals acquire both their distinctive talents and traits along<br />

with their ability to choose a way of life only in a political association, in<br />

dividual differences are not merely or completely products of the division of<br />

labor. On the contrary, Aristotle argues, there are natural differences in indi<br />

vidual potential; it is the existence of such differences that makes the division<br />

of labor rational, productive, and<br />

generally<br />

beneficial. If there were no such<br />

natural differences in potential, neither differentiation nor<br />

hierarchy of any kind<br />

would be just. Specialization would<br />

merely<br />

constitute a restriction and contor<br />

tion of human potential. All social organization would rest ultimately<br />

on arbi<br />

trary<br />

preferences and coercive control. The master-slave relation represents the<br />

simplest and most extreme esse.<br />

Aristotle's discussion of the master-slave relation reveals two fundamental<br />

characteristics of all human association: (1) the utility of a division of labor,<br />

and (2) the need to use force to maintain order. Like Marx, Aristotle suggests<br />

that the most fundamental division of labor is that between mind or soul and<br />

body.4<br />

Through an snslysis of the compound constitution of the individusl humsn<br />

being, however, Aristotle argues that such a division is necesssry, natural, and<br />

beneficial. If soul does not rule body, that is, if there is no intelligent direc<br />

tion of physical motion, no man will long<br />

survive. Rule of the soul or mind is<br />

thus necessary and beneficial for both ruler and ruled. By analogy, Aristotle<br />

4. Karl Marx, "The German Ideology," reprinted in Robert Tucker, The Marx-Engels Reader,<br />

2nd ed. (New York: Norton, 1978), p. 159.


190 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

therefore argues, one man has a right to control the actions of another com<br />

pletely, to own him, if the two are related to each other as soul is to body.<br />

The nstursl slsve is thus s humsn being<br />

with enough resson to follow orders<br />

but not to direct his own life. He lscks enough foresight snd control to order<br />

his own sffsirs sufficiently to survive without direction. Rule by<br />

s msster is<br />

good for the slsve ss well ss the msster, becsuse the slsve left slone is unsble<br />

to preserve himself. All humsn beings sre nsturslly<br />

sttached to their own exis<br />

tence, so preservstion msy certsinly be regsrded ss good. Although msstery is<br />

just when both psrties benefit, the justice of msstery does not rest on the<br />

consent of the slsve. It could not becsuse the nstursl or justly enslsved man<br />

is enslsved precisely becsuse he is not sble to determine or to do whst is best<br />

for himself. The masters have to determine which men ought to be slaves and<br />

force them to serve. Mastery<br />

can be just even when it rests on force rather<br />

than consent, but forceful conquest does not suffice to establish just rule.<br />

Only<br />

common benefit establishes justice.<br />

The only<br />

reason human beings associate with each other is for their mutual<br />

benefit or pleasure, but mutual benefit does not necessarily<br />

mean equal benefit.<br />

Aristotle wss<br />

certsinly<br />

not quixotic or unobservsnt enough to believe thst men<br />

enslsve others in order to preserve or benefit the slsves.<br />

They tske slsves be<br />

csuse<br />

they wsnt to use them to obtsin or to do what the masters want, for the<br />

benefit of the mssters, not the slsves. Aristotle does not emphssize the com<br />

mon benefit which for the slsves is mere preservation so much as the essen<br />

tially instrumental character of mastery. Despite a common opinion to the con<br />

trary, Aristotle argues, careful examination of the situation shows that command<br />

snd control of the sctions of other humsn beings snd the division of lsbor in<br />

volved in thst commsnd sre not good or desirable in themselves. A fortunate<br />

master will find a reliable steward to manage his slaves for him so that he will<br />

be free to engage in politics or<br />

philosophy (i255b30-37). Human excellence<br />

or virtue does not consist merely in the recognition of superiority by<br />

consists in a way of life, a kind of activity<br />

thst the psrticipsnts find<br />

satisfying<br />

in itself,<br />

others; it<br />

not as a means to some other good. Aristotle's suggestion that<br />

the work of slsves might be performed<br />

by "divine<br />

machines"<br />

msy<br />

mske the dif<br />

ference he sees between politics snd msstery clesrer to the modern reader.<br />

Technology, again the intelligent direction of physical force, is supposed to in<br />

crease our power or ability to realize our desires; it is essentially instrumental<br />

rather than choiceworthy or valuable in and of itself. It could only replace<br />

politics, deliberation and judgment by rigidly restricting the mental develop<br />

ment and the serve.5<br />

variety of life it is supposed to<br />

Both the emergence and continued existence of a politicsl sssocistion de<br />

pend upon the intelligent use of force to msintsin order snd a division of labor<br />

5. There are, indeed, some who fear that it will. Cf. Joseph Weizenbaum, Computer Power<br />

and Human Reason: From Judgment to Calculation (San Francisco: Freeman, 1976), and Jacques<br />

Ellul, Technological Society (New York: Knopf, 1964).


possible.7<br />

But,<br />

Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life -191<br />

to produce enough to free some from the press of necessity. Both the need for<br />

coercion and a division of labor inherent in the master-slave relation<br />

belong<br />

to the household; both are necessary parts or elements of every political order,<br />

but neither constitutes its essence, that which makes it distinctly<br />

the contrary, both of these necessary<br />

political. On<br />

elements constitute limitations of politics<br />

the extent to which it can be free, reasonable, just and beneficial to all.<br />

Aristotle indicates the extent of such limitations only briefly<br />

when he observes<br />

two respects in which nature falls short of her "intention." First, she<br />

"intends"<br />

that masters and slaves be visibly distinguishable (I254b27~34). In fsct, it is<br />

difficult if not impossible to tell who is s nstursl slsve snd who s msster,<br />

becsuse the primsry difference is one of intellectual potential rather than physi<br />

cal strength,<br />

and intellectual potential cannot be seen. In order to be identified,<br />

intellectual potential has to be actualized, and the actualization depends upon a<br />

child's social (family) and, later,<br />

political position. As the Coleman report has<br />

more recently reminded us, the development of a child's intelligence depends<br />

very much on his family circumstances. A good family<br />

produce excellence,<br />

life does not suffice to<br />

moreover. As Aristotle observes (i255bi-5), outstanding<br />

men do not always have excellent sons, not<br />

only<br />

because public men often<br />

neglect their own families but also because the sons do not have the same<br />

potential. Human excellence is not<br />

simply inherited, although nature again<br />

"intends"<br />

it. Social and political order, the division of labor, does not and<br />

never will<br />

clearly and perfectly<br />

reflect the differences in individual potentisl<br />

snd talent, becsuse the development of potential into excellence presupposes<br />

social order. But the fact that political order can<br />

only<br />

completely duplicate the naturally<br />

abandon the natural as the standard of right.<br />

Contrary<br />

approximate and never<br />

indicated order does not lead Aristotle to<br />

to Marx, Aristotle suggests that the division of labor arises not so<br />

much from need as from the desire to live<br />

well.6<br />

One man can support himself<br />

to amass more than<br />

alone with<br />

only an ox. Unfortunstely, the same tendency<br />

they need also prevents most human beings from ever realizing their desires.<br />

Although acquisition ought to be defined and limited by the requirements of a<br />

fully sstisfying life, since the "mesns"<br />

utility of sny must be determined by<br />

its "end" or purpose, it is much essier, ss Aristotle observes, to see the utility<br />

of life. Most<br />

of goods and money thsn it is to find s fully satisfying way<br />

men thus devote themselves to acquiring as much as they can, because they are<br />

ultimately more concerned with their mere preservation than they<br />

sre with<br />

living well (I257b4i-i258&2).<br />

As Hobbes lster emphssizes, human beings never know exsctly<br />

whst<br />

they<br />

will need, so they amsss ss much ss possible to take csre of ss msny future<br />

contingencies as<br />

Aristotle insists, this unlimited desire for acqui<br />

sition results in a fundamental perversion. Rather than use<br />

money<br />

6. Marx, op. cit., pp. 156-58.<br />

7. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan VI, XIII.<br />

and goods


192 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

to improve the quality of their lives by raising their level of activity, most<br />

men exercise and improve their faculties in order to acquire more goods. The<br />

first illustration Aristotle uses is indicative. Men need courage in order to live<br />

well, that is, not to live in fear, but in mercenary<br />

armies or wars for con<br />

quest, they make courage merely into a means of acquiring more wealth. They<br />

never find satisfaction in their own activity; they look only for the (external)<br />

rewards.<br />

Although Aristotle's view of the primary driving forces in the lives of most<br />

men is thus quite similar to Hobbes', there are two important differences.<br />

First, Aristotle describes a positive attachment to life rather than the negstive<br />

fesr of death or the unknown. The naive or natural view is that life is good,<br />

something to be desired. Second, Aristotle maintains that there are some few<br />

who are not moved<br />

solely by the desire for acquisition or mere life. In taking<br />

account<br />

only of the majority, Hobbes does not reveal the full human truth. A<br />

few can achieve full satisfaction in philosophy<br />

or government. If that is true,<br />

human life does not<br />

necessarily and always consist merely in striving that<br />

ceases only in death. So long<br />

as some human beings have to devote their lives<br />

to providing the goods, that is, so long a division of labor is necessary, every<br />

one will not be able to devote his or her life to politics or philosophy.<br />

Nevertheless, if most men seek good without end. there is bound to be<br />

competition and conflict on what we call economic grounds. And where there<br />

is conflict, force must be used to estsblish order. The use of force is therefore<br />

necesssry in instituting politicsl order not only<br />

to provide necessities in the<br />

form of the msster-slsve relstion but slso to desl with the conflict thst results<br />

from the expsnsion of desire thst follows the productive success of a division<br />

of labor. Since scarcity does not result so much from the limits of natural<br />

goods as the unlimited range of human desire, the productivity<br />

technology would not fundamentally<br />

of modern<br />

alter the situation. As Aristotle argues in<br />

Book II, acquisitive desires give rise to conflict which cannot be solved<br />

by<br />

solely<br />

economic means.<br />

Plato attempted to abolish self-interested conflict or "factions." especially<br />

between rich and poor, by making the citizens of his politeia as much like<br />

each other as possible and<br />

having them share everything. This most radical<br />

communism ever proposed is radically defective, according to Aristotle, in both<br />

means and end. If a political society necesssrily<br />

comprehends several different<br />

functions, conflict csnnot be reduced<br />

by destroying differentistion without<br />

destroying the possibility of politics ss well. Politicsl deliberation consists pre<br />

cisely in determining<br />

the difficult question of which activities to encourage<br />

smong<br />

which groups of citizens snd how to reward them with goods or praise.<br />

Like Plato, Aristotle asserts that education is the way to produce political unity,<br />

but Aristotle criticizes Plato for not recognizing<br />

the significance of economic<br />

function for education. If the farmers and guardians receive the same education,<br />

Aristotle asks, how will<br />

they remain able to perform their different functions?


Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 193<br />

If they don't, how does the educational scheme unify the city? Education means<br />

more than the acquisition of skills and common beliefs; human beings learn<br />

largely by doing, so their education is virtually inseparable from their way of<br />

life. Rsther than unity itself or in the abstract, it is the desire to foster and<br />

protect an accepted way<br />

of life that holds together different activities which<br />

necessarily constitute a polity.<br />

Although Plato purports to rely on education to unify his politeia, Aristotle<br />

observes, he actually depends more on the communistic institutions. Aristotle's<br />

critique of these institutions thus points to his understanding<br />

of the origin or<br />

core of the politicsl conflict thst Plsto tried to svoid<br />

sre nsturslly first attached to their own existence. By having<br />

self-love. Humsn beings<br />

all citizens own<br />

all property in common, Aristotle argues, Plato insures that no one will take<br />

care of any<br />

of it. Each will tend to leave the msnagement of the<br />

"commons"<br />

to others, and it will not be possible to identify the failure of any specific<br />

individual to contribute his share because no one hss sny<br />

psrticulsr responsi<br />

bility for any specified psrt. The ssme observstion spplies even more strongly<br />

to the fsmily snd the raising of children. Men care for their own, both as an<br />

extension of themselves and because others hold them responsible.<br />

By making<br />

the city into one big family, Plato does not extend a close tie, therefore, so<br />

much as dissolve it. No one<br />

any longer "belongs" to any<br />

one else.<br />

The foundation of the traditional family structure is not solely economic<br />

or primarily bssed on the general difference between the sexes in physicsl<br />

strength snd reproductive function, sccording to Aristotle. On the contrary, the<br />

fsmily<br />

comprises three different relstions. One is the msster-slsve or economic<br />

function, but thst is only<br />

one. Women are not properly slaves, because they<br />

can reason; the relation between husband and wife is a "political" one of<br />

equals, as opposed to the despotic rule of slaves or the monarchical guidance<br />

of children (1259b!). Since it involves choice, the conjugal relstion is not<br />

merely animal, erotic, or procreative. Third and most important, however, is<br />

the educationsl relstion of psrents to children. Like sdults, children csn be<br />

educsted<br />

only if their needs sre met, but most sdults will care enough to take<br />

the trouble only for their own children, as an extension of themselves or, at<br />

least, as a duty for which they are publicly and individually<br />

held responsible.<br />

The family structure is thus necessary, because men will care for their children<br />

only when these are publicly and privately identifisble ss theirs. As Aristotle<br />

indicstes in his discussion of the differences between politicsl snd subpolitical<br />

associations in Book I, the family is economically necessary to produce future<br />

generations of human beings. It is politically necessary to make most men act<br />

to preserve the regime by taking<br />

csre to psss on their own wsy of life to their<br />

life will therefore slso<br />

children. The specific chsrscter snd regulstion of fsmily<br />

vary according<br />

to the regime (1260b 12-18).<br />

If education is, or ought to be, the first concern of any government, a public<br />

system will be provided and the laws will regulate family life as well ss more


opportunity"<br />

194 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

formsl studies. If educstion remains almost entirely within the private family,<br />

the division of labor will certainly be unjust, because privste weslth snd<br />

family<br />

position will determine future occupations rather than individual potential. Citi<br />

zens will be encouraged to care for their own, moreover,<br />

rather than what is<br />

common. Like Plato, Aristotle is aware of the Spartan system of public and<br />

equal, although segregated, education for both males and females. Like Plato,<br />

he suggests that men will not be educated unless their mothers are also (1260a).<br />

Unlike Plato, however, Aristotle srgues that public efforts cannot entirely replsce<br />

fsmily ties. Personsl sttention is importsnt not merely<br />

becsuse humsn<br />

beings desire it, but becsuse it is such a clesr indicstion of whst is vslued.<br />

If educstion is truly deemed to be important, fathers will concern themselves<br />

with it not<br />

only in general, in the law, but also as it specifically concerns<br />

their own sons. Indeed, concern for the existence and future of their own<br />

families constitutes one of the strongest bonds uniting<br />

men in a polity. Political<br />

unity cannot be achieved by destroying man's attachment to his own, Aristotle<br />

suggests, because politics itself grows out of this self-same attachment.<br />

Aristotle states his full view of the political function of the family only as<br />

a critique of Plato, because the family structure involves another fundamental<br />

limitation on political justice. Plato suggested the "community of wives and<br />

children"<br />

not only in order to overcome man's attachment to his own but also<br />

to offer both sexes an "equal<br />

to<br />

develop their individual poten<br />

tial, that is, as a matter of justice rather than efficiency. In Book I, Aristotle<br />

claims that as the master rules the slave by nature, so the man leads the woman<br />

(except when the union is against nature, that is, when a woman marries her<br />

inferior) (1259b 1-5). He thus<br />

implicitly recognizes the possibility explicitly<br />

discussed in the Republic (4550-4563) thst s womsn inferior to 3 few men<br />

will still be superior to most. Since he insists thst the conjugal associstion is<br />

politicsl 3nd reflects in the immediste sequel thst political relstions generally<br />

occur between equsls, who rule snd sre ruled in turn, it is difficult to see why<br />

he nevertheless concludes that the man should alwsys rule (i259b5-io). In<br />

describing the basis of the three different kinds of rule or relations in the<br />

household, Aristotle explains that the parts are different. Where the slave does<br />

not participste in council or deliberation (fiovXevtixov) at all, both women<br />

and children do, but the woman's participation is axvgov, without authority,<br />

and the child is undeveloped (dasXeg). To ssy that the womsn deliberates<br />

without authority, rule or decisiveness (the alternative meanings of xvgioc;) is<br />

as much as to say<br />

that her reason does not rule because she does not rule.<br />

Aristotle does not give the reason why she does not rule or justify<br />

the ex<br />

ception to the ordinary equality in political relations.<br />

Aristotle admits that his discussion of the family and the proper excellence<br />

and functions of its varied psrts in Book I is not complete (i26ob8-20). The<br />

question must be reconsidered in the context of the discussion of the different<br />

regimes becsuse it is s question of the respective excellences of ruled and


ule."<br />

Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 195<br />

rulers. The fsmily is, sfter all, but a part of the polis, and the excellence of<br />

the part is relstive to the whole. When Aristotle returns to the question of the<br />

relative excellences of ruler and ruled in Book III (1277^4-30), he also dis<br />

cusses the different virtues of the two sexes. The only virtue peculiar to rulers.<br />

he concludes, is cbgovrjoig or practicsl resson which is and can be developed<br />

only in the process of governing, that is, in use. Otherwise the virtues of the<br />

ruler and the ruled are the same; the ruler must know how to obey (himself<br />

and others) before he can rule. The virtues of the two sexes differ, not because<br />

of differences in natural potential for deliberation, according to Aristotle, but<br />

because of their different household functions. According<br />

to the true laws of<br />

the household (olxovoLiia), the business of the man is to acquire where that of<br />

the woman is to secure. (Is Aristotle guilty of an ironic pun here? The verb<br />

he uses to describe the female function, cbvXctTTEtv,<br />

hss the ssme root ss<br />

the noun, tbvkaxr), thst Plsto uses to describe the rulers in the Republic.) The<br />

definition of the functionsl difference underlying<br />

sexusl differences in excel<br />

lence seems to refer bsck to the srt of war, described ss s form of the art of<br />

acquisition and so oikonomia in Book I (i256b24-28). If so, the sexual divi<br />

sion of labor in the household reflects differences in physical strength more<br />

than deliberative potential; and the woman's silence or "modesty" is a product<br />

more of place than intellectual deficiency. Aristotle's discussion of<br />

slavery<br />

makes it clear, moreover, that he does not regard physical strength as a legiti<br />

mate ground for<br />

Defense is usually<br />

considered to be just while<br />

tsking the property and lives<br />

of others is not. Perhaps for thst resson Aristotle includes the srt of wsr or<br />

the hunting of slsves only conditionally<br />

statesman.<br />

Only<br />

with the yolk, is the taking<br />

in the true oikonomia and art of the<br />

if nature provides for man's needs as she does for the chick<br />

of slaves just. Aristotle does not srgue thst there<br />

will be a sufficient number of natural slaves to serve the needs of each oikos<br />

or polis; on the contrary, in Book VII (1330326-33) he indicates that even in<br />

the best regime some who are not naturally<br />

slaves will be forced to serve others<br />

by proposing to free some of them. (A natural slave could not be freed, be<br />

cause he is incapable of<br />

taking<br />

does not snd cannot correspond exsctly<br />

potential among individuals.<br />

csre of himself.) Even the best politicsl order<br />

to the uneven distribution of nstural<br />

Just as slavery is finally justified not merely by a natural difference among<br />

individuals in talent but also as a necessary<br />

means or part of a greater whole,<br />

the political association, so is the perpetual debarment of women from poli<br />

tics.9<br />

Some must provide the necessities so that others csn be free. So Aristotle<br />

8. See also Arlene Saxonhouse, "Aristotle's Critique of<br />

Socrates'<br />

Community of Wives,"<br />

paper<br />

prepared for presentation at the Midwest Political Science Association meetings, April 19-21.<br />

1979, Chicago, Illinois.<br />

9. Even Susan Okin, Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton: Princeton University<br />

Press, 1979). p. 235. admits that Aristotle treats women in accord with his general teleological<br />

understanding, not as exceptions to the rule for men.


"more,"<br />

196 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

observes st the end of his critique of Plsto's Laws (i265b22-27)<br />

thst some one<br />

must msnsge the household. In Book I, however, Aristotle suggests thst it is<br />

desirable to find s steward to oversee the employment of one's slaves in order<br />

to free oneself for politics or philosophy.<br />

Why<br />

couldn't a wife also hire a<br />

household manager? In contrast to slsvery, the subordinstion of women does<br />

not sppesr to rest<br />

primsrily<br />

on the need for sn economic division of labor.<br />

True, the provision of necessities is a prerequisite of politicsl life; but it is<br />

not sufficient. Men must slso be educsted; snd ss Aristotle points out in his<br />

critique of Plsto's sttempt to mske politicsl order correspond to nstursl dif<br />

ferences, men will not sttend to the educstion of their sons unless they sre<br />

certsin these children sre in fsct theirs. The fundsmentsl resson women sre<br />

bsrred from the full development of their deliberative fsculties in public life<br />

sppesrs to be the need to msximize esch husbsnd's conviction thst his wife's<br />

children sre his own so thst he will tend to their educstion. As public con<br />

cern for educstion decresses, in s<br />

democracy for exsmple, Aristotle lster ob<br />

serves, so does the need to regulste the sctivities of women snd children.<br />

Sexusl differentistion of function does hsve a natural foundation, but that<br />

foundation appears to consist more in man's love of his own than in differ<br />

ences between the sexes in potential intellectual ability.<br />

Aristotle is thus very<br />

much aware of the role of self-interest in politics snd<br />

its primsrily<br />

economic msnifestation. He simply insists that as forms of human<br />

existence differ, so do the expressions and demsnds of self-interest. Since sll<br />

interests are not<br />

simply economic, he points out in his critique of Phaleas, all<br />

conflicts of interest cannot be solved<br />

solely by<br />

economic means. Because eco<br />

nomic desires extend beyond need, as soon as need is met, conflict will not<br />

end<br />

by giving all equal shares. Some will try to get more, not simply because<br />

they want more things, but because they wsnt honor, to be recognized<br />

by other<br />

men ss being better. Since economic desires resdily expsnd beyond need, eco<br />

nomic conflict is inevitsble snd csn be regulsted only by noneconomic means,<br />

that is, government. Government will also be based on self-interest, but interest<br />

of a different kind. Relatively few people in sny community hsve either the<br />

opportunity or the desire to psrticipate regularly in directing<br />

its affairs. Most<br />

people will be content business.10<br />

merely to be left alone to mansge their own<br />

Prompted by stsrvation, people may revolt, but such popular uprisings are rela<br />

tively rare and certainly not of long duration. The people who desire s place<br />

in government on an ongoing basis will not be prompted by need so much as a<br />

desire for<br />

which is most often a desire for recognition.<br />

Political conflict is thus not<br />

fundamentally or properly speaking<br />

economic in<br />

origin.<br />

Precisely for that reason, Aristotle suggests, it is possible to obtain<br />

civil peace, if the desire for recognition, office, or honors of the few mskes<br />

them unwilling to engage in purely scquisitive sctivities snd they<br />

sre granted<br />

io. Cf. Machiavelli. Prince IX.


military."<br />

Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 197<br />

the power to control the scquisitive desires of others with force (i267b4-io).<br />

The wsy in which s community sllocates offices and honors is thus absolutely<br />

crucial, because it determines the kinds of activities or achievements ambitious<br />

men pursue and whether or not<br />

they will see an opportunity to realize their de<br />

sires and so support the regime.<br />

Aristotle mskes us confront the fsct thst the "people" set politically only<br />

with leadership<br />

or organization. The character snd educstion of the leaders is<br />

thus the decisive political phenomenon,<br />

even in democracies. Political leaders<br />

can be led or educated through an appeal to their desire for recognition, but<br />

Aristotle reminds us that the desire for recognition is not the only motive<br />

which brings men into politics. Some also seek to become tyrants, to have the<br />

power to do whatever<br />

they want, or as he says, to have pleasure without pain.<br />

They are mistaken in this attempt, he suggests, because there are always "costs"<br />

or "trade-offs" in politics of the kind we have discussed in the context of the<br />

division of lsbor. The only<br />

source of pure plessure is philosophy, presumsbly<br />

ss Plsto argues, because the truth is the only good human being<br />

can share<br />

without losing any themselves, that is, the only good they can truly hold in<br />

common and noncompetitively.<br />

Nevertheless, Aristotle does not support Montesquieu's later suggestion that<br />

ancient political virtue consists fundsmentslly in an appeal to the desire for<br />

recognition and is basically<br />

Aristotle argues that this is true of ancient<br />

practice, particulsrly of Spsrts, but he insists thst militsry<br />

prowess does not<br />

constitute the whole of practical or political virtue. The excellence of a ruler, as<br />

Aristotle presents it, is primarily intellectual. It consists in duplicating<br />

the com<br />

plex determination Aristotle himself begins in Book III of what is just not<br />

only<br />

in general but also in the specific circumstances. Such considerations<br />

apply not<br />

only to the founding, the fundamental law, or the organization of offices and<br />

honors in the constitution, but also potentially to every<br />

piece of legislation,<br />

every particular administrative decision, because, as Aristotle observes, small<br />

changes, in the qualifications for voting, for example, can change the entire<br />

constitution (128934-6;<br />

1303321-25). It takes great prudence to foresee the<br />

long-term effects of current actions. These deliberations are thus continually<br />

necessary snd so difficult thst they tsx snd fully occupy<br />

mental snd physicsl capscity. They<br />

are inherently satisfying,<br />

s human being's entire<br />

although not en<br />

without<br />

tirely pain, becsuse political decisions slwsys involve hsrd 3lternstives<br />

snd 3lw3ys h&ve costs, since they always benefit some more than others. In any<br />

form of government, only<br />

a few participate at this level and so realize the full<br />

benefits. Everyone csnnot govern;<br />

slwsys sttend primsrily<br />

st most the rulers will tske turns. Most will<br />

to the means of their own self-preservation.<br />

If very few people ever take part in full political deliberation, very<br />

fully understand the reasons for any set of lsws. Most will obey<br />

few will<br />

on the bssis<br />

1 1. Montesquieu. Spirit of the Laws IV, V.


198 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

of s general trust or belief that the laws sre beneficisl. But every time the<br />

lsw is chsnged, this general belief will be brought into question. Aristotle thus<br />

criticizes<br />

Hippodamus'<br />

suggestion that innovation should be rewarded snd so<br />

encouraged. Since every change hss such s fundsmentsl cost, only<br />

msjor re<br />

forms should even be considered. Reform per se cannot be advocsted without<br />

undermining obedience to the law.<br />

Improvement in politics is possible and reason is the major source of im<br />

provement. Politicsl resson is essentislly deliberative rather thsn linesr or<br />

simply additive, however, for two reasons. First, there sre competing<br />

and<br />

noncommensurable<br />

elements to be weighed, and second, the weight of each de<br />

pends somewhat upon the particular circumstsnces,<br />

which sre slwsys chsnging.<br />

The most important political decision, as we have seen, is the constitutional<br />

one<br />

determining<br />

what the offices or honors shall be and who is eligible for<br />

them. In short, who should rule. This question is difficult, slthough not im<br />

possible to snswer, Aristotle sees, becsuse of the necessary differentiation of<br />

function. Several groups can claim to provide what is most essential to the<br />

politicsl association and, therefore, the right to have the decisive voice in its<br />

affairs. No one<br />

group can provide all the community's needs, so any group(s)<br />

denied the right to participate to the extent of electing<br />

officials st least will<br />

have some just grounds for complsint. The primsry<br />

sttschment to his own exis<br />

tence of esch individusl will, moreover, tend to mske esch<br />

group overestimste<br />

the importance of its own contribution and denigrate the services of others.<br />

Conflict almost necessarily results; whether dissent is voiced or not, there will<br />

never be perfect agreement or consent<br />

underlying any<br />

regime. Man's self-love<br />

not<br />

only makes unanimous consent extremely unlikely but also invalidates con<br />

sent as the sole measure of justice.<br />

Unlike modern relativists, Aristotle insists that it is possible to answer the<br />

question, who should rule, with reason. There are two kinds of considerations<br />

to be taken into account. First, there are the broad criteria set<br />

by the ends of<br />

the association. A political association is more than a market or a mutual de<br />

fense pact, Aristotle argues, because different polities can trade or slly with<br />

each other without becoming politically united (1280a). Political sssocistion in<br />

volves sgreement on s desirable way<br />

of life, and those who contribute to the<br />

maintensnce of this distinctive way of life have a greater claim to participate<br />

in the government than those who simply contribute to its subsistence by pro<br />

viding food or defending its territory. All contributions or services to the polity<br />

are not necessarily performed by discrete groups, however. Farmers can also be<br />

soldiers, and soldiers can become judges. In order to determine what groups<br />

should participate in making decisions for the community, and to what extent,<br />

one must also look at the specific circumstances or people to see which group<br />

or groups, on the whole, contribute most and so deserve to rule.<br />

Mechanics or artisans represent the limiting and so most revealing case.<br />

Clearly, mechanics and artisans are not "nstursl<br />

because they<br />

are able


"outvoted"<br />

Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 199<br />

to order their lives and preserve themselves. Their need to lsbor prevents them<br />

from doing more. They contribute to the msintensnce of the life of the city,<br />

but they csnnot psrticipste in politics or government in any very mesningful<br />

sense, becsuse they have not the time, experience, or occasion to follow and<br />

participate in public deliberations. The institution of political association does<br />

not, therefore, enable members of this class to reach their full human potentisl.<br />

Aristotle concludes, therefore, that they should not be citizens in sny wellordered<br />

regime (i 278s). Have they not been treated unjustly, we might respond;<br />

they, too, contribute to the common good. Should they not at lesst be sllowed to<br />

vote? Aristotle would respond that they enjoy the advantages of law and order;<br />

in exchange for their contribution to the preservation of the city, they, too, are<br />

preserved. Nevertheless, he concludes that it is dsngerous not to let them hsve<br />

some shsre in the enjoyment of power; for a polis with a<br />

body<br />

chised citizens who are numerous and poor must necessarily<br />

of disenfran<br />

be a polis which<br />

is full of enemies (128^28-31). Men love their own, and they<br />

will view the<br />

government as their own only if they participate in it to a certain extent. Aris<br />

totle thus mskes his recommendstion with regsrd to artisans in full view of<br />

the potential costs.<br />

Democracies tend to be more stable than other forms of government, Aris<br />

totle observes, but they also tend to be ill-governed. If the people decide issues<br />

or vote for a psrty platform directly, they do so on the bssis of insdequste<br />

information and disregard for the need to adapt to changing<br />

circumstances. If<br />

they merely vote for officials to make these decisions for them, they<br />

must be<br />

very fine judges of character (i28ib-i282a; I326b2).<br />

Usually they Either they blame officials for problems they had no control over, or they ele<br />

are not.<br />

vate sycophantic scoundrels. (Aristotle might well recall Athens' trestment of<br />

Perikles as well ss Kleon.) Most fundsmentsl, however, s government which<br />

elevates the necessities of life and those who provide them, whether democratic<br />

or oligarchic, implicitly<br />

endorses and frees the acquisitive desires. It will neces<br />

sarily be corrupt in itself and corrupt the people. The only check on the ac<br />

quisitive desires is reason, but Aristotle recognizes that the people who see the<br />

reasons<br />

why acquisition should be limited are few, so few that they<br />

be apt to press their claims to rule.<br />

They<br />

(130404-5). They see that they<br />

will be<br />

will not<br />

have too much practical sense<br />

in effect<br />

by<br />

others. To the<br />

extent to which all government rests on the consent of the many, it is not<br />

based on reason.<br />

Although reason can solve the political problem. Aristotle suggests that it is<br />

not likely to be effective very often at least not fully<br />

effective. The best<br />

regime possible<br />

generally is not a regime which elevates the best men (an<br />

"aristocracy") but one which checks the worst abuses of power. In a "mixed<br />

or polity, elections and offices are structured so that they balance the<br />

powers of the people (numbers) and their moderate<br />

relatively desires against<br />

the rapacity of the few wealthy. There are many<br />

possible structures or<br />

varia-


200 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

tions, Aristotle recognizes, but no such mixture is possible where there is not<br />

a substsntial middle class.<br />

Only the middle class has an interest in keeping the<br />

balance, because they<br />

would suffer from either expropriation and redistribution<br />

of all<br />

property by the poor or oppressive taxation by the party<br />

Even regimes which do not intentionally and explicitly<br />

of the rich.<br />

seek to educate their<br />

citizens have a formative effect, but in these regimes predominantly economic<br />

factors have a much more powerful role.<br />

Many people, Aristotle observes, believe that there are<br />

fundamentally only<br />

two types of government democracies and oligarchies. (The distinction lives<br />

on in contemporary<br />

political science in the contrast between authoritarisn and<br />

psrticipstory.) Distinguishing them merely<br />

in terms of the number of people<br />

involved does not describe regimes sccurstely, however. As Aristotle reminds<br />

us, the rule of the "people" or s "msjority" still represents the rule of the<br />

whole<br />

by s psrt, very<br />

often in its own self-interest. Politics is slwsys psrtial.<br />

The government of msny educsted middle-clsss citizens is significsntly differ<br />

ent, moreover, from the rule of poor pesssnts. Men tend to cstegorize all re<br />

gimes ss either democracies or oligsrchies, Aristotle suggests, not<br />

simply on<br />

the bssis of the number of people involved but becsuse rich snd poor sppear<br />

to be the only mutually exclusive characteristics of ruling classes. Since it is<br />

possible to be both poor snd brave or rich snd educated, democracy<br />

and oli<br />

garchy or simple economic and numerical classifications do not suffice to de<br />

scribe a regime. There are monarchies, aristocracies, and polities as well as<br />

democracies, oligarchies, and tyrannies. Whether the ruling clsss defines its<br />

self-interest in terms of the prosperity of the whole or over snd against other<br />

classes makes a fundamental difference. Even when the ruling party<br />

evidently and narrowly self-interested and defines its interest primarily<br />

is more<br />

in eco<br />

nomic terms, there are still important practicsl differences smong oligsrchies<br />

and democracies.<br />

Political action always reflects self-interest, as Aristotle presents it, but that<br />

fact alone does not suffice to show that it is unjust or will be effective. Like<br />

sll human beings, rulers act for their own good. Whether their rule is just or<br />

not depends on how they<br />

understand their own interest. The best man would<br />

see that it is not in his interest to abuse s slsve or srtissn; the middle clsss<br />

is also politically self-controlled, but for economic rather than moral reasons,<br />

in its public sets but not on an individual or private level. Although a mixed<br />

regime is not possible without a large middle class, that is, the best regime<br />

generally possible depends on the existence of s certsin distribution of weslth,<br />

the distribution of wealth is not in itself politically determinative because gov<br />

ernment can change the distribution through taxation or outright expropriation.<br />

The political effects of both the distribution of wealth snd the mode of pro<br />

duction, so to speak, are more indirect. They affect the polity largely through<br />

the effect<br />

they have on the characteristic attitudes of the people.<br />

The differences Aristotle describes among democracies and oligarchies, for


Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 201<br />

example, have two primarily economic sources: the distribution of property and<br />

population on the one hsnd<br />

related<br />

snd the "mode of<br />

Aristotle slwsys insists thst the two factors be<br />

production"<br />

on the other. If s<br />

democracy is com<br />

posed of msny smsll lsndholders or farmers, it is apt to be law-abiding snd<br />

highly stsble. Small lsndholders or fsrmers necesssrily hsve to spend most of<br />

their time sttending to their own sffsirs. Since they sre geographically dis<br />

persed, it is difficult for them to organize or participste<br />

directly in political<br />

deliberation very<br />

often.<br />

They will tend, therefore, to support the rule of law<br />

and to maintsin widespresd distribution of property (by opposing oppressive<br />

tsxstion), becsuse both sre in their rather immediate and narrow economic in<br />

terest. The same is true of sn<br />

oligsrchy composed of msny<br />

citizens who csn<br />

meet s relatively low property quslificstion. If, on the other hsnd, power de<br />

volves to urbsn day-laborers, they will be apt to meet regularly<br />

and to change<br />

the lsw frequently, becsuse it will be relstively essy for them to congregste.<br />

They will slso be spt to expropriste the holdings of the rich, st lesst to tsx<br />

property hesvily, in order to pay themselves for public service. Likewise, an<br />

oligarchy composed of s few very weslthy fsmilies who recognize no clsim of<br />

right or humsn excellence but wealth is apt to adopt very<br />

oppressive laws or<br />

even to act outside the law in an sttempt to incresse their own holdings even<br />

more. The distribution of weslth snd types of property held sre politically im<br />

portant not merely because they arouse conflict. As Aristotle argues in Book V,<br />

politicsl conflict seldom revolves<br />

solely sround the economic question; there is<br />

slwsys sn sdmixture of a concern for what is "right" or just. Distribution and<br />

the "mode of<br />

production"<br />

are politically important because they determine the<br />

way of life of a people, their general habits snd opinions, especially<br />

to the law.<br />

Surely it would be best if all men could rationally<br />

with regard<br />

decide what is the best<br />

way of life and then foster it intentionally. Lsws sre necessary, however, pre<br />

cisely because human beings are not entirely rational,<br />

society<br />

and not all members of a<br />

will ever have the leisure to engsge in extended deliberations. A divi<br />

sion of lsbor is necesssry<br />

with the result thst most men will spend most of their<br />

time pursuing s vsriety of essentislly economic tssks. When they<br />

csnnot be<br />

persusded to restrain their scquisitive desires intentionslly snd willingly, it is<br />

necesssry to use force. Force slone does not suffice to produce obedience to the<br />

lsw, however, becsuse it is too clear that force may be used to gratify the<br />

acquisitive desires of the rulers at the expense of the ruled. If most citizens<br />

cannot be persusded to do whst is right or commonly beneficisl for that resson<br />

slone, they msy still obey the lsw because they<br />

see it as in their own economic<br />

interest. Both the distribution of goods snd the kinds of property held sre sub<br />

ject, after all, to legal control. When the laws csnnot shspe or improve the<br />

chsracter of citizens directly, they may approximate the same results indirectly<br />

through economic regulation.<br />

Although Aristotle's name is justly<br />

associsted with the thought thst politicsl


202 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

psrticipation is the only means by<br />

which human beings can realize their full<br />

potential for self-rule, he does not advocate participation per se.12<br />

trary, he seems as interested as James Madison in diffusing<br />

directing<br />

into private and<br />

largely economic directions. Organizing and arguing<br />

On the con<br />

the energies and<br />

the self-interest of those who have not been educated to public service<br />

or pres<br />

suring merely to foster one's own interest at the expense of others does not<br />

difference between public<br />

develop the highest human faculties. There is a big<br />

deliberations concerning the good of the community, or political participation<br />

properly speaking, and interest group<br />

sctivity. Aristotle does not merely point<br />

out the wsy in which the privste pursuit of economic self-interest, ss opposed<br />

to the use of public power to sttsin economic benefits, lesds to more stable,<br />

less oppressive government. He slso points out the brosder effects on the chsr<br />

scter of the populsce, the inculcstion of s relstively<br />

low order of moderation<br />

or self-control, which is a reflection at least of man's higher and fuller capacity<br />

for self-rule. As a student of both Machiavelli and Montesquieu, Msdison sim<br />

ply drops thst concern. The question, of course, is whether we retsin sn sdequste<br />

understsnding<br />

of either legislstion or politics if we ignore the formstive<br />

effects, intended or sccidental, and conceive of government solely<br />

in terms of<br />

what it controls or leaves free from restraint.<br />

Rather than advocate participation, Aristotle supports the rule of law in<br />

almost all cases. The rule of law is ususlly superior to ad hoc decisions, he<br />

srgues, because it is freer from passion and hence more reasonable. Not only is<br />

the law general in application and so freer from personal interest or attachment<br />

than particular decisions made in particular cases, but the law is also the product<br />

of a prior determination of what is right without regard to particular applica<br />

tions. If the law is spt to be better than the legislators' direct adjudication of<br />

specific controversies, however, it cannot be better than the legislators' general<br />

understanding<br />

of what is right and appropriate. Laws thus always reflect the<br />

men who make them, that is, the ruling<br />

body. Good laws cease to be good,<br />

moreover, when<br />

they sre not suited to the psrticulsr people in question; they<br />

will not be obeyed and a negative lesson in reasonableness and order or selfcontrol<br />

will result. There is no substitute<br />

finally<br />

for political wisdom which<br />

combines knowledge of the general principles of politics with observation of<br />

the specific circumstances and the limits these place on the achievement of<br />

what is in itself desirable. In his discussion of the relative merits of the rule<br />

of law and the absolute rule of one man of superior wisdom. Aristotle thus<br />

returns at the end of Book III to the essential tension between the necessary<br />

conditions for political life and the realization of its end that he introduced by<br />

asking<br />

whether mechanics should be citizens.<br />

12. Delba Winthrop, "Aristotle and Political Responsibility," Political Theory, Vol. 3. No. 4<br />

(November 1975), pp. 406-22; Benjamin Barber.<br />

System,"<br />

"The Undemocratic Party in Robert A.<br />

Goldwin, ed., Political Parties, U.S.A. (Washington, D.C.: American Enterprise Institute, 1980),<br />

PP- 34-49: Sheldon Wolin, Politics and Vision (Boston: Little Brown, i960), pp. 58-63.


Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 203<br />

Although the rule of law is almost slwsys to be preferred to individusl dis<br />

cretion, Aristotle srgues thst if one msn is wiser than sll his countrymen com<br />

bined, he should rule sbsolutely. He hss more resson. It would pervert the<br />

end of the sssocistion entirely, moreover, if the better were subordinsted to the<br />

worse. Nevertheless, the rule of the one best msn represents snother extreme<br />

and limiting case, because politicsl relstions are essentially deliberative, con<br />

ducted among equals, and there is no real, interpersonsl exchsnge of opinion or<br />

equslity in the absolute rule of one man. His rule is, therefore, not truly polit<br />

ical. If such an extraordinary man wished to benefit his countrymen,<br />

and such<br />

a man would, he would legislate for them. Political knowledge must be essen<br />

tially practical, because it concerns practice; yet the man who possesses and<br />

acts upon it, should the opportunity<br />

above politics (interestedness) itself.<br />

arise, also stands somewhat outside and<br />

Aristotle's suggestion that political knowledge properly culminates in legis<br />

lation and that the construction of the constitution is the fundamental political<br />

act differs in two importsnt respects from similsr srguments lster offered<br />

by<br />

Mschiavelli concerning the importsnce of "founding" snd<br />

by Roussesu on the<br />

role of the "Legislstor."13 Aristotle certsinly does not suggest thst the legislator<br />

use religion to convince the people who cannot understand the reasons for his<br />

new constitution to adopt it as a matter of divine will. He does recognize the<br />

priesthood as a political office (1322^2-37), but he seems to hsve the exist<br />

ing<br />

institutions in mind. He himself does not indicste much respect for the<br />

Greek Gods or their worship when he observes thst they merely<br />

represent pro<br />

jections of humsn chsrscteristics snd desires (I252b25~30). And he repestedly<br />

urges his resders to svoid one of the commonest mistskes politicisns mske, to<br />

sttempt to deceive or manipulate the people (i297b5-io; 130831-5; I308b30-<br />

40). The second difference follows from the first. Aristotle denies the possi<br />

bility of instituting any radically<br />

new political order. Institutions snd laws<br />

must be suited to the particular character of the people. If these institutions<br />

serve to educate as well as to benefit the people in material ways, as<br />

they can,<br />

this education will occur over time and through practice rather than precept.<br />

Political order is not primarily s mstter of rhetoric any<br />

damentally<br />

a product of force.<br />

Aristotle's Politics thus points more to the possibility<br />

and knowledge than to any<br />

more than it is fun<br />

of political wisdom<br />

specific set of reforms. Here, too, his work stands<br />

in marked contrast to Plsto's Republic, at least on the surface. If political<br />

knowledge consists largely<br />

of reflections on politicsl practice, and practice may<br />

improve on the basis of these reflections, ss Aristotle argues in Book II<br />

(i264ai-5; 1269a), it is extremely unlikely that any<br />

sion to legislate entirely<br />

man will hsve the occa<br />

from scratch. Aristotle observes that it is ss difficult<br />

to reform sn existing regime ss it is to design sn entirely<br />

new one. The leg-<br />

13. Prince VI; Discourses l:xi; Social Contract 11:7.


204 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

islator needs to know both the direction in which to move and the limits of the<br />

possible, that is, to have full political knowledge, in order to achieve even a<br />

small but truly beneficial change. Small changes can hsve cumulstively lsrge<br />

effects.<br />

Aristotle concentrates on whst we can know generally<br />

sbout politicsl sctivity<br />

snd organization rather than making specific recommendstions not only be<br />

csuse the "ought"<br />

depends on the particular circumstances but also because<br />

what we can know far exceeds what we can do.<br />

Even though it is difficult to find the truth in these matters of<br />

equality and justice, it<br />

is easier than to persuade those with the power to act for their own advantage to<br />

act justly. (I3i8bi 5)<br />

Aristotle addresses the Politics primarily to potential rulers, and his advice,<br />

most<br />

simply<br />

stated, is, obey your own laws. Political association depends on<br />

friendship, trust in the character, and faith in the good intentions of the gov<br />

ernors (i295b24-28). Such trust can grow<br />

only on the bssis of experience.<br />

The people will sccept<br />

sny government, Aristotle thinks, thst lesves them<br />

slone.<br />

They will even serve in the army to defend it, if they<br />

1-15). The most important factor in maintaining any government, therefore, is<br />

that the rulers<br />

obey their own laws; they<br />

are paid (1297b<br />

must want to preserve the constitu<br />

tion. Any infraction of the law must be immediately and seriously punished.<br />

Aristotle differs most from both modern political philosophers and con<br />

temporary politicsl scientists in his insistence thst justice is prscticslly<br />

fectively crucisl in politics. It is importsnt not only<br />

snd ef<br />

to tske sccount of whst<br />

people believe is right or their "values," but also to determine and to do what<br />

is beneficial (although not<br />

necessarily equally beneficial) for all members of a<br />

society in order to maintain a regime. The fact that all ruling<br />

groups claim to<br />

rule, ss a mstter of right, for the common good, is not<br />

merely a kind of<br />

"white-washing"<br />

or propaganda. It reflects the fundamental truth about politics.<br />

Human beings associate only for their common benefit or pleasure, and all<br />

these associations reflect their powers of reason. The rationality of these asso<br />

ciations is simply<br />

not complete or uniform. Few men will understand how to<br />

structure institutions; fewer will be farsighted enough to predict the long-term<br />

effects of laws (1308333-35). Although most men sre unsble to live or understsnd<br />

s<br />

fully satisfying life, they<br />

understsnd quite well when their lives or live<br />

lihoods are threatened and take messures to resist. Politicsl associations will<br />

last, therefore, only so long as they benefit most of the inhabitants, even<br />

though the benefits will<br />

largely be rather low and concrete<br />

the right to own a bit of property.<br />

personal safety and<br />

Although Aristotle srgues that it is in the interest of rulers to be just, he<br />

does not express much fsith in the powers of most men to exercise selfcontrol.<br />

The acquisitive desire is too strong, so strong thst in his "bestregim<br />

Aristotle would<br />

unnaturally and unjustly enslave some to perform the tssks of


Aristotle on the Limits and Satisfactions of Political Life 205<br />

the mechanics rather than give the contributions of necessary<br />

goods public rec<br />

ognition<br />

by making srtissns citizens. Short of the best regime, Aristotle ob<br />

serves, rulers tend to use their power to smsss s fortune snd so undermine the<br />

end of politicsl sssocistion itself ss well as the particular regime. In arguing the<br />

essential importance of justice, Aristotle does not preach<br />

any<br />

On the contrary, his Politics differs from Plato's Republic primarily because<br />

selfless<br />

"virtue."<br />

Aristotle puts self-interest first snd foremost. "To feel that something<br />

own makes an inexpressible difference. Love of oneself is surely<br />

natural. Self<br />

is one's<br />

ishness is justly blamed, but this is really not so much love of oneself as love<br />

of oneself more than one<br />

ought"<br />

(I263a4i-i263b5). Beginning<br />

with man's<br />

self-love, Aristotle shows not<br />

only why justice is in the interest of the rulers<br />

but also why<br />

most men are not just most of the time.<br />

The same desire, the desire not only to live but to live well, that gives<br />

rise to politics and the need for justice also limits both. The limits are, in the<br />

first instance, economic. As we have seen, the propagstion snd nurture of fu<br />

ture generations requires the fsmily structure, snd the msintensnce of the fsmily<br />

requires the somewhst unjust subordinstion of women. Fsmilies sre necesssry,<br />

psrticulsrly to educste the young. So long ss there sre differences smong<br />

fsmilies snd there will be differences so long<br />

ss there is s division of lsbor<br />

the division or sllocstion of tasks smong sdults, including governing,<br />

correspond<br />

perfectly<br />

will not<br />

to differences in natural potentisl. Potentisl per se is not<br />

visible or identifisble, snd its sctuslizstion is fostered or restricted<br />

by fsmily<br />

circumstsnce. Aristotle thus shows in psssing thst equsl<br />

opportunity<br />

in the<br />

modern, liberal form is something<br />

of a myth which can never be perfectly<br />

realized. Unlike Plato, Aristotle does not propose<br />

any "noble lies." Aristotle<br />

admits that women need not be confined, that it is not even appropriate, in<br />

democracies and that all contributions or vocations tend to be recognized in<br />

such regimes through universal suffrage. But he suggests that no one will lead<br />

a truly satisfying life in such a regime, no one perhaps but the entirely private<br />

philosopher, because the acquisitive desire is freed, and there is no wsy of<br />

satisfying thst desire for mere life or more goods on its own terms.<br />

Economic desires give rise to competition snd conflict, moreover, snd this<br />

conflict produces s need for government. If humsn beings slwsys set for their<br />

own good, sll governments will be psrtisl to the interests of the ruling group,<br />

however, snd those not in office will have reason to object. No regime will<br />

benefit all those under its control equally,<br />

and no regime will rest on universal<br />

consent. Force will slwsys be necesssry to msintsin order. And, ss s mstter<br />

of fsct in contrast to right, Aristotle observes thst politicsl power tends to<br />

devolve upon those who possess arms (1297b 16-20). Even the legislator who<br />

understsnds thst it is in his own interest to be just, to benefit his fellow citi<br />

zens (actually subjects) rather than to seek to enrich himself at their expense,<br />

will find that he is unable to benefit them all completely<br />

or equally. The neces<br />

sity of providing the basics, food and defense, mandates a division of labor


206 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

which makes it impossible for sll to psrticipate in political deliberations snd<br />

so to develop<br />

their natural potential to the fullest extent possible. Most human<br />

beings will continue to live under laws they<br />

do not make or understand.<br />

Unlike Plato, whose philosophers must be forced to rule (Republic 579c),<br />

Aristotle suggests that politics may also be an inherently satisfying activity. It<br />

is so st Aristotle's own level, however, in thought or deliberation rather than in<br />

effect. In showing the limits of political action, Aristotle thus also teaches a<br />

certain kind of self-restraint. If his resders do not become Utopians or radical<br />

reformers, they also surely do not become nihilists and despair of humanity.


Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice<br />

in The Tempest<br />

Timothy Fuller<br />

The Colorado College<br />

The Tempest begins in a tempest which is to ssy that it begins not only<br />

in s storm but in the midst of time. One msy thus be reminded that the<br />

tempest is both without, imposed by the storm, snd the remembrance of things<br />

past and hoped for within. The passengers on the storm-tossed ship<br />

are chsr<br />

scters constituted out of the circumstances of storm and time. But these are<br />

not<br />

ordinary passengers. Rather, they are, in order of appearance, the ship's<br />

master, the boatswain, the King of Naples, and the apparent Duke of Milan.<br />

They are all, in greater or lesser degree, "authorities", yet<br />

they are all en<br />

compassed within the unsought commsnd of the storm itself. Both Alonso<br />

the king snd Antonio the duke sppesr first with s question, "Where is the<br />

msster?"<br />

Literally, they wish to know where the ship's msster is. However,<br />

ss the play will show, the master is the storm and hence, in that respect,<br />

the master is evident snd everywhere; but beyond this the msster of the storm<br />

is Prospero, who is not evident. It is worth reflection thst a<br />

king<br />

ask where the master is<br />

snd a duke<br />

neither of these masters is the master here. In these<br />

circumstances mastery<br />

is ambiguous.<br />

Next in order of appearance is the old councillor Gonzalo, who advises<br />

patience to the boatswain, who is angry<br />

at the interference of the king and<br />

duke. Gonzalo tries to remind him of who<br />

they<br />

are. This reminder is inef<br />

fective because their authority is usurped by the storm and the ship's master.<br />

The boatswain says to Gonzalo,<br />

"If you can command these elements to silence and work the peace of the present,<br />

we will not hand a rope more; use your<br />

authority"<br />

(i.i. 20-22). '<br />

But Gonzalo also has no authority here. On the other hand, he is heartened<br />

by the apparent authority of the boatswain who "hath no drowning<br />

him"<br />

(i.i. 27). The bostswain is contemptuous of the howling<br />

who are "louder than the westher or our<br />

msrk upon<br />

of the passengers<br />

(i.i. 35). But the recognition<br />

of the boatswain's authority is then undercut by the appearance of Sebastisn,<br />

the brother of the King of Nsples, who curses the boatswain to a faretheewell .<br />

Sebastian is the first character to appear who is neither an authority nor a<br />

This paper was prepared for delivery at the annual meeting of The Midwest Political Science<br />

Association, Cincinnati, Ohio, April 16-18, 1981.<br />

1 All citations from The Tempest are from The Pelican Shakespeare edition edited<br />

by Northrop<br />

Frye, 1970. The New Arden Edition, edited by Frank Kermode (London, 1966), has also been<br />

consulted.


power<br />

srt"<br />

208 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

respecter of authority. But this seems to incite Antonio the duke to curse the<br />

boatswain ss well (i.i.41-42), suggesting thst this apparent authority is not<br />

necessarily a respecter of authority<br />

even though he holds it.<br />

becomes inevitable<br />

As the storm worsens and the need to abandon ship<br />

the King and the Prince pray<br />

but Sebastian and Antonio continue to complain<br />

snd curse. The king snd prince hsve some conventionsl piety<br />

st the<br />

threshhold<br />

of desth but Sebsstisn snd Antonio do not. Rsther, they<br />

king ss the ship<br />

sbsndon the<br />

breaks apart. Gonzalo affects a certain degree of patience<br />

sbout his own counsel in ssying "the wills sbove be done" (i.i. 62).<br />

One msy<br />

summsrize the first scene of the plsy by ssying thst it dramatizes<br />

the uncertainty of authority<br />

in the face of the elements. This reminds us of<br />

our<br />

temporality or mortality, and that better and worse responses can be made<br />

to this drama of uncertain authority. The ship's master and bostswsin respond<br />

with hsbitusl skill to their fsmilisr adversity; Gonzslo responds with resignation;<br />

the King and the Prince with conventional pieties; and Sebastian and Antonio<br />

with fear snd self-preserving instinct.<br />

The second scene tempestuousness.<br />

It opens with s speech of Mirsnds, the wondering one, who<br />

provides<br />

tranquility<br />

sntitheticsl to the first scene's<br />

begins,<br />

"If by your srt, my dearest father" (i.ii.i). The tranquility<br />

is presented not<br />

only in a rhetoric of reflection and wonder, or philosophically, for philosophy<br />

appears in the first scene only tangentially in Gonzalo's resignation, but also<br />

in the unsmbiguous relstion of<br />

suthority between fsther snd child, snd in the<br />

sense of commsnd thst is implied by reference to Prospero's<br />

"srt"<br />

But Mirsnds<br />

also exhibits two other characteristics in her first speech: the first is the capacity<br />

for suffering empathetically<br />

with the victims of the storm; the second is her<br />

insistence that if she were a "god of<br />

to preserve rather than to destroy<br />

she would have used her power<br />

the ship. The daughter of Prospero antici<br />

pates the conclusion to which Prospero himself will come at the end of the<br />

play, except that the literal sense in which she seems to speak will be trans<br />

formed in Prospero's finsl reslizstion when he ss the precise "god of<br />

preserves rather than destroys by an act of renouncing the very<br />

power which<br />

is his. By snticipsting in her speech Prospero's lster sction. Mirsnds transforms<br />

sn sbstrsct proposition sbout life into 3 self-ensctment in the midst of life.<br />

Prospero's renunciation will be the reslity<br />

power justly.<br />

behind Mirsnds's desire to use<br />

A further indicstion of this is thst Prospero, in telling Miranda the full<br />

background of their situation for the first time, begins by asking<br />

her to "Lend<br />

thy hsnd / And pluck my msgic gsrment from me. So, / Lie there my<br />

(i.ii. 23-25). This is the first occssion for Prospero to renounce his msgic<br />

srt.<br />

Underlying the spectscle which csuses Mirsnds's amszement is s history<br />

of events events not at sll msgical. Prospero's commsnd to "be<br />

(i.ii. 13) is fulfilled through Prospero's recollection. The lsying<br />

sside of Pros<br />

pero's gsrment of magical authority is connected to his revelation of the loss


sssur<br />

Temporal Royalties and Virtue' s Airy Voice in The Tempest 209<br />

of his authority in Milan. The setting aside of the magic garment is also the<br />

setting<br />

sside of the childhood illusion sbout the authoritstive psrent.<br />

Mirands professes to remember "rather like s dream thsn sn<br />

something of her esrliest childhood in Milsn. And, ss the story<br />

begins to be<br />

unfolded Mirsnda wonders whether their coming to the islsnd wss s curse or<br />

s blessing (i.ii.60-62). To this Prospero snswers "both" Literally it is a curse<br />

to be exiled, but also s<br />

blessing thst they were sble to survive. But it is,<br />

more importantly, the occasion for reflection on the proper order of things.<br />

Thus, the tempest produced in scene i is paralleled<br />

by the calmer tempest<br />

of recollection in scene ii, which Prospero produces in Miranda as her first<br />

confrontation with the ambiguities thst wonder produces. Mirsnds is swsre<br />

of this insofsr as she sees thst Prospero's troubled sspect is csused<br />

by her<br />

"remembrance"<br />

of her early childhood (i.ii.64-65). Remembrance is thus a<br />

blessing and a curse. But, ultimately, remembering is necessary<br />

have the understanding<br />

if one is to<br />

thst is the msrk of humsn wisdom on humsn things.<br />

For, while it is true thst Antonio's exercise of the power Prospero entrusted<br />

to him "set sll hesrts i' th' state / To what tune pleased his<br />

ear,"<br />

it is also<br />

true that Prospero was the true source of this sad state of affairs. The tempest<br />

produced in Miranda is a reflection of the tempest within Prospero himself.<br />

Prospero's recollections excite Mirsnds's. The tempestuousness is constituted<br />

out of Prospero's inner intellectusl sscent following his sctusl political descent<br />

from first duke in Italy to exile, in juxtaposition to Antonio's assumption of<br />

the "outward face of<br />

a "god of<br />

royalty"<br />

(i.ii. 104), which is a political ascent to being<br />

power"<br />

but a descent in the sense of a revelstion of the corruption<br />

of his soul in endless smbition.<br />

Prospero now sees thst Antonio, unlike Prospero, csnnot comprehend the<br />

thought thst s library could be s sufficient dukedom. Thus, Antonio concludes<br />

thst Prospero is incspsble of exercising "temporal royslties". For Antonio,<br />

the cspscity to exercise temporal royalties seems to be exhibited in endlessly<br />

growing ambition. He thus made a pact with the King of Naples that, in<br />

return for tribute, the would support<br />

King his extirpation of Prospero and<br />

Miranda from Milan. Fearing an outcry from the people of Milan, however,<br />

the conspirators set Prospero and Miranda adrift in the sea rather than kill<br />

them outright, and so they were left "To cry to<br />

th' sea"<br />

(i.ii. 149).<br />

Their eventual ssfe srrivsl on this enchsnted isle wss msde possible<br />

by the<br />

generosity of Gonzslo, who hsd pity<br />

on them, providing them with sustensnce<br />

both edible snd intellectual. Prospero calls this an act of providence, and sn<br />

set of chsrity. This remembrance of providentisl<br />

charity is the second instance,<br />

following Miranda's innocent charitsble instinct, thst reinforces the mercifulness<br />

thst will eventuste from Prospero's recollections of things psst.<br />

This moment slso msrks the occssion of a new<br />

beginning<br />

for Prospero.<br />

What wss recollected ss prior misfortune is sbout to turn to his sdvsntsge.<br />

Fortune is now "bountiful", now his dear lady, for she has brought his enemies


stsr"<br />

210 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

to the shore where he currently exercises his authority. The descent from power<br />

into humiliation is the premise of the plays<br />

beginning but the action of the<br />

play proper is, virtually from the outset, an ascent. This structural feature<br />

supports the oft-made remark among the critics that this play is, in an im<br />

portant sense, the sequel to King Lear; and that the theme of ascent and<br />

descent is not only to be found repestedly<br />

within the plsys but runs through<br />

the Shskespesresn corpus generally. (See, for exsmple, D. G. Jsmes in The<br />

Dream of Prospero.)<br />

Prospero hss been presented with sn "suspicious<br />

whose influence he must court if his fortunes sre not forever sfter "to droop"<br />

(i.ii. 178-184). But if Prospero's fortunes sre not drooping, Mirsnds's eye<br />

lids sre, snd she perforce retires ss Prospero's servsnt Ariel mskes his first<br />

appesrsnce.<br />

Ariel reports thst he hss carried out in precise detail the raising<br />

of the<br />

storm on the ship as directed by Prospero. He has deposited Ferdinand alone<br />

in s ssfe snd obscure<br />

on the isle, dispersed the others sbout, snchored the ship<br />

hsrbor, snd put the crew to sleep below deck. The remsinder of Prospero's<br />

plsn must be csrried out between 2 p.m. snd 6 p.m. The moment of fortune<br />

already referred to is reinforced by<br />

the compression of time in which all the<br />

remaining action is to be undertaken, which, as noted<br />

by scholsrs, is roughly<br />

equivslent to the time it tskes to perform the plsy itself.<br />

In the conversation between Prospero and Ariel it turns out thst the exile<br />

Prospero wss preceded on the isle by the exile Sycorax, sn evil msgicisn,<br />

who is contrasted to the exiled good msgician. Ariel has been transferred from<br />

serving black magic to white magic or from serving evil to serving<br />

good. If<br />

Sycorax had the power to imprison Ariel, Prospero had the power to release<br />

him. The release wss predicated on service, for a time, to Prospero. Ariel<br />

is engaged in working<br />

off this indebtedness. And, although the action of the<br />

play is to run from 2 p.m. to 6 p.m., the freedom of Ariel is to come after<br />

two days (i.ii. 229), presumably to give him time to guide all back to Milan.<br />

During<br />

the dozen years when Ariel was incarcerated in a pine tree he<br />

howled and screamed in such a way<br />

as to create a tempest of his own on<br />

the isle. Sycorax caused this condition but did not have the power to amend<br />

the torment that resulted. What remains is for Ariel to become like a nymph<br />

of the sea and to be invisible to all but himself and Prospero. He initiates<br />

his invisibility by exiting, whereupon Miranda is bidden to wake up. It is<br />

thus clear that Miranda is not at this point to be given sight of Ariel.<br />

She is, however, against her wishes, to be given sight of Caliban, whom<br />

she detests as a villain. Caliban is Prospero's slave and is addressed as "esrth"<br />

(i.ii. 314). Cslibsn presents himself as the ruler of the isle by<br />

right as the off<br />

spring of Sycorax. Thus, for Caliban, Prospero is the usurper who, as we<br />

know, has arrived here because of<br />

being usurped. But Caliban had attempted<br />

the overthrow of Prospero by raping Miranda in the hope of populating the<br />

islsnd with Cslibans. This stirs Mirands to curse Cslibsn. Unable to be im<br />

printed with goodness, Caliban wants to imprint goodness with himself, to


Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice in The Tempest 21 1<br />

subdue it to his power. To be imprinted with goodness is, for Miranda, to be<br />

taught how to speak snd, thus, to be sble to pursue one's purposes self<br />

consciously. But it would appesr thst the purposes of Cslibsn when brought<br />

to self-swsreness sre unsavory to ssy the least. Caliban's view is that the<br />

how to curse. This might be expected from the<br />

result of language is knowing<br />

offspring<br />

of Sycorax.<br />

It would appear that we have here a confrontation between two first responses<br />

to the human condition. One, in Miranda, has been revealed as<br />

seeing the<br />

noble in the world and<br />

being revolted by the ignoble. The fsct that, in her<br />

innocence, she may not always accurately distinguish one from the other does<br />

not alter the point about her disposition. The other response, in Caliban, consists<br />

in the heightening<br />

of self-assertion as the consequence of self-awareness.<br />

Whether it was Prospero who taught Caliban speech, or Miranda who taught<br />

Cslibsn whst Prospero taught her (the matter is disputed by scholars), in the<br />

most important sense both Miranda and Caliban are the results of Prospero's<br />

tutelage. Prospero has the capacity to unlock both orderliness and disorderliness<br />

but, in these two cases, has remained in control of both. On the isle Prospero's<br />

rule is both just and competent.<br />

The scene now shifts to Ferdinand, accompanied by the invisible but audible<br />

Ariel. The tempest in Ferdinand's soul, a consequence of the supposed loss<br />

of his father the king, is allayed<br />

by Ariel's music. Ferdinand intuits that the<br />

song is in the service of some god of the island. The sweet air calms the<br />

waters and also his spiritusl frenzy,<br />

esrth-<br />

snd he is led on by it. It is no<br />

bound sound snd it is sbove him.<br />

Just as Ferdinand is led on by a spirit, so Miranda, on being directed by<br />

Prospero to raise her eyes to look on Ferdinand, is taken by<br />

what she thinks<br />

a spirit<br />

Ferdinsnd himself. To Mirsnda, Ferdinand is a divine thing and<br />

that Prospero kept Ariel invisible to Miranda and brought<br />

noble. It is likely<br />

her directly to gaze upon Caliban in order to educate her gazing<br />

upon Ferdinand.<br />

Thus, Prospero orchestrates the first encounter of Mirands snd Ferdinsnd. Esch<br />

is returning from sn encounter with the distssteful: in Mirsnds's esse the<br />

encounter with Cslibsn; in Ferdinand's case the encounter with a storm-tossed<br />

sea snd the grief of losing his fsther. Ferdinand sees Mirands ss divine snd<br />

s goddess<br />

he supposes her the source of the sweet airs he has been hearing.<br />

The proper union of male and female is the encounter of the divine within<br />

the human and this is not presented as a mistsken perception on the p3rt of<br />

either/ It is the conclusion to which Prospero directs them both.<br />

Whst results is s complex insight into the problem of ruling 3nd being<br />

2. Upon reflection, readers may ask themselves. What is there really<br />

divine about this en<br />

counter? The answer is that Ferdinand and Miranda respond to each other<br />

by interpreting their<br />

meeting as the encountering of divinity. Moreover, their response to each other throughout the<br />

play is intellectualized and ritualized (they play chess) in a manner unmistakably reminiscent of<br />

the neoplatonic attitude that the divine is intimated in those striking human interactions which<br />

reveal unplumbed depths of experience, drawing thought beyond all ordinary<br />

sideration into the mysteries of conscious life.<br />

objects of con


212 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

ruled. Ferdinsnd, thinking he hss met s goddess of the islsnd,<br />

3sks if she csn<br />

direct his conduct there, snd if she is s maid. She surprises him by speaking<br />

his langusge. This reminds Ferdinsnd that, as his f3ther is now<br />

spp3rently<br />

desd, he is the le3ding spesker of thst lsngusge ss the new king, or thst he<br />

would be if he were st home in Nsples (i.ii.422ff.). Thus, divine spirit hss<br />

recognized divine spirit, or roysl person hss encountered royal person. Prospero<br />

rules Mirands snd the King of Nsples still rules Ferdinsnd; nonetheless,<br />

their potentisl msrks them for each other, and together they constitute the<br />

key to the reconciliation of Milan and Nsples thst must tske plsce lster.<br />

Ferdinsnd st this point understsndsbly thinks of Milsn ss subordinate to Naples<br />

because he thinks Alonso has ruled Antonio. But of course Prospero rules<br />

them all on this isle. He will be able to transfer this rule to Miranda and<br />

Ferdinand, thus achieving what, for example, Lear could not achieve. Prospero's<br />

intention has succeeded, for Ferdinand and Miranda "have changed<br />

now Ferdinand has ceased<br />

thinking<br />

eyes"<br />

and<br />

of Miranda as a goddess and begun to<br />

think her a virgin eligible to be queen of Naples.3 But just as she is not<br />

ready to be relessed from the tutelsge of Prospero, so Ferdinsnd is not yet<br />

free of due submission to the old king.<br />

Wishing to keep mstters complicsted for s time, Prospero sccuses Ferdinsnd<br />

of<br />

arriving with trescherous intent to usurp<br />

Prospero's position. Prospero's<br />

threst to imprison Ferdinand draws manly resistance which is immediately<br />

overcome<br />

by<br />

Prospero's hypnotic charm. As with the Duke in Measure for<br />

Measure Prospero is exemplary<br />

of the union of power and justice as is evi<br />

denced by his use of power here to unite those who should be together.<br />

The first scene of the second act begins with Gonzalo's speech of conso<br />

lation: the threshold of death is present for human beings every day<br />

theme of<br />

it is "our<br />

woe"<br />

(u.i.6) as human. But few live through impending mortality<br />

to enjoy<br />

merriment once more. One ought to weigh sorrow against comfort.<br />

Alonso turns this consolation aside, undoubtedly considering the apparent loss<br />

of his son, and Antonio and Sebastian make fun of Gonzalo. Just as they<br />

showed themselves to no advsntsge in the opening<br />

scene's confrontstion with<br />

desth, so now<br />

they seem, hsving escsped, to hsve forgotten the ordinsry<br />

mortslity of life which Gonzalo wisely enough has not forgotten. Gonzalo<br />

thus remembers, parallel to Prospero, and in remembering the human condition<br />

is ensbled to see opportunity in it as well as danger, and, more importantly,<br />

opportunity of an ennobling sort.<br />

It can be said that Sebastian and Antonio are mindful of opportunities<br />

too. However, their notion of opportunity is entirely<br />

and conspiracy.<br />

Every<br />

desth<br />

one of self-assertion<br />

occssion of life is the razor edge between life snd<br />

most<br />

significsntly between the life snd desth of whstever potentisl<br />

3. One may note here the coalescence of the divine, the political-legal, and the passionate<br />

in a single dramatic moment. A comparison of the method by<br />

Measure for Measure, among other plays, would be pertinent.<br />

which this is brought about in


Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice in The Tempest 213<br />

for nobility there msy<br />

be in the soul of an individual. How such occasions<br />

sre used will determine whst sssessment is to be msde of the chsrscter enscted<br />

and so revealed.<br />

Every<br />

set is s self-disclosure. But whst is disclosed is not<br />

only<br />

sn sssessment of whst sction is required. An sction is slso s consequence<br />

of the understsnding<br />

the drsmstic identity<br />

thst informs the attempt st self-ensctment which constitutes<br />

of s<br />

chsrscter.4<br />

is entertsined, that's offered / Comes to<br />

As Gonzslo ssys, "When every grief<br />

th' entertsiner"<br />

(n.i. 16-17).<br />

Gonzslo's stoic spirit is ridiculed<br />

by Sebsstisn snd Antonio. The play on<br />

"dollar"<br />

and<br />

"dolor"<br />

(n.i.19) reveals the preoccupation of Sebsstisn as well<br />

as Gonzalo's stubborn persistsnee in trying to console Alonso, who prefers<br />

not to be bothered. So slso Adrisn's sttempt to see s delicste climste or<br />

temperance on the isle is ridiculed ss the sweet smell of the rotting lung or<br />

perfumed fen. Whst's green to Gonzslo is tswny to Antonio. Gonzslo sees<br />

them snd their garments as refreshed and glossy, not ses- water stained. He<br />

refuses to entertain the grief that might be expected in their situation. By<br />

contrast, Sebastian, when he turns to Alonso, chides him for insisting<br />

on the<br />

marriage of his daughter in Tunis against their advice and thus setting in<br />

train a series of events which led to their wreck and the loss of Ferdinand.<br />

Alonso's fate, looked at in this way, is the result of his own actions and<br />

parallels Prospero's. There is a way, then, in which Sebastian has a clearer<br />

perception thsn Gonzslo, who wishes to console, to look on the bright side.<br />

Gonzslo is decent but sbstrsct. He speculstes thst here is a place for a new<br />

commonwealth as a natural anarchy,<br />

close to nature and without sovereignty.<br />

But as Sebastian and Antonio point out, this order without a sovereign would<br />

be founded by an act of sovereignty. Thus, "the latter end of his common<br />

wealth forgets the beginning" (11. i. 154).<br />

Among other things, this means that<br />

innocence in this commonwealth would require innocence of its origins. The<br />

extended description given<br />

by Gonzalo of his vision is quite clearly<br />

of a<br />

pre-<br />

4. Michael Oakeshott is invoked here because he expresses a view of conduct remarkably<br />

like that of Shakespeare's: "This unresolved and inconclusive character of human conduct is<br />

qualified (and not merely concealed)<br />

when actions are recognized as self-enactments; that is,<br />

when<br />

they are understood in terms of the sentiments in which they<br />

are performed. There is at<br />

least the echo of an imperishable achievement when the valour of the agent and not the soonto-vanish<br />

victory, when his loyalty and fortitude and not the evanescent defeat, are the con<br />

siderations.<br />

But nowhere is it more than a distant echo. Self-enactment (virtuous or other<br />

wise) is itself an episodic and an inconclusive engagement, as ondoyant and as full of unresolved<br />

tensions as any other the enacted self is itself a fugitive; not a generic unity but a dramatic<br />

identity."<br />

Michael Oakeshott, On Human Conduct (Oxford, 1975). P- 84.<br />

Self-enactment has to do with "an agent's sentiment in choosing and performing the actions<br />

he chooses and performs<br />

the 'motive' of an action is the action itself considered in terms<br />

of the sentiment or sentiments in which it is chosen and performed<br />

choosing<br />

an action<br />

is always meaning to procure a satisfaction in a motive of some sort an agent thinking as<br />

he chooses to think and enacting or re-enacting himself as he wishes to be what the agent<br />

of his<br />

chooses to think is related to his understanding and respect for himself, to the integrity<br />

character, and not at all to his understanding of a contingent situation to which he must respond<br />

by choosing an<br />

action."<br />

Op. cit., pp. 70-74.


214 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

fallen psrsdise where there would be neither lsbor nor struggle nor<br />

mortslity<br />

but "sll<br />

sbundsnce"<br />

(ii.i.159). But this vision which Gonzslo intends as a<br />

further consolation to Alonso is to Alonso "nothing" (11. i. 166). This dream<br />

world commonwealth is known by Gonzalo to be nothing, that is, it is a<br />

speculative dream. It can be understood in parallel to Prospero's dream-world<br />

commonwealth which he eventually dissolves as a nothing,<br />

and perhaps slso in<br />

psrsllel to Cslibsn's sim to people the islsnd with Cslibsns. Whst is envisioned<br />

by esch is revelstory of the chsrscter snd motives of esch.<br />

Ariel sppesrs snd puts Gonzslo snd Alonso to sleep. This lesves the field<br />

of imsginstion to Antonio, who sees s crown on Sebsstisn's hesd. Sebsstisn<br />

sre in<br />

csnnot tell whether Antonio is swske or dresming. He sees thst they<br />

3 dre3ming state while awske. Antonio, on the other hsnd, 3ccuses Sebsstisn<br />

of not<br />

exercising his imsginstion snd thus sllowing<br />

he lives,<br />

or slumber while he wskes (11. i. 2 10).<br />

his fortunes to die while<br />

One might conclude st this point thst every character in the play<br />

is the<br />

embodiment of his dream within the larger dresm of life. Idyllic 3nd Mschisvellisn<br />

dresms 3re presented here in the common context of the lsrger dresm of<br />

life which overrides them all. Esch character makes s world for itself where<br />

its m3nifeststion of itself would be ssfe or sppropriste. Sebastian recognizes<br />

this by retorting<br />

that Antonio's speech to him is snoring. Who then is 3wske<br />

snd who ssleep?<br />

But this turns into s distinction between Antonio's smbition, which is to in<br />

crease Sebastian's stature threefold to be the teacher of ambition and Sebas<br />

tian's confession of laziness. Sebastian's natural<br />

tendency<br />

is to ebb<br />

(ll.i.216-<br />

17), but his ebbing<br />

encourages Antonio's ambitiousness. Antonio will teach<br />

Sebastian ambition in a<br />

way reminiscent of the manner in which, so to speak,<br />

he taught Prospero about ambition<br />

by overthrowing him. The man of ambition<br />

looks for opportunities to realize ambition. For now, Antonio can realize his<br />

ambition through Sebastian. This moment of grief for Alonso and resignation<br />

for Gonzslo is a new<br />

beginning<br />

for Antonio. With Ferdinand and Claribel out<br />

of the wsy, Antonio wishes thst he were Sebsstian (11. i. 260-61 ).<br />

But as Sebastian takes Antonio's meaning he remembers that Antonio over<br />

threw Prospero. This should be a source of discomfort to Sebastian. However,<br />

Antonio uses it as s mesns to persusde Sebsstisn: "True. / And look how well<br />

my gsrments sit upon me, / Much fester thsn before. My brother's servsnts /<br />

Were then my fellows; now<br />

they sre my<br />

men"<br />

(11. i. 266-68). Antonio thinks<br />

that power makes the man this is his dream whereas the play<br />

seems to be<br />

saying that power shows the man for what he is. One notes also that, whereas<br />

in Gonzalo's dream there would be a natural anarchy, or a spontaneous equality<br />

of men and women, Antonio's dream is of<br />

tyranny and distinction in his favor.<br />

His dream is consistent with his sction. This disturbing<br />

Sebsstisn to remind Antonio of his "conscience"<br />

turn of events prompts<br />

Antonio confesses thst T<br />

feel not this deity in my bosom" (11. i. 271-72). Not only is Antonio sn stheist


things"<br />

Temporal Royalties and<br />

Virtue'<br />

s Airv Voice in The Tempest 215<br />

with respect to the clsims of conscience but he has no kindred or<br />

brotherly<br />

upon"<br />

feeling: "Here lies your brother, / No better than the earth he lies<br />

(ii. i. 274-75). Antonio's contempt and ambition are a full realization of his<br />

Machiavellisn chsracter. He seems to be what he is because he hss sn enormous<br />

capacity to forget his own mortality or to be unimpressed by it. He can, in<br />

short, see the mortality in sll others but not in himself. He is psrsllel to<br />

Cslibsn in wishing to populate the world only with his own image, but becsuse,<br />

unlike Cslibsn, he has the sttributes of full humanity, he is a lower character<br />

than Caliban because he hss the cspscity<br />

reslity<br />

to dissemble in order to exploit the<br />

of the humsn condition. If Alonso is no better thsn the earth he lies<br />

upon, which, in one sense, is certainly true of human beings, then for Antonio<br />

it is slso true thst Prospero is no more slive thsn the books he studied in<br />

seclusion. Cslibsn at least recognizes that there is power in books (m.ii.89 90).<br />

The earth of which sll humsnity is constituted is made human in the selfenactment<br />

of the dreams which imprint the earthiness with form. Who con<br />

trols the teaching of form to matter will make a difference. Sebastian, a<br />

slothful fellow who describes himself as "standing<br />

(11. i. 2 16), that is as<br />

matter, will be imprinted here with Antonio's form of smbition. His quick<br />

submission to Antonio's plans is explained by the fact that the submissive,<br />

passive type, low in ambition, is easily<br />

persuaded.<br />

Having little imaginative<br />

vision of self-enactment, he can live on that of another. The watery Sebsstisn<br />

is properly<br />

slothful snd phlegmatic. Thus Antonio's case becomes his precedent<br />

(n. i. 284). Alonso's sleep<br />

shall be like Prospero's study. Neither study<br />

nor<br />

grief can be comprehended<br />

by<br />

the ambitious or the slothful. The alliance of<br />

ambition and sloth is a powerful source of wickedness in the ordering<br />

of humsn<br />

sffairs.<br />

Now Ariel intervenes to rouse Gonzalo and thus return the favor Gonzalo<br />

extended to Prospero, and Gonzalo and Alonso, being saved, set off to search for<br />

Ferdinand. The second scene of Act II plays Cslibsn, Trinculo and Stephano.<br />

Caliban's first real look at Stephano and Trinculo (11.ii.114)<br />

they<br />

are "fine<br />

convinces him that<br />

This is parallel to Miranda's first look at Ferdinand<br />

and offers the proper comparison of noble to bsse innocence. Cslibsn thinks<br />

they sre from the moon snd he will conduct these "gods" on a tour of the<br />

island. He prefers their drink to Prospero's servitude. They, believing them<br />

selves the only survivors, now plan to inherit this island kingdom. Caliban<br />

shows his slavish nature in wishing to submit himself to yet s new msster.<br />

In the mesntime, Act III, scene i, opens with the enslsved Ferdinsnd,<br />

whose burdens sre nothing when redeemed by the thought thst he is serving<br />

Mirands. She revesls her name to him, against her father's command, and<br />

Ferdinand opines that she is flswless and the first such a one that he has<br />

met. She thinks his form outstrips all imagination and ssys so, thus sgsin<br />

depsrting from her father's commands to honor discretion. He reveals that,<br />

though s log-msn now, in 3Ctuslity he is 3 prince.


216 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

There follows a series of professions in which esch seeks to be the servsnt of<br />

the other. Love induces self-tempering<br />

and marks the contrast to the ambitious<br />

Antonio and slothful Sebasti3n who sre incspable of love or self-restraint.<br />

Love is the bondage that is free (m.i.89).5<br />

We are<br />

immediately reminded of the bondage that is not free by<br />

appearance of Caliban, Stephano and Trinculo at the outset of Act III,<br />

the re<br />

scene ii.<br />

Caliban entreats Stephano to overthrow Prospero so that Stephano can rule<br />

and favor Caliban. Freedom here is equated with self-assertion once more.<br />

Again we have presented what might be called the tyrsnnicsl imsginstion ss<br />

opposed to the noble imsgination suffused<br />

by charity. But the conspiracy is<br />

constantly being upset by the presence of Ariel's airy voice, which makes it<br />

appear that Caliban is simultsneously sttscking Trinculo, thus setting<br />

the con<br />

spirators sgsinst esch other. Ariel spesks in Trinculo's voice snd thus csuses<br />

Stephsno to drive Trinculo further away from him. Cslibsn then proposes<br />

thst they murder Prospero in his sleep, so thst Stephsno will be sble to rule,<br />

to possess Mirsnds snd to create offspring<br />

for the islsnd. Thus Cslibsn will<br />

schieve his own sspirstion vicsriously. Csliban is to Stephano as Antonio is<br />

to Sebastian.<br />

But Ariel is intervening again and playing<br />

tunes which csuse fright. Cslibsn<br />

counsels cslmness because the isle is "full of noises, / Sounds and sweet sirs<br />

thst give delight and hurt<br />

not"<br />

(m.ii.130). These sounds orchestrate Caliban's<br />

sleeping and waking and his description spurs Stephano's desire to rule. How<br />

ever, Caliban reminds him that the condition of this rule is the destruction of<br />

Prospero. But it would appear that the sweet sound of the isle might disappear<br />

with the destruction of Prospero. There is nothing in the speech of Caliban<br />

to suggest thst the sweet sound of the isle is not dependent on Prospero snd<br />

Ariel even though, of course, Csliban dissociates the sound from Prospero's<br />

rule. When Caliban dreams, he dresms of riches thst<br />

drop from the clouds,<br />

but he does not understsnd thst the dresm of riches is fulfilled in living<br />

surrounded by the sweet hsrmonies of just rule. Thus, not surprisingly, he<br />

believes thst the sweet riches he alresdy enjoys are inferior to what would<br />

come if the "dreams" were to become<br />

"realities"<br />

in the reign of Stephano.<br />

Caliban cannot learn the deeper lesson of dreaming, and thus also cannot<br />

appreciate the rule of the just, which would be to live encompassed in the<br />

harmonious imagination. If this action is a metaphor for the dramatic art<br />

itself, as seems likely, then it may also be said that Caliban cannot appreciate<br />

the rule of the poetic as what distinguishes the human being<br />

from mere esrth.<br />

Act III, scene iii, brings us bsck to Alonso's psrty. The scene opens with<br />

both Gonzslo snd Alonso wesry from wsndering in s msze. Alonso tells<br />

Gonzslo, "Sit down snd rest. / Even here I will put off my hope, snd<br />

keep<br />

5. For Antonio, self-restraint is only concealed ambition. For Sebastian, there is only the<br />

inertia that prevents attempting much. For the former, everything is permissible; for the latter,<br />

most things are too much trouble.


Temporal Royalties and Virtue' s Airy Voice in The Tempest 217<br />

it / No longer for my flstterer: he is drowned" (in. iii.6-8). This is noticesbly<br />

s prefiguring of Prospero's renuncistion speech in Act V, scene i, 3nd reminds<br />

one of Prospero's first renuncistion in Act I, scene ii. Thst the "ses mocks /<br />

Our frustrate sesrch on tend" (m. iii. 9-10) indicstes not only the literal situstion<br />

ss it sppears to Alonso, but also indicstes the dresm world of the islsnd's<br />

relstion to the stormy condition of temporal, humsn existence, whose undulation<br />

mocks the powers of the human imagination to order the world in its own<br />

image. That this is intimated in the attitude of Gonzalo and Alonso is drsmstized<br />

by the contrast immediately<br />

Antonio snd Sebsstisn.<br />

made with the attitude now shsred between<br />

Immedistely following thst dramstic contrsst 3 new hsrmony<br />

snd sweet<br />

music srise, sccompsnied<br />

by s bsnquet. Typicslly, Gonzslo snd Alonso sre<br />

refreshed and inspired, while Sebastian and Antonio respond with touristic<br />

amusement. The appearing<br />

shspes sre, to Alonso,<br />

more gentle snd kind than<br />

human beings. And, in sn aside, Prospero editorializes that Alonso speaks<br />

well because some there are worse thsn devils. The gentle but monstrous<br />

shspes vanish but the food remains, and Alonso lapses back into his despairing<br />

thought that "the best is<br />

past ss<br />

"prologue"<br />

past"<br />

(in. iii. 51), which contrasts usefully<br />

with Antonio's<br />

(u.i.247). One is led to reflect that Prospero, in a manner<br />

very reminiscent of the Duke in Measure for Measure, has arranged things<br />

so that at this moment in the drama the wicked see opportunity<br />

where the decent<br />

see only cause for despair, and that this arrangement must be emblematic<br />

of a providentisl<br />

ordering thst one would nsturslly<br />

associste with the nsme of<br />

Prospero. Underlying the perceived order is snother order but it is one only<br />

intimsted in the vsnishing moments of time. If it is true,<br />

thst the good differ from God only in the element of time,<br />

the thought that our vision of right order is fleeting<br />

divine would almost<br />

certainly<br />

ss Senecs remsrked,<br />

reflection compels<br />

and ondoyant while the<br />

be firm and constant. But this is also connected<br />

to the poetic insight which underlies the play<br />

and connects the human condition<br />

to Shakespeare's art. For it is poetic vision which discovers something<br />

of<br />

grest constancy in the midst of endless becoming. One may<br />

agree with Douglas<br />

Peterson that "time in the Renaissance cosmology is only<br />

the measure of<br />

that poetic vision<br />

motion, a condition rather thsn sn sgent,"6 snd go on to ssy<br />

in responding to the intimations of immortality is agency<br />

par excellence. If,<br />

following Hooker, we were to admit that time "neither causeth things nor<br />

opportunities of things, although it comprise and contain both" (Ecc. Pol.<br />

11.383), we would be led on to think that time is suffused with being because<br />

time is the humsn experience which, in its fleetingness, excites unsvoidsbly<br />

the thought of the eternal. On the other hand, we will also note thst the<br />

providentisl design here is Prospero's snd thst it will come to sn end with<br />

the ending of the plsy. The constancy<br />

of the poetic vision is itself, sfter<br />

6. Douglas L. Peterson, Time Tide and Tempest, A Study of Shakespeare's Romances (San<br />

Marino, 1973). P- r7-


. . Thou<br />

218 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

sll, fleeting snd not constsncy unquslified. To quote Peterson sgain, "All<br />

temporal things sctively psrticipste in the eternal. On the other hand, to be<br />

more sharply aware of process is to be more remorseless-<br />

sharply<br />

aware of its<br />

ness and of the precariousness and<br />

dependency<br />

of one's existence upon<br />

it."7<br />

This new precariousness which denies the possibility of ignoring the temporal<br />

in sn act of contemplstion intimstes the superiority<br />

of poetic vision to philo<br />

sophic or theologicsl vision, superiority not in seeing further thsn philosophy<br />

or theology but in seeing ss creatures of crumbling dust must see: "A breath<br />

thou art, / Servile to sll the skyey influences . srt Desth's fool"<br />

(Measure for Measure,<br />

m.i.8 1 1).<br />

Humsnity is free not to be not temporal,<br />

but free to choose in self-ensctment its visions, snd by<br />

such visions to be<br />

known sfter the occssions of their initial sppesrsnce have passed, snd the<br />

instigstors with them. It is s question of seeing<br />

ssnd, of seeing substsntislity in the merest momentsry contiguity<br />

s universe in a grain of<br />

of goings-on.<br />

Time is duration to be endured. Self-ensctment is enduring according to an<br />

agent's self-understanding. Prospero drags his opponents into confrontation<br />

with time as duration but in the shelter of the island. The reduction in com<br />

plexity of life thus achieved allows the drsmstic evocstion of the timeless<br />

presence in the midst of time. It slso permits the revelstion snd assessment<br />

of the characters. What distinguishes one character from another is the use<br />

each character makes of time. Nobility of response is connected to seeing<br />

the contingency of the human condition as persistently occasioning the necessity<br />

of love and forgiveness. Whst Prospero will finslly schieve is the extension<br />

of the occssions of the right use of<br />

temporality by the marriage of Ferdinand<br />

and Miranda, as almost all commentators have noticed. What has changed<br />

from Measure for Measure to The Tempest is that the poetic vision has become<br />

the rule of restraint on the enchanted isle instead of the resurgent law of<br />

Vienna.8<br />

Such agency is to be seen as<br />

teasing constancy<br />

out of nothingness, and in<br />

this way is the mark of the play itself. The plsy msy<br />

be understood as an<br />

7. Op. cit., pp. 20-21.<br />

8. The reader may wonder to what extent this is a specifically<br />

Christian interpretation of<br />

the play's action. It is true that the virtues of love and forgiveness are specifically associated<br />

with Christiantiy. It is also true that there are many occasions of Christian symbolism in Shake<br />

speare's play which cannot be dismissed as mere ironies. However, what these usages meant to<br />

Shakespeare this author is unable to say with conviction despite having examined many com<br />

mentaries on this point. What is unmistakable is the dominance of poetic vision in The Tempest,<br />

and the relation of poetic vision to a profound confrontation with temporality, contingency, human<br />

failing, mortality, and reconciliation. At the very least it would seem that Shakespeare explored<br />

the connection between wisdom, courage, temperance, and justice on the one hand; and faith,<br />

hope, and charity on the other. He could not have done this without exploring Christian themes<br />

and ideas. It does not seem<br />

likely Shakespeare could have achieved the profundity he did, in fact,<br />

achieve<br />

by a merely ironic negation of the tradition which rested on the Augustinian meditation on<br />

the intimation of the eternal in the temporal a tradition which itself rested on an affinity for<br />

Plato's complementary account of what human experience must<br />

inevitably involve.


Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice in The Tempest -219<br />

"emblematic narrative",9 that is, it is an imitation of action, or it is a recon<br />

struction of humsn sction from the perspective of the virtue<br />

implicitly possible<br />

in human action but not normally directly seen. It is seeing<br />

human action<br />

from above so to speak. The high characters are ritualized vis-a-vis the low<br />

characters who are reslistic or cynical or simply semiconscious. Thus every<br />

moment of time is the eternal moment snd the tssk is to see that that is so.<br />

Every moment is thus a promise and a peril, for at every<br />

moment the human<br />

agent is caught between merely temporal royslties and virtue's siry voice.<br />

Prospero's vision is s momentsry<br />

unificstion of these themes before time<br />

sweeps sll before it. But on the other hsnd, the plsy<br />

is the remembrance of<br />

a vision and a sign of its repetitive presence in all moments of human en<br />

durance. It is the fleeting glimpse of the unity<br />

of the real snd the ideal<br />

which st the outset of the plsy hsd been hopelessly sepsrsted as the discrepancy<br />

between Milan and Antonio on the one hand, snd the dukedom of the library<br />

on the other.<br />

In this reflective moment in the midst of time none of the reslities of the<br />

humsn condition is denied, but whst is ssserted positively is thst any moment<br />

can be the occasion for a deeper vision<br />

it must be transmitted through the visible and<br />

transitory<br />

what is to be seen never alters but<br />

self-ensctment of agents.<br />

At any rate, Ariel returns now to make the banquet vanish, and he reveals<br />

himself as the minister of Fate demanding of Alonso, Sebsstisn snd Antonio<br />

repentance and from this point on an innocent life. He disappears in a<br />

clap<br />

of thunder. Prospero praises Ariel's work and has reached the height of his<br />

power:<br />

"My high charms work, / And these, mine enemies, sre sll knit up /<br />

In their distractions: they now sre in my<br />

(in. iii. 88-90). In this hypnotic<br />

stste Alonso thinks the clouds, the winds snd the thunder pronounce the nsme of<br />

Prospero. The tempest has now revesled itself ss Fste snd 3 call to remembrance<br />

and hence repentance. Thus, Alonso assumes that the loss of Ferdinand is the<br />

recompense for his allisnce with Antonio sgsinst Prospero. Ferdinsnd is bedded<br />

in the ooze and now Alonso wishes to join him: "I'll seek him deeper than<br />

e'er plummet sounded / And with him there lie<br />

mudded"<br />

(m.iii. 100102).<br />

The confrontation with the ethereal hss driven Alonso towards the insensste<br />

mud.<br />

Now Alonso, Sebsstisn snd Antonio confront their own guilt. This is their<br />

second encounter with the tempest. The first brought them to the island,<br />

the second to self-awareness.<br />

By contrast the first scene of Act IV begins with Prospero, Ferdinand<br />

and Mirands, in s situstion where Prospero is beginning to release Ferdinand<br />

from his thralldom. Ferdinand has been tried and found good. Prospero ad<br />

monishes Ferdinand to be chaste. Ferdinand mskes s stirring speech for honor<br />

snd for "quiet dsys, fsir issue, and long<br />

life"<br />

(iv.i. 24). With a few minor<br />

9. Peterson, op. cit., p. 215.


220 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

lapses of passion Ferdinand and Miranda look to be composed, and now<br />

Ariel will produce the masque.<br />

The masque duly celebrates<br />

fertility and the cooperation of sky<br />

and earth<br />

in the lives of Ferdinand and Miands. Ferdinsnd wishes to think these sre<br />

spirits, but Prospero foreshadows what is to come<br />

by remarking, "Spirits,<br />

which by<br />

mine art / I have from their confines called to enact / My present<br />

fancies"<br />

(iv.i. 120-22). Ferdinand understandably<br />

wishes for time to stand still<br />

now for the fair thing it has revealed. But time will not stand still, for at<br />

the moment of harvest in the wearying August of the mssque, Prospero's fsncy<br />

shifts to Caliban's foul conspiracy (iv.i. 140). In the regime of Prospero the<br />

visions of the island shift with his fancy. This confirms the view that The<br />

Tempest is the story<br />

of the interior drama of the "dream of Prospero". "Prospero<br />

hsd plsyed with the thought of humsn life ss a masque, beautiful, majestic,<br />

transient: but it would not do. It is instesd s bitter drams of good snd evil."10<br />

"In the end the choice is between himself sffirming the spiritusl sources of<br />

society, the dependence of the temporal snd the seculsr upon the eternsl snd<br />

the sscred, snd s<br />

society<br />

which rejects supernstursl ssnctions snd in the event<br />

rejects morality itself."11 The return to human affairs, in short, is not to the<br />

Machiavellian perspective but to a comprehensive view<br />

leading<br />

to moderation:<br />

He ne'er is crowned / With immortality who fears to follow / Where airy<br />

voices lead. Prospero's remembrance of Caliban's conspiracy is, naturally, the<br />

occasion for remembering the general atmosphere of conspiracy Prospero has<br />

inhabited, and, necessarily, in the end, the fact that he himself has conspired<br />

against the conspirators. This memory produces a tempest in Prospero's own<br />

mind now which is evident to Ferdinand. But Prospero dismisses him snd in<br />

reflecting<br />

on Cslibsn recognizes a limit to his imaginative power to transform<br />

the stuff of which human beings are formed. Caliban's is a nature which<br />

Prospero's nurture cannot perfect. Thus, Caliban and his co-conspirators now<br />

creep up on Prospero's dwelling like animals and are driven out by<br />

spirits in<br />

the form of hunting dogs chasing prey.<br />

Now all Prospero's enemies are st his mercy, snd the sixth hour hss been<br />

resched. The king snd his followers hsve become penitent snd this is sufficient<br />

for Prospero. He shall choose virtue over vengeance snd relinquish his msgicsl<br />

powers. The king's party has been reduced to something less than human<br />

under Prospero's spell.<br />

They thus lie foul and muddy, at the ebb tide of their<br />

humanity. As they are gradually<br />

led back into the human condition the flood<br />

of reason overcomes their muddiness. Their humiliation is the prerequisite to<br />

repentance which is the<br />

beginning<br />

not of their degradation but of their ascent<br />

to some semblance of virtue. That there is virtue in Alonso has been strongly<br />

intimated for some time, and this is the case in his first reunion with Prospero.<br />

Gonzalo is of course virtuous. Sebastian and Antonio may be held by some<br />

10. D. G. James, The Dream of Prospero (Oxford, 1967), p. 136.<br />

11. James, op. cit., p. 150.


. .<br />

Possibly<br />

Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice in The Tempest 221<br />

virtue becsuse of Prospero's direst to revesl their abortive conspiracy sgainst<br />

Alonso.<br />

Now Prospero plays on Alonso' s apparent loss of Ferdinand by saying he<br />

hss lost his daughter without<br />

saying that he has lost his daughter to Ferdinand.<br />

This serves to remind Alonso of his separation from his daughter Claribel.<br />

But having<br />

Ferdinand.<br />

had this bitter joke the restored Duke of Milan now produces<br />

The play's conclusion is contained in Gonzalo's reflection that in one voyage<br />

"all of<br />

us"<br />

hsve found "ourselves / When no msn wss his<br />

own"<br />

(v.i. 209-13).<br />

"Prospero trsnsvslues the wickedness snd torment on his isle into the stuff<br />

of dresms. .<br />

the lsst evil for Prospero abides in cynicism, the<br />

Antonio malady. Antonio is, like Iago,<br />

in psrts instesd of by totsl<br />

an antipoetic mind who sees the world<br />

vision."<br />

psrs-<br />

In this dilemms the eternsl is only,<br />

doxicslly, s momentsry<br />

solution within the terms of the human condition. The<br />

incipient lawlessness of<br />

humanity can be subdued "only for a moment in a<br />

scene created<br />

by a consciousness."12<br />

wholly poetic The enacted self is itself a<br />

fugitive; not s generic unity but s drsmstic identity.<br />

There are, however, s number of sdditionsl considerations: it would be<br />

difficult to study The Tempest without remarking its evanescence both in theme<br />

and structure, and most commentators have done so. To this point, the dis<br />

cussion has proceeded in an attempt to be faithful to that quality in the play,<br />

and to be mindful of the centrality<br />

of Prospero's sentiment that the fabric<br />

of his vision is "baseless" (iv.i. 151), that the human condition is an "insub<br />

stantial<br />

pageant"<br />

(iv.i. 155). On the other hand, it must be reaffirmed that<br />

there is a fabric and a pagesnt, snd their reslity<br />

is not constituted in their<br />

msterislity. This certifies the connection between Shskespeare and the ancient<br />

roots of philosophy and theology, and leaves no doubt that Shakespeare pre<br />

sents both a conception of excellence or nobility ss real,<br />

snd slso s forthright<br />

these quslities. Since thst schievement<br />

sccount of the difficulty of schieving<br />

is intuitive snd/or intellectusl, it is s mstter of<br />

seeing snd, in The Tempest,<br />

poetic seeing.<br />

It hss been suggested esrlier thst, within the specific terms of this plsy,<br />

poetic<br />

seeing<br />

is superior to philosophicsl or theological seeing. To the extent<br />

that is so in The Tempest, it is because the srt of seeing<br />

the<br />

"insubstsntisl"<br />

seems to demsnd poetic seeing, snd, if proof were needed, The Tempest<br />

itself is proof, provided one suspends a prejudice against the sheer<br />

possibility<br />

of such seeing. The rank of characters in the play is based on the vision, or<br />

lack of it, which<br />

they possess, and on the degree to which<br />

they can learn,<br />

when given a fresh chsnce, to see whst previously they<br />

hsd not seen. This is,<br />

of course, true in the highest degree of Prospero snd thus is reminiscent of<br />

Duke Vincentio's insight in Measure for Measure.<br />

12. Wylie Sypher, The Ethic of Time, Structures of Experience in Shakespeare (New York,<br />

1976), pp. 205-6.


222 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

On the other hsnd, there is s clesr difference of tone between The Tempest<br />

snd Measure for Measure. Measure for Measure is more esrthbound snd has<br />

a more obvious political<br />

teaching<br />

about the value of domestic or familial<br />

orderliness for the maintenance of political order in a condition of moderate<br />

virtue (between the extremes of the dissolution of the suburbs snd divine<br />

perfection which, on esrth, devolves into mere rules).<br />

Does this mesn thst Shskespesre, in moving, by s long<br />

route not described<br />

here, from Measure for Measure to The Tempest, hss gradually abandoned<br />

solid political<br />

teaching<br />

for a dependence on poetic imsginstion ss a kind of<br />

consolation for the imperfectibility of the mortal, human condition? There is<br />

much evidence to suggest otherwise.<br />

In the first place, the theme of proper marriage is maintained in The Tempest<br />

in a semidivine presentation. Ferdinand and Miranda are united in their vision<br />

of each other and reinforced<br />

by<br />

sky in the msrrisge mssque. But this is done in s wsy<br />

with The Tempest's internsl integrity<br />

the vision of cooperation between earth and<br />

thst remsins consistent<br />

snd themstic cohesion. In the second<br />

plsce, Prospero's descent from power which is repsired by an ascent in wisdom,<br />

snd his eventusl return to his proper post in Milan armed with s more compre<br />

hensive vision, echoes Shskespesre's recurrent theme of suffusing<br />

the humsn<br />

moral order with a larger vision that leads to the moderation that only those<br />

of comprehensive and sober<br />

understanding<br />

can display.<br />

The Tempest may then be seen as Shakespeare's greatest effort to achieve a<br />

philosophical expression of the thought that consistently underlies his teaching<br />

on moral and political life. This play seems to assert that generic unity is<br />

subsumed in dramstic identity. But whst does it mesn to ssy thst? Does it<br />

mesn thst nothing persists? On the contrary, it is quite clesr thst if there is<br />

not<br />

something in the poetic vision thst persists, the emphssis on nobility,<br />

excellence, snd sober judgment could not confront us so clesrly<br />

ss it does.<br />

Rsther, we must<br />

ssy thst no humsn sgent of such poetic seeing persists.<br />

To the extent thst the vision of The Tempest is specificslly Prospero's vision,<br />

or, for thst mstter, specificslly Shskespesre's, it must be "rounded with a<br />

sleep,"<br />

dissolving to "leave not a rack behind" (iv.i.i54ff.). To the extent that<br />

the vision of The Tempest is not<br />

only Prospero's or Shakespeare's, but is<br />

instead at least a mysterious presence in the text itself, it obviously must<br />

persist. However, its presence in the text depends on its continued potential<br />

for being seen by<br />

successive observers.<br />

But this potential depends in some measure on the observers themselves<br />

who will know what<br />

they are being expected to see. Implied, therefore, is a<br />

"practice"<br />

of seeing which can persist but which must be reaffirmed on every<br />

occasion<br />

by those who see, thus<br />

distinguishing<br />

themselves from those who<br />

do not see. In this way The Tempest may be understood as a teaching of<br />

the highest sort, and necessarily reminiscent, in its own idiom, of the experience<br />

of the Platonic presentation of Socrates. To see in this sense is to put into<br />

practice a vision of human conduct but, simultaneously, to avoid the reduction


Temporal Royalties and Virtue's Airy Voice in The Tempest 223<br />

of such vision to a set of rules which, in the temporality of humsn things,<br />

cannot with sny certsinty be of permanent value in guiding<br />

humsn beings<br />

through the vicissitudes of historical existence. It is the vision to which one<br />

subscribes rsther thsn s command which one must obey. There is a fundamental<br />

optimism in this understanding<br />

that what is to be seen can be seen despite<br />

the conspiracy against it, and that it can be resffirmed in every psssing moment.<br />

It is thus s vision which seeks to hold together the moral sutonomy<br />

of humsn<br />

beings in the exercise of their sgency, with the possibility<br />

of s conception<br />

of whst humsn sgency<br />

should le3d to snd look like providing sn elusive, but<br />

resl, stsndard of judgment. It is this which Prospero must csrry bsck to Milsn<br />

snd psss on to Ferdinsnd snd Mirands.<br />

The purity<br />

or<br />

sdmirsbility<br />

of motives will not relesse us from the dsngers<br />

of missdventure in the mutable and uncertain circumstsnces in which we must<br />

try to act on those motives. On the other hsnd, the nsture of our motives,<br />

insofsr ss they msy be revesled to us, undoubtedly sffects our judgment of<br />

the actions thst proceeded under their guidsnce. Prospero's misadventure in<br />

originally relinquishing his political responsibilities is of a different sort from<br />

Antonio's in perverting his political responsibilities.<br />

Furthermore, Prospero's misadventure lesds to s grester, more compre<br />

hensive understsnding<br />

symbolized<br />

by his two renuncistions of power: the first<br />

insdvertent snd the second by<br />

choice under conditions of unlimited power.<br />

Prospero's initisl motives betray limited perception, subject to revision snd<br />

improvement, but not wickedness or mslevolence. Antonio's motives sre wicked<br />

snd, in the event, unimproved snd ambitiousness<br />

csn<br />

unimprovsble.<br />

sppsrently Antonio's<br />

only be magnified or diminished as circumstances dictate. It<br />

cannot be transformed or transposed into a different urging.<br />

Of Caliban, it might be said that his motives are unsettled.<br />

They are some<br />

where between instinct and reflective maturity.<br />

They lack the delibersteness<br />

which would permit us to judge with<br />

certainty how far he might be able to<br />

advsnce. Antonio is unsmbiguous in this sense, snd lower.<br />

The question will, of course, srise ss to whether tslk of the higher snd<br />

the lower, the base and the noble, the admirable and the despicable, the<br />

benevolent and the malicious,<br />

sentiment of the actor<br />

makes sense if self-enactment is the self-chosen<br />

whence comes this sppsrently<br />

independent standsrd<br />

by which to sssess motives? For Shskespesre, it seems to come from an<br />

swareness of the comprehensive range of possible motives for humsn beings<br />

to spprehend and choose smong. The range is real and imposes itself upon us.<br />

It is natural, if by<br />

natural is meant the unsought but unsvoidsble conditions<br />

human experience imposes upon humsn reflection. But it is not only natural.<br />

The range of motives is slso orderly<br />

snd csnnot be expressed otherwise thsn<br />

in terms of better or worse. Thus, we<br />

msy be flooded by msny possible<br />

motives but we are not permitted to be unaware of their implications in a<br />

moral sense.<br />

Finally, it may be remarked that no hierarchy among<br />

the better motives


224 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

is sppsrent. This is true enough. But whst is decisive is the revelstion of<br />

chsrscter in respect, first, of better or worse motives, snd second, of the<br />

srrsngement schieved by<br />

(including<br />

esch well-disposed individusl of the better motives<br />

consideration of the comprehensiveness of the range of motives so<br />

srrsnged). Ususlly, Shskespesre personifies the stsndsrd in s chsrscter who is<br />

both well-disposed snd exhibiting sn extensive array of worthy<br />

orderly manner. The hierarchy<br />

vision in each play.<br />

motives in an<br />

of the virtues thus depends on the dramatic<br />

The relative importance of the various good motives will depend in each<br />

case on the contingent conditions the play imposes on the chsrscters. The<br />

relstive equslity<br />

of the virtues does not prevent a hierarchical arrangement<br />

among them, but does require different arrangements in different cases. The<br />

coherence of the moral order struck in each case is crucial. For, in preserving<br />

coherence among the good things in the midst of life's contingency, one does<br />

not diminish one virtue for the sake of another. On the contrary, one cslls<br />

upon one virtue for the sske of virtue sltogether. Were this not the esse,<br />

contingency would overwhelm virtue. The good msn must hsve the cunning<br />

of virtue if he is to outwit the deceptions of the wicked and remain resilient<br />

to the endlessness of temporality. Surely, The Tempest is about this if it is<br />

about anything.<br />

From this point of view, the "Epilogue" of The Tempest takes on a sig<br />

nificant dimension: Prospero's charms are now overthrown, snd he is reduced<br />

to the fsint strength st the disposal of any human being<br />

in confrontation with<br />

temporality. But if he is not to be "confined" but "Sent to Naples" it will<br />

depend on the audience, that is, it will depend on their appropriation of his<br />

vision to resubstantiate it as his successors. Their gentle breath must fill his<br />

sails or else his project fails. The task of<br />

seeing now falls to them. Of course,<br />

his dramatic task was "to please", and he wishes to be applauded. In addition,<br />

he wishes to persist in the persistence of their pleasure. In the meantime,<br />

the play has taught us something about the rank of pleasures. Thus, while<br />

the audience can see what it wants to see, the play<br />

has provided a precept<br />

for seeing better. To insist thst this is not a political<br />

tesching<br />

would be to<br />

insist thst the dreams of politics are not encompassed<br />

by the dream of life.


goal'<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson<br />

and its Background in Bacon and Hobbes<br />

Jeffrey Barnouw<br />

John Dewey Fellow, ig83~84<br />

When Thomas Jefferson maintained that government is instituted among<br />

men to secure their inaliensble rights, including "preservstion of life, snd<br />

liberty snd the pursuit of happiness,"1 he was stating<br />

conviction widespresd<br />

smong his compstriots, but slso msking<br />

with respect to the inaliensble right to the pursuit of hsppiness<br />

whst he felt to be s<br />

particularly<br />

s complex<br />

snd subtle clsim with fsr-resching implicstions for constitutions! theory. The<br />

series is sn sscending order: self-preservstion is s prerequisite of liberty, snd<br />

liberty, for Jefferson, provides the bssis for all sorts of individual and joint<br />

endeavors.<br />

Following Hume and Montesquieu, Locke and ultimately Hobbes,<br />

he tends to construe political<br />

liberty as individusl security, ss ssfegusrding<br />

pursuits thst sre not themselves politicsl, nor necesssrily<br />

public. If he thus<br />

conceives of liberty in so-cslled negative terms, not as an end in itself but<br />

as making possible other ends, Jefferson also conceives of the 'ultimate<br />

as open-ended,<br />

Jefferson is not ssserting<br />

s pursuit which generates new purposes ss it progresses.<br />

thst legitimste government has an obligstion to<br />

provide for the hsppiness of its citizens. On the contrary, with regsrd to the<br />

constitution of the stste the emphssis is ss much on 'pursuit' ss on 'hsppiness'.<br />

Not only is it not the plsce of the stste to determine whst might constitute<br />

hsppiness or whst should be the psrticulsr gosls for its citizens; the quslity<br />

of endeavor itself represents s vslue both for the individusl snd for the stste.<br />

In securing the pursuit of hsppiness, the stste is mesnt to protect snd encourage<br />

s spirit of enterprise in its people, s sense of venturesome self-relisnce which<br />

is essenti3l to hsppiness. It msy<br />

seem one-sided to mske support of the indi<br />

vidusl'<br />

s spontsneous striving for self- fulfilment the crux of the legitimscy of<br />

the stste, until it is recognized thst the individusl 's urge to enjoy and develop<br />

this natural liberty is in turn crucial to the good of the whole, to maintain<br />

ing<br />

a just government snd constitution.<br />

The tssk of the present essay<br />

is to elucidate the relation of these ideas<br />

in Jefferson's writings against the background of analogous constellations of<br />

ideas in Bacon and Hobbes, who were the first to recognize and promote a<br />

new psychology<br />

of endeavor associated with the emergence of experimental<br />

science in the seventeenth century. Hobbes's own<br />

continuity<br />

with Bacon has<br />

been underestimated and neglected in the secondary literature, ss hss the extent<br />

I. From his "original Rough draught" of the Declaration of Independence, in The Papers of<br />

Thomas Jefferson, ed. Julian P. Boyd (Princeton, I950ff.), I: 423.


226 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

of his sffinities with lesding writers of the later Enlightenment.2 To discern<br />

continuities and sffinities is not the ssme ss tracing<br />

sources or influences.<br />

No sttempt will be msde here to contribute directly to the debste on the<br />

immediste sntecedents of the idess snd expressions of the Declaration of<br />

Independence, but it csn be shown, for example, thst the understsnding of<br />

endesvor in Bscon snd Hobbes is more relevsnt to Jefferson's conception of<br />

the pursuit of hsppiness snd its politicsl rsmificstions thsn the idess elsborsted<br />

by Locke under the hesding 'pursuit of hsppiness.' The lstter in fsct reflect<br />

s distinctly different snd even opposite psychology. Intellectusl history which<br />

proceeds in terms of continuities snd sffinities need not be less rigorous or<br />

less illuminsting<br />

th3n thst which insists on the sttribution of actual influence.<br />

Its cogency<br />

will depend on the depth of<br />

understanding<br />

which it reveals in<br />

interpreting configurations of ideas, whether in an individual writer or a par<br />

ticular period, and on the capacity to ground its correlations between different<br />

writers or disparate ages in this deeper level of coherence.<br />

I. THE PURSUIT OF HAPPINESS<br />

At the beginning, we must see how the pursuit of happiness is relsted, in<br />

Jefferson's thinking, to politicsl order snd<br />

liberty and to the progress that is<br />

bound up<br />

with social enlightenment. In 1786 he wrote to George Wythe that<br />

"no other sure foundation can be devised for the preservation of freedom<br />

and happiness" than "the diffusion of knowledge among the The<br />

people."3<br />

underlying idea is that only the people are a reliable judge of what is in their<br />

interest, and then only when they are well informed. The connection becomes<br />

more complex when enlightenment is taken to mean not<br />

only<br />

the advance of knowledge, and<br />

corresponding<br />

In 1 8 16 Jefferson wrote,<br />

the spread but<br />

change of interests and purposes.<br />

laws and institutions must go hand in hand with the progress of the human mind.<br />

As that becomes more developed, more enlightened, as new discoveries are made,<br />

new truths disclosed, and manners and opinions change with the change of circum<br />

times.4<br />

stances, institutions must advance also, and<br />

keep pace with the<br />

It is significant that this was said not to vindicate the Revolution, the<br />

constitution of a new republic, but to caution the present generation ss well<br />

2. I have followed up several strands<br />

linking Bacon to Hobbes, and Hobbes to various figures<br />

of the Enlightenment, in essays cited in notes 11, 18, 28, 35, 37, 40 and 50-52.<br />

3. August 13, 1786, Papers X: 244f. Cf. to James Madison, December 20, 1787.<br />

4. To Samuel Kercheval, July 12, 1816, in The Writings of Thomas Jefferson, ed. Andrew<br />

A. Lipscomb and Albert Ellery Bergh (Washington, D.C., 1903ft.), XV, 41. Next paragraph:<br />

XV, 40. (Where the appropriate volume of Papers has not yet been published. I will cite Writings.)<br />

Jefferson's letter to John Adams, June 15,<br />

in broader terms.<br />

1813, Writings XIII: 254f., makes the same point


. It<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 227<br />

ss posterity sgsinst venerating the Revolution in the wrong<br />

wsy. "Some men<br />

look st constitutions with ssnctimonious<br />

reverence."<br />

Jefferson remsrks.<br />

They ascribe to the men of the preceding age a wisdom more than human, and<br />

suppose what<br />

they did to be beyond amendment. I knew that age well; I belonged to<br />

it. .<br />

was very like the present, but without the experience of the present; and<br />

forty years of experience in government is worth a century of book-reading.<br />

Forty<br />

alter or to<br />

years esrlier he had written that "it is the right of the people to<br />

abolish"<br />

a form of government that has become destructive of their<br />

inalienable rights "and to institute new government, laying<br />

its foundation on<br />

such principles .<br />

as to them shall seem most<br />

likely to effect their ssfety<br />

and happiness." Reformulating this in 1816, Jefferson adapts the motive of<br />

revolution to support a provision for constitutionsl revision snd renewsl on a<br />

regulsr snd perpetual basis. "Esch generation is ss independent of the one pre<br />

ceding, as that was of sll which had gone before. It has then, like them,<br />

a right to choose for itself the form of government it believes most promotive<br />

of its own happiness."<br />

The Revolution sets a precedent for the government that follows from it.<br />

For Jefferson, at lesst, the founding<br />

of the Republic does not csll for per<br />

petuation in its originsl form, like sn achitectural foundation that can be built<br />

upon but not altered, but rather calls for emulation, that is, for repeated renewal<br />

which reaches deeper than mere sdsptation of the heritage, to measure the form<br />

of the present polity against the prevailing (common) sense of the goals it<br />

was instituted to promote. We will come back to consider the implications of<br />

this conception of a republic as a perpetual founding (not 'permanent revolu<br />

tion'), its introduction of a new understanding<br />

of time into the sphere of<br />

political constitution.<br />

For Jefferson it was<br />

precisely a safeguard, as well as a virtue, of the<br />

new republican form of government that it was responsive to public happiness.<br />

Writing from Paris in his 1786 letter to George Wythe, Jefferson saw kings,<br />

nobles and priests as "an sbsndoned<br />

confederacy<br />

msss of<br />

sgsinst the hsppiness of the<br />

people,"<br />

snd conversely the pursuit of happiness of an informed<br />

people as security agaist the rise of priests, nobles or kings in a republic<br />

or representative democracy. This is Jefferson's point when he tells Wythe,<br />

"Preach .<br />

a crusade against ignorance, establish and improve the law<br />

for educating the common people. Let our Countrymen know that the people<br />

alone can protect us against these<br />

In the preceding<br />

were becoming universally<br />

year he had written to Richard Price that "the people<br />

sensible"<br />

of "the want of power in the federal<br />

head"<br />

as "the flaw in our constitution which might endsnger its<br />

destruction,"<br />

snd thst sccordingly "s spirit to enlsrge the powers of Congress wss becoming<br />

general."<br />

In this response he recognizes an essentisl trait of republicanism,<br />

The happiness of governments like ours, wherein the poeple are truly the mainspring,<br />

is that they are never to be despaired of. When an evil becomes so glaring as to


'entail'<br />

228 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

strike them generally, they arouse themselves, and it is redressed. He only is then the<br />

popular man and can get into office who shows the best disposition to reform the<br />

evil. This truth was obvious on several occasions<br />

during the late war, and this char<br />

acter in our governments saved us. Calamity<br />

was our best physician.<br />

s<br />

The letters we have drawn on so far present a variety of contexts, yet<br />

a coherent outline of the relations between public happiness, as the people's<br />

own concern, and the progressivity and stability<br />

of republican government<br />

has begun to emerge. The capacity to recognize and respond to negative<br />

situations,<br />

with popular welfare and approval as criterion and touchstone, and<br />

to change accordingly, is what "promises<br />

permsnence"<br />

for s republic. The ides<br />

thst each generation is or should be its own focus, that the esrth (to use<br />

Jefferson's expression) "belongs to the living," is precisely, snd not st sll<br />

parsdoxicslly, the bssis of the continuity snd enduring<br />

strength of the polity.<br />

is introduced into politicsl thought with the<br />

A new conception of<br />

history<br />

ides thst esch generation should consider itself independent of the preceding<br />

snd "all which had gone before." One critic has seen this functional<br />

selfcenteredness<br />

as necessarily leading<br />

'rights'<br />

a concern for<br />

concern not to<br />

to a lsck of concern for the needs snd<br />

of posterity, but I think, on the contrary, that it brings with it both<br />

'our'<br />

such ss the nstionsl debt, on future<br />

posterity (however broadly we construe 'our')<br />

and the<br />

opinions and institutions and<br />

constraining situations,<br />

generations.6<br />

Jefferson in fsct offers a rationsle for concern with the rights of posterity,<br />

the obligstion not to foreclose their possibilities, which is bssed not in s<br />

responsibility entsiled in the heritsge, but precisely<br />

in the ides thst the fruits<br />

of the esrth<br />

belong to the living. It is in s letter to Msdison from Psris,<br />

September 6, 1789, thst he takes up "the question, whether one generation<br />

of men has a right to bind<br />

another."<br />

Again the context of French politics,<br />

now very different, is an importsnt influence; the preceding<br />

month hsd seen<br />

5.<br />

February 1, 1785, Papers VII; 631.<br />

6. In Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence (New York, 1978), Garry<br />

purposes<br />

Wills goes overboard in his eagerness to debunk the<br />

"pulse-quickening for which<br />

"modem liberals" quote 'the earth belongs to the living,'<br />

By making each generation live only for itself, Jefferson would not only inhibit the entailing<br />

of one's posterity, but the enhancing of its life. He would teach men not only to live quit<br />

of any claim from the dead, but quit of the<br />

unborns'<br />

claims as well since only the living<br />

should enjoy earth's usufructs, (p. 127)<br />

Wills even suggests it would be consonant with Jefferson's idea if one generation were to "acquire<br />

the means for its own enjoyment<br />

by aliening the land itself sell it off and leave none of it to<br />

native posterity, or use up the land by short-sighted management, returning quick<br />

profits."<br />

Jefferson,<br />

on the contrary, counted on the interest in posterity<br />

as part of the self-interest of the living,<br />

as when he writes to the Marquis de Lafayette, April 11, 1787, criticizing the short leases on<br />

land in France, in contrast to England where<br />

long leases, linking the generations, "render the<br />

highly."<br />

farms there almost hereditary, [and] make it worth the farmers while to manure the lands<br />

Papers XI: 284.


usufruct'<br />

Enlightenment,'<br />

society."<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 229<br />

the decrees sbolishing<br />

'feudal'<br />

privileges. The immediate implication of his<br />

principle seems to be the very opposite of what Garry Wills inferred. "I<br />

set out on this ground, which I suppose to be self-evident, that the earth<br />

belongs in usufruct to the living; that the dead have neither powers nor rights<br />

over it. The portion occupied<br />

by any individusl cesses to be his when himself<br />

cesses to be,<br />

property<br />

snd reverts to the<br />

Jefferson srgues that a man inherits<br />

not by natural right, but by a law of the society of which he is a member, and to<br />

which he is subject. Then, no man can, by natural right, oblige the lands he occu<br />

pied or the persons who succeed him in that occupation, to the payment of debts<br />

contracted<br />

by him. For if he could, he might<br />

during his own life, eat up the usu<br />

fruct of the lands for several generations to come; and then the lands would<br />

belong<br />

to the dead, and not the living.7<br />

The principle that the earth belongs to the living and the qualification<br />

living'<br />

'in only brings out what is implied in the emphasis on 'the<br />

is connected with Jefferson's view that property is not s nstursl right but one<br />

which is estsblished<br />

by snd subject to the civil power. This view of property<br />

is in turn closely<br />

linked to the conception of the pursuit of hsppiness ss s<br />

nstursl right. In 1785 Jefferson hsd written,<br />

Whenever there is in any country, uncultivated lands and unemployed poor, it is<br />

clear that the laws of property have been so far extended as to violate natural right.<br />

The earth is given as a common stock for man to labour & live on. If for the encour<br />

agement of<br />

industry we allow it to be appropriated, we must take care that other<br />

employment be provided to those excluded from the appropriation. If we do not,<br />

the fundamental right to labour the earth returns to the unemployed."<br />

in<br />

Whether or not Jefferson's original reference to the pursuit of happiness<br />

1776 was influenced by the idea of effecting<br />

a correction of the con<br />

ventional (Lockean) triad 'life, liberty and<br />

that by 1789<br />

property,'<br />

it seems<br />

highly probable<br />

Jefferson saw the pursuit of hsppiness as an inalienable right<br />

which is incompatible with a natural right to property or inheritance,<br />

and that<br />

this conflict was sddressed in his principle 'the esrth beongs to the living.'<br />

When Jefferson pencilled in suggested emendstions of Lsfsyette's draft for s<br />

'Declsrstion of the rights of msn and<br />

citizen,'<br />

early in 1789, he bracketed<br />

two of the phrases put forward under the 'essential rights of msn': "le soin<br />

7. Papers XV: 392-93. Wills does not recognize the connection between the idea that the<br />

earth belongs to the living and the idea that property is not a natural but a civil right. In a<br />

different context, p. 231, he refers to the latter idea as setting Jefferson apart from Locke and<br />

linking him with Hutcheson, a correlation that has been challenged, in this regard and in general,<br />

in a trenchant critique of<br />

Inventing America by Ronald Hamowy, "Jefferson and the Scottish<br />

William and<br />

Mary Quarterly'^, no. 4 (October 1979): 503-23. If neither Locke<br />

nor Hutcheson saw property rights as civil in origin, Hobbes did.<br />

8. To the Reverend James Madison, (the statesman's cousin and President of the College of<br />

William and Mary,) October 28, 1785, Papers VIII: 682.


230 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

de son honneur" snd "le droit de<br />

bonheur."9<br />

lstter be replsced by "Is recherche du<br />

propriete"<br />

snd sppsrently<br />

suggested thst the<br />

The stability<br />

and<br />

continuity<br />

of the republic are thus seen to depend on esch<br />

generation and each individual being<br />

'self-centered'<br />

in and through the pursuit<br />

of happiness. This configuration of ideas in Jefferson's writings in effect intro<br />

duced a new conception of historical time into political thought, as will be<br />

argued below, but it is a conception (based on analogous configurations) that<br />

hsd slresdy<br />

proved its worth in other spheres of culture in the Scientific<br />

Revolution snd the Enlightenment. This characteristic interrelation of pursuit,<br />

progress and posterity<br />

clearly in the work of Francis Bacon.<br />

as dimensions of historical time can be delineated most<br />

ever<br />

Jefferson regarded Bacon as one "of the three greatest men the world has<br />

yet little has been written on what he might owe to Bacon.10<br />

Beyond any strictly identifisble debt in scientific mstters or methodology, I<br />

believe Jefferson msy hsve derived from his resding<br />

of Bscon s bssic theme<br />

of his political thought. Such s connection, lacking<br />

explicit testimony, is<br />

incspsble of proof, but what is important is the breadth and depth of the<br />

analogy, that is, its systematic character and psychological grounding.<br />

9. The Letters of Lafayette and Jefferson, ed. Gilbert Chinard (Baltimore, 1929). pp. 80-82;<br />

Chinard, Thomas Jefferson, The Apostle of Americanism (Ann Arbor, 1957), pp. 232-34. and<br />

Adrienne Koch, Jefferson and Madison: The Great Collaboration (New York, 1964). pp. 80-81.<br />

Chinard claims that Jefferson was also responsible for the insertion of an additional reason, beyond<br />

abuses that might arise and the need to keep abreast of the "progres des lumieres," for revising<br />

human institutions: "le droit des generations qui se<br />

succedent,"<br />

the right of succeeding generations.<br />

In her discussion of 'the earth belongs to the living,' pp. 62-96, Koch resists the tendency to<br />

oppose 'the pursuit of happiness' to a natural right of property, citing the letter to Madison quoted<br />

in note 8. This issue is also addressed in chapter 3 of William B. Scott, In Pursuit of Happiness:<br />

American Conceptions of Property from the Seventeenth to the Twentieth Century (Bloomington,<br />

1977). Scott writes, p. 42, "it is tempting to conclude, but impossible to prove, that in 1776<br />

Jefferson sensed the disparity between certain contemporary forms of private property and Locke's<br />

idealized 'natural<br />

property'<br />

and that in an effort to restore the old moral content to the concept<br />

of individual property, Jefferson substituted in its stead the more suggestive phrase 'pursuit of<br />

Happiness.'"<br />

This is fair enough as far as it goes, but Locke's idealization was linked from<br />

the beginning with an interest in safeguarding established property<br />

relations. The Jeffersonian<br />

natural right to a pursuit of happiness would<br />

keep sovereign power at a distance in a very<br />

different direction. Hamowy, (see preceding note 7) p. 519<br />

and n. 62. made this point at just<br />

the time the present paper was first delivered, in slightly different form but with this same<br />

emphasis, at the plenary session of a conference on 'The Pan-Atlantic Enlightenment' sponsored<br />

by the East-Central region of the American Society for Eighteenth-Century<br />

of Early American History and Culture, November 8-10, 1979, at Williamsburg, Virginia.<br />

Studies and the Institute<br />

10. To Benjamin Rush, January 16, 181 1, Writings XIII: 4. Cf. to Walter Jones, January<br />

2, 1814, Writings XIV: 48. Douglass Adair explores one aspect of the deeper resonance of<br />

Bacon's ideas and attitudes in Jefferson, in his essay, "Fame and the<br />

founding<br />

Fathers,"<br />

reprinted<br />

in Fame and the Founding h others (New York, 1974), pp. 3-26. esp. 16-20. The only sub<br />

stantive reference to Baconian method that I have been able to find is in "Report on the Methods<br />

for Obtaining Fresh Water from Salt,' The Complete Jefferson, ed. Saul K. Padovcr (New York,<br />

1943), P- 970.


The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 231<br />

Bacon conceived of science ss a<br />

disciplining<br />

of the mind through deliberate<br />

experience. He was thus opposed both to a nsive psssive mode of experience<br />

snd to reliance on teachers, tradition and particularly<br />

classical philosophy.<br />

According to Bacon, Plato and Aristotle presented (their) science as a closed<br />

and completed whole, exploiting and reinforcing<br />

the predisposition of the<br />

mind, which is evident in common induction or experience in its passive<br />

mode, to ignore "negative instances,' that is, experiences that do not fit its<br />

expectations, and<br />

thereby to preserve the vsin pretense to a knowledge without<br />

gaps or loose ends.<br />

Science, to Bacon, therefore involves overcoming a conservatism (and pride)<br />

native to msn's mind. The nstursl concern for continuity and closure of ex<br />

perience must be countered and mediated<br />

by curiosity, innovation and attention<br />

to the faults and limits of current knowledge. (It is in an analogous sense<br />

that sccident or even cslsmity csn be s tescher.) Experience ss initistive snd<br />

enterprise is the foundstion of science, for Bscon, because it throws into relief<br />

hand'<br />

the active contact with<br />

reality that is 'first one's<br />

own experience.<br />

Only<br />

this pervssive, if implicit, recourse to 'personsl' experience and the individual<br />

responsibility for knowledge assures a real continuity in science, that is, an<br />

advancement which is at the same time a form of tradition or<br />

handing on.<br />

Bacon criticized the presentstion of (supposed) science in finished form<br />

becsuse this seemed to him cslculated to induce awe, belief snd resssurance,<br />

rather than to stimulate "expectant inquiry." He attscked the misdirected venerstion<br />

of the schievements of the sncients and the related assumption that these<br />

could not be surpassed or improved, because such attitudes "tend wholly to<br />

the unfair circumscription of human power, and to s deliberate snd fsctitious<br />

despsir, which not only disturbs the suguries of hope, but also cuts the sinews<br />

the chances of experience<br />

itself.""<br />

and spur of industry, and throws away<br />

prog-<br />

One of the general signs which Bacon took as justifying hope is the<br />

ressivitv of science, which he saw prefigured in the cumulative advance of<br />

the mechanical arts. He contrasted this with the continual vicissitudes in the<br />

history of that sort of philosophy which, instead of fruits and works, seeks<br />

conviction and produces contention.<br />

All the tradition and succession of schools is still a succession of masters and scholars<br />

[disciples], not of inventors and those who bring to further perfection the things<br />

invented. In the mechanical arts we do not find it so: they, on the contrary, as<br />

having<br />

in them some breath of life, are continually growing and perfect.12<br />

becoming more<br />

II. Novum Organum. Book I. Aphorism 88, as translated in The Works of Francis Bacon,<br />

ed. Spedding, Ellis, and Heath (London, i857ff.), IV: 86. For fuller treatment of the themes<br />

of this and the following paragraphs, see my essays, "Active Experience vs. Wish-Fulfilment<br />

Science,"<br />

in Francis Bacon's Moral Psychology of The Philosophical Forum 9 (1979): 78-99,<br />

and "Bacon and Hobbes: The Conception of Experience in the Scientific Revolution," Science/<br />

Technology & the Humanities 2 (1979): 92-1 10- which are extended in the articles cited below,<br />

note 28.<br />

12. From the Preface to Instauratio Magna, as translated in Works IV: 14.


opinion'<br />

232 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

This progressivity, like utility itself, is an indication for Bacon that the knowl<br />

edge involved is rooted in reality. "Knowledge which is founded in nature<br />

has, like living waters, perpetual uprushings and outflowings, while knowledge<br />

based on opinion can, of course, vary but never increase."13 A tradition based<br />

on authority<br />

never rises higher than its original founder.<br />

The self-corrective and cumulative chsrscter of trades snd crafts is grounded<br />

in the continual recourse of these arts to practice ss 'proof in the sense of<br />

testing. The relstion of one thinker or generation and the next is mediated<br />

by s primsry involvement in practice, the individual engagement with particular<br />

problems. In this sense Bacon distinguished two types of<br />

continuity "touching<br />

the tradition [or handing on] of knowledge, the one Critical, the other Pedantical.<br />

For all knowledge is either delivered by teachers, or attained by men's<br />

proper endeavours."14<br />

A critical tradition, of which the mechanical arts and Baconian science<br />

are examples, and Jeffersonian republicanism perhaps another, depends for its<br />

continuity on the repeated initiative of individuals who bring their heritage<br />

to the test of their own experience. It stands in marked contrast to the passive<br />

sort of tradition in which, as Bacon said, followers make a 'leader of<br />

great, like ciphers<br />

coming after an integer, in that "they have never given a<br />

valid assent to the general opinion, for this results from an act of independent<br />

judgment."15<br />

This broad analogy<br />

of Baconian and Jeffersonian ideas, which may or may<br />

not be a reflection of direct influence, will<br />

help to underline a crucial point<br />

about the role of the 'pursuit of happiness' in Jefferson's idea of a republic.<br />

It is not that government should be directly<br />

concerned with the happiness of<br />

the people (a characteristic assumption of 'benevolent' absolutism), but rather<br />

that it should be responsive to, and indeed rely on, their concern, their pursuit.<br />

The determinstion of whst thst happiness is to include is precisely psrt of the<br />

people's own concern, snd in Jefferson's words from the Declsrstion there is<br />

sn emphssis not so much on " . to<br />

effect their ssfety<br />

ss on the preceding phrase, "ss to them shall seem most likely to<br />

snd<br />

hsppiness,"<br />

The constitutive reference of the American polity to the pursuit of happiness<br />

of each present generation, which can of course include their care for the<br />

welfare of their posterity, represents a fundamental acknowledgement of the<br />

possible positive value of the qualitative changes and emergent realities which<br />

time brings. The American conception of a republic marks a radical break<br />

with classicsl republicanism in a number of respects, one of the most drsmstic<br />

13. From Redargutio philosophiarum . not translated in Works, but as "The Refutation of<br />

Philosophies'<br />

in The Philosophy of Francis Bacon, ed. Benjamin Farrington (Chicago, 1966),<br />

p. 127.<br />

14. From The Advancement of Learning, Works III: 413.<br />

15. From Cogitata et Visa, as translated in Philosophy of Francis Bacon, p. 95.


'private'<br />

. . that<br />

government'<br />

being<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 233<br />

chance.<br />

the reversal of the attitude toward time as the medium of change and<br />

J. G. A. Pocock has argued thst for clsssical republicanism time meant<br />

only instability<br />

the universality<br />

and decay. "In the Polybisn 'mixed<br />

of the Aristotelisn<br />

we recognize<br />

polis,"<br />

he claims. "We recognize also that<br />

the aim of politics is to escape from time; that time is the dimension of<br />

imperfection and that change must necessarily be degenerative." This entails a<br />

strict opposition between 'virtue'<br />

and 'commerce'.<br />

in the classical republican and stoic sense<br />

The doctrine that the integrity of the polity must be founded on the integrity<br />

of the<br />

personality, and that the latter could be maintained only through devotion to univer<br />

sal, not particular goods, had committed both ethical and political<br />

theory<br />

to a static<br />

ideal. The concept of the citizen or patriot was antithetical to that of economic man,<br />

his culture in a temporal process: it<br />

multiplying his satisfactions and transforming<br />

encouraged the idea .<br />

only a Spartan rigidity of institutions could enable men<br />

to master the politics of time."'<br />

Instead of recognizing the fundamental break which American independence<br />

meant ss s revolution of the republicsn idesl, Pocock insists on an historical<br />

continuity<br />

of the classical<br />

'paradigm'<br />

broke and 'the Country<br />

whst he cslls " Jeffersonisn<br />

through Machiavelli, Harrington, Boling<br />

party'<br />

to the Americsn revolutionsries, psrticulsrly<br />

mythology."17<br />

This last link is based in the alleged<br />

opposition of agricultural and commercial wsys of life, and overlooks the<br />

intimate interdependence of the two, which Jefferson not only<br />

sought to further.<br />

perceived but<br />

I have criticized Pocock's construction of the supposed historical continuity<br />

of republicanism, the illusion of a persistence of the paradigm of republican<br />

virtue, at length<br />

elsewhere.18<br />

The clsssicsl model sketched by<br />

Pocock is of<br />

interest here in thst its incompstibility with the 'pursuit of happiness' suggests<br />

how fundamentslly idess of the stste must hsve been sffected by the new<br />

significsnce snd dignity sssumed by individual interest and initiative, both in<br />

the<br />

socioeconomic sphere and in political participation. The Revolu<br />

tion in America presupposed and sought to reinforce the consonsnce of privste<br />

pursuits snd public good, ss exemplified by Jefferson's consistent<br />

championing<br />

of the rights of commerce. His spprecistion of the rewsrds of commerce ss s<br />

16. "Civic Humanism and Its Role in Anglo-American Thought," in J. G. A. Pocock, Politics,<br />

Language and Time (New York, 1971), pp. 88, 90.<br />

17. For "Jeffersonian<br />

mythology"<br />

see Pocock, pp. 97L Such misconceptions are cleared up,<br />

and the relations between agriculture and commerce approached on a sound basis, in Joyce<br />

Appleby, "Commercial Farming and the 'Agrarian Myth' Republic,"<br />

in the Early<br />

Journal of<br />

American History 68, no. 4 (March 1982), and "What is still American in the Political Philosophy<br />

of Thomas<br />

Jefferson?"<br />

William and<br />

Mary Quarterly 39, no. 2 (April 1982).<br />

18. "American Independence: Revolution of the Republican Ideal," in The American Revolu<br />

tion and Eighteenth-Century Culture, ed. Paul J. Korshin (New York, <strong>1983</strong>).


mind"<br />

. Remote<br />

mainspring,"<br />

234 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

way of life must be seen as contributing<br />

happiness.<br />

to his conception of the pursuit of<br />

If the American Revolution, as I believe, introduced s new conception of<br />

the polity into history, it wss in psrt because, like Bsconisn science, it broke<br />

through a traditional orientation of experience to the past. A new sense of the<br />

reality of possibility gave experience an active relation to an essentially open<br />

future. Bacon had written, "Men's anticipations of the new are fashioned on<br />

the model of the old. The old governs their imagination. Yet this is a com<br />

pletely fallacious pattern of thought."19 We can illustrate the relation between<br />

the 'new<br />

science'<br />

of the seventeenth century snd this new sense of possibility,<br />

thst is, the reorientstion of experience to the future, by pursuing s further<br />

elsborstion of Bscon's thought in Hobbes.<br />

Hobbes distinguishes two principsl modes of experience or thinking. Pru<br />

dence, the mode of prscticsl thought sppropriste to the clsssicsl conception<br />

of the politicsl sphere, which is tsken by Hobbes ss the model of passive<br />

from given appearances or effects to their<br />

experience, depends on<br />

inferring<br />

possible, that is, conjectured,<br />

causes. Based on the recall of previous associa<br />

tions of events, such experience is essentially past-oriented in its approach<br />

to the future. "The other [mode of thinking] is, when<br />

imagining anything<br />

whatsoever, we seek all the possible effects, that can<br />

by it be produced; that<br />

is to say, we imagine what we can do with it,<br />

when we have<br />

it."20<br />

Hobbes's immediate point is that inference from a cause thst is in our<br />

power to s possible, thst is, reslizsble, effect is necesssry knowledge, or science,<br />

in s way<br />

that inference from effect to possible cause csnnot be. But Hobbes's<br />

underlying insight links the capacity<br />

for science not so much with the urge<br />

to practical control (which is as true of prudence, shared by animsls), but<br />

rsther with msn's<br />

distinguishing trait of curiosity. All thinking<br />

or regulsted<br />

"discourse of the for Hobbes "is nothing but Seeking, or the fsculty<br />

of Invention." In the reorientstion of experience from psssive to sctive thst<br />

is connected with the Scientific Revolution, this seeking<br />

open future thst is no longer supposed to conform<br />

"required'<br />

to conform<br />

to the terms of the psst.<br />

is directed to sn<br />

expected snd<br />

instinctively<br />

Such sn openness to possibility, to whst csn be schieved<br />

by imsginstion<br />

snd endesvor, shows Jefferson to ssy to Price, with regsrd to government<br />

"wherein the people are truly the<br />

"our motto is truly<br />

'nil desperandum'<br />

"21<br />

As he wrote in a letter two years later, "It is part of the American<br />

character to consider nothing ss desperate; to surmount every difficulty by<br />

resolution and contrivance. .<br />

from sll other sid, we sre obliged<br />

to invent snd to execute; to find mesns within ourselves."22<br />

19. The Philosophy of Francis Bacon, p. 96.<br />

20. Leviathan, ch. 3. ed. Macpherson (Baltimore, 1968), p. 96.<br />

Spelling modernized.<br />

21.<br />

February 1, 1785, Papers VII: 631.<br />

22. To Martha Jefferson, March 28, 1787, Papers XI: 251.


'sdvsncement'<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 235<br />

The 'progressive' nsture of republican government in the new sense thus<br />

corresponded to s striving, resourceful chsrscter in the Americsn people. Hope<br />

snd curiosity, imsginstion snd initistive, resourcefulness snd resolution: these<br />

sre universsl humsn chsrscteristics. But within s psrticular historical psy<br />

chological constellation<br />

they can take on a new quality and role. Human<br />

nature is, to a considerable degree, historical in its constitution snd influenced<br />

by ideas, including ideas about human nature. We have examined the role of<br />

the 'pursuit of happiness' in Jefferson's political<br />

thinking and traced its ho<br />

mology with the desire for real knowledge in Bscon's conception of science<br />

snd its sdvsncement.<br />

The integration of the pursuit of hsppiness into the psychological as well<br />

as legal foundation of the modern state goes back, not to Bacon, however,<br />

but to Hobbes. It was Hobbes who first conceived of the state as<br />

guaranteeing<br />

the pursuit of happiness as a 'natural' or 'inalienable right,' and who first saw<br />

the state as relying for its stability and legitimacy<br />

on a spirit in its citizens<br />

which was rooted in the pursuit of happiness. To appreciate fully Hobbes's<br />

undeniable but indirect and scarcely acknowledged contribution to the Americsn,<br />

and psrticulsrly the Jeffersonisn, conception of republicsn government, we<br />

must follow both the legsl snd the psychologicsl strands of foundstion: the<br />

constitutionsl status of the pursuit of hsppiness ss s right, snd the trait of<br />

mind thst gives<br />

reslity to the pursuit snd mskes possible its role in msintsining<br />

s stsble polity.<br />

To understsnd the connection between the two strands, we must begin with<br />

Hobbes's conception of humsn nsture, which, like Bacon's, was both an<br />

snslysis snd, in the sspect of interest here, sn idesl projection. As in his<br />

critique of past-oriented prudential experience and the nstursl predisposition<br />

of the mind that is reflected in thst mode of experience, here too, in his<br />

elsboration of the active, initiative propensity<br />

of human nature, Hobbes could<br />

find resources for his conception in Bacon.<br />

II. THE HAPPINESS OF PURSUIT<br />

In The Advancement of Learning, Bacon is concerned not with<br />

only<br />

moti<br />

vating science, but with<br />

understanding<br />

motivation snd the psychologicsl bssis<br />

in humsn sctivity<br />

generally. In snticipstion of the contrast<br />

of<br />

between Pedsnticsl snd Critical types of tradition with particular reference<br />

to "the progression of knowledge," he writes, "since the labour and life of<br />

one man cannot attain to perfection of knowledge, the wisdom of tradition<br />

is that which inspireth the felicity<br />

sort of tradition or<br />

handing<br />

ss a thresd to be spun<br />

proceeding."23<br />

of continuance snd The wiser<br />

on of knowledge ensures that it "is delivered<br />

on,"<br />

thst insight snd motivstion sre conveyed ss well.<br />

23. Works III: 43-


enjoying."<br />

236 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

One might expect thst in this context Bscon would refer either to a self<br />

less concern for posterity, or the higher egotism of that regard for posterity<br />

known as fame, but he is content here to concentrate on the method of delivery.<br />

For insight into the "felicity<br />

of continuance and<br />

proceedin<br />

from the point<br />

of view of the individual, we must turn to the conception of 'plessure in<br />

proceeding'<br />

which Bscon develops in his 'Georgics of the Mind,' which serve<br />

"to instruct snd suborn sction snd sctive life." There Bscon srgues for s<br />

"priority of the Active Good" which he ssys is "much upheld<br />

by the con<br />

sideration of our estste to be mortsl snd exposed to fortune." Moreover,<br />

he sdds,<br />

The pre-eminence likewise of this Active Good is upheld<br />

by the affection which is<br />

natural in man towards variety<br />

and proceeding; But<br />

in enterprises, pursuits,<br />

and purposes of life, there is much variety; whereof men are sensible with pleasure in<br />

their inceptions, progressions, recoils, reintegrations, approaches, and attainings to<br />

their ends.24<br />

In Eden before the Fall, work had been only "for exercise and experiment,<br />

hss sur<br />

use,"<br />

and not matter of labour for the and this self-sustsining quslity<br />

vived st lesst with respect to intellectusl effort:<br />

"Only lesrned men love business<br />

as an action<br />

according to nature, taking pleasure in the action itself,<br />

purchase."<br />

and not in the<br />

Intellectual pursuits provide the model for 'plessure<br />

in<br />

proceeding,'<br />

in which sppetite is itself enjoysble snd satisfaction leads to<br />

new desire: "Of knowledge there is no satiety, but satisfsction snd sppetite<br />

sre<br />

perpetuslly interchsngesble."25<br />

Bscon spplies this model, however, to humsn desire generally. It is this<br />

chsrscter of life which he seeks to vindicste, in his practicsl ethics or 'Georgics<br />

of the Mind,' by countering snd redirecting<br />

bssic tendencies of stoicism.<br />

Bscon pits s rsther stoic Socrates sgsinst s Sophist in debste, "Socrates placing<br />

felicity in an equal and constant peace of mind, and the Sophist in much<br />

desiring<br />

and much<br />

After weighing both sides, Bacon supports the<br />

Sophist to the effect thst 'to sbstsin from the use of s<br />

thing thst you msy<br />

not feel s want of it; to shun the want that you may not fear the loss of it;<br />

are the precautions of pusillanimity<br />

and<br />

cowardice.'26<br />

Bacon's crucial departure from stoicism can be seen in his conception of<br />

how to learn from experience, to which he ironically<br />

assimilates the stoic<br />

idea of 'suffering' by an adroit reversal of its intention. For a stoic, 'suf<br />

fering'<br />

means undergoing and enduring external necessitation, but with an inner<br />

superiority and indifference to it. Bacon speaks rather of "a wise and industrious<br />

suffering, which draweth and contriveth use and sdvantage out of that which<br />

seemeth adverse and<br />

complements the undertaking<br />

contrary."<br />

In effect this is the sort of undergoing which<br />

or initiative aspect in that form of experience<br />

24. Works III: 424!'.<br />

25. From Advancement, Book I, Works III: 296, 272, 317.<br />

26. From Advancement, Book II, Works III: 427.


proceeding.'<br />

wsy."<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 237<br />

which leads to science, since the advantage which industrious suffering draws<br />

from adverse experience depends on "the exsct snd distinct knowledge of the<br />

precedent stste or disposition."27<br />

It is this undergoing thst is implied in the fsmous Bsconisn msxim: "Nsture<br />

to be commsnded must be<br />

obeyed,"<br />

which is the bssis of his clsim that "human<br />

knowledge and human power meet in one; for where the cause is not known<br />

the effect cannot be produced .<br />

and that which in contemplation is as the<br />

This correlation of cause-and-effect with<br />

cause is in operation as the rule."28<br />

means-and-end provides the starting point for Hobbes's conception of science<br />

as knowledge of effect<br />

by way of knowledge of cause or production, which I<br />

have shown to be related to a new sense of possibility snd future-orientstion<br />

of experience. The bssis of thst relstion is to be found in Hobbes's elaboration<br />

of Bscon's germinal idea of 'pleasure in<br />

In Hobbes this ides is expsnded and deepened in an empirical psychology<br />

that is centered in the conception of conatus or 'endeavor' . Here the natural<br />

integration of<br />

feeling and motive, of plessure snd appetite, which is basic to<br />

Hobbes's account of sensstion snd<br />

thinking ss well ss willing, is snslyzed<br />

with insight. Instesd of<br />

sttempting to desl with the subtleties snd difficulties<br />

of Hobbes's grasp<br />

of mentsl processes here,29 we csn content ourselves with<br />

one passage which reflects the positive interdependence of pleasure and active<br />

desire or pursuit, not at the subliminal level of conatus (that is, infinitesimal<br />

impulses to act which Hobbes conceives of as competing and combining as<br />

motives develop) but at the level of conscious striving.<br />

In chapter II of Leviathan, Hobbes focuses on "the difference of Manners,"<br />

Pesce,"<br />

"those qualities of man-kind thst concern their living together in<br />

To which end we are to consider, that the Felicity of this life, consisteth not in the<br />

repose of a mind satisfied. For there is no such Finis ultimus, (utmost aim,) nor<br />

Summum Bonum, (greatest Good,) as is spoken of in the Books of the old Moral<br />

Philosophers. Nor can a man any more live, whose Desires are at an end, than he,<br />

whose Senses and Imaginations are at a stand. Felicity is continual progress of the<br />

desire, from one object to another; the attaining<br />

later.30<br />

way to the<br />

of the former, being<br />

still but the<br />

For Hobbes this predisposition of human nature leads to a fundamental<br />

premise for the establishment of political order: "And therefore the voluntary<br />

actions, and inclinations of all men, tend, not only to the procuring, but slso<br />

to the sssuring of s contented life; snd differ only in the<br />

It may be surprising to have Hobbes's notorious phrase, "I put for a general<br />

27. Works III: 434-<br />

28. Novum Organum, Book I, Aphorism 3, Works IV: 47.<br />

29. See my essays, "Hobbes's Causal Account of Sensation," Journal of the History of<br />

Philosophy 18 (1980): 1 15-130, and "Vico and the Continuity of Science: The Relation of his<br />

Epistemology to Bacon and Hobbes," Isis 71 (1980): 609-20.<br />

30. Leviathan, p. 160.<br />

Spelling modernized here and in subsequent quotations from this work.


power,"<br />

238 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

inclination of all mankind,<br />

a perpetual and restless desire of Power after<br />

offered as a gloss on 'the pursuit of hsppiness.' This is in psrt because a<br />

sinister construction has been put on Hobbes's use of the term 'power' as if it<br />

meant coercive power over others, where his meaning is mainly psychological<br />

and concerns sn expansive 'sense of self.'31<br />

The general meaning<br />

of<br />

'power'<br />

in Hobbes, which holds in this context, is "present means, to obtain some<br />

future apparent Good."32 The desire of "Power after<br />

power,"<br />

as predicated of<br />

msn in general, reflects the desire to assure "the way<br />

of his future desire"<br />

and thus leads quite nsturslly<br />

which can<br />

keep all individuals in awe and order,<br />

to general consent in a common coercive power<br />

as part of its basic function<br />

as a power for securing<br />

present and future good for those individuals.<br />

If we can understand how the open-ended character of human desire is<br />

related to the foundation of the state for Hobbes, we should gain further in<br />

sight into the pursuit of hsppiness snd the hsppiness of pursuit thst sre pre<br />

supposed<br />

by Jefferson in the Declaration of Independence. Civil pesce for<br />

Hobbes is the precondition of all meaningful human pursuits, and even the<br />

attaining and keeping of pesce is conceived by<br />

him in terms of endesvor. (Compsre<br />

Jefferson's "Peace is my passion.") The constituting of a common coercive<br />

power or sovereignty releases individuals from the state of nature, that is,<br />

from the constant expectation of conflict, in that it makes it safe and thus<br />

rational to follow what he cslls "the first, snd Fundsmentsl Lsw of Nsture;<br />

which is, to seek Peace, and follow it.""<br />

In Hobbes's definition, "A Lsw of Nsture, (Lex Naturalis,) is s Precept,<br />

or general Rule, found out<br />

by Resson, by<br />

which s msn is forbidden to do<br />

thst which is destructive of his life, or taketh away the means of preserving<br />

the<br />

same."<br />

In the state of nature the operative rule is "'That every msn,<br />

ought to endesvour Pesce, ss fsr ss he hss hope of obtsining it;<br />

snd when he<br />

cannot obtain it, that he may seek, and use, all helps and sdvsntsges of<br />

Wsr.'"<br />

It is by insight into their own best interest in the long<br />

run thst men<br />

"sre commsnded to endesvour Pesce" snd led to transfer or alienate certain<br />

nstursl rights (Jus, "liberty to do, or to forbesr") to the common power, in<br />

order better to enjoy snd use other nstursl rights which Hobbes ssys must be<br />

thought of ss insliensble.<br />

"Whensoever s msn Trsnsferreth his Right, or Renounceth it; it is either in<br />

consideration of some Right reciprocslly transferred to himself;<br />

other good he hopeth for<br />

thereby."<br />

By conceiving<br />

or for some<br />

of the constitution of common<br />

power or sovereignty as a transfer or mutual renouncing of certain natural<br />

liberties on the part of all individuals, Hobbes introduces the deliberate fiction<br />

of the 'social<br />

contract'<br />

as a voluntary act, with the proviso: "and of the<br />

31. See Hobbes, Thomas White's De Mundo Examined, trans. Harold Whitmore Jones (London,<br />

1976), pp. 466-69, where 'potentia'<br />

32. Leviathan, p. 150.<br />

is rendered as 'potential'<br />

33. Leviathan, p. 190.<br />

Following paragraphs, pp. 189, 192.


esses."35<br />

but<br />

peopl<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 239<br />

voluntary acts of every man, the object is some Good to himself." A contract<br />

constitutes a mutual<br />

binding<br />

of wills or persistent endeavors over time. The<br />

social contract is sn open-ended one, entered into to secure future (sppsrent)<br />

good, hoped for snd expected.<br />

his natural right<br />

While a man, to this end, can be understood to give up<br />

to the use of force, for example, he csnnot be understood to "lsy down the<br />

right of resisting them, thst ssssult him by force, or tske swsy<br />

his<br />

life."<br />

Self-preservstion is sn insliensble right. But the life which is msde secure<br />

by sovereignty<br />

is more thsn mere existence. "The motive snd end for which<br />

this renouncing snd transferring of Right is introduced, is nothing<br />

else but<br />

the security of s msns person, in his life, snd in the mesns of so<br />

preserving<br />

life, ss not to be wesry<br />

of<br />

it."<br />

In the preceding<br />

chspter of Leviathan, "Of the Nstursl Condition of Msnkind,<br />

ss concerning their Felicity, snd Misery," Hobbes hsd characterized the<br />

state of nature ss s condition in which "there is no plsce for Industry, becsuse<br />

the fruit thereof is<br />

uncertsin,"<br />

snd hsd concluded, "The Psssions that encline<br />

men to Peace are Fear of Death, Desire of such things as are<br />

necessary to<br />

commodious living, and a Hope by their Industry<br />

to obtain<br />

them."<br />

The civil<br />

state makes the future reliable to the extent that individual industriousness can<br />

living"<br />

be motivsted by the expectstion of sttsining the goods of "commodious<br />

through one's own efforts.<br />

Similsrly, st the outset of the chspter, "Of the Office of the Sovereign<br />

Representative,"<br />

where Hobbes speaks of "the end, for which he was trusted<br />

with the Sovereign Power, namely the procuration of the safety of the<br />

he adds, "By Safety here is not meant a bsre Preservation, but also all other<br />

Contentments of life, which every man by lawful Industry, without danger<br />

or hurt to the Common- himself."<br />

wealth, shall acquire to In a parallel passsge<br />

"ssfety"<br />

in De Cive he writes of ss the preservstion of life "in order to its<br />

hsppiness. For to this end did men freely<br />

sssemble themselves snd institute s<br />

government, thst they might, ss much ss their human condition would afford,<br />

live delightfully."34<br />

At the same time Hobbes holds that government "can confer no more to<br />

[its subjects'] civil happiness, than that being<br />

preserved from foreign and<br />

civil wars, they may quietly enjoy that wealth which they have purchased by<br />

industry."<br />

their own<br />

Moreover, in Leviathan Hobbes stipulates that "this is<br />

intended should be done, not by<br />

care applied to Individuals ...<br />

by a<br />

.<br />

general Providence,<br />

contsined in public Instruction, snd in the msking,<br />

snd executing of good Lsws, to which individual persons<br />

msy spply their own<br />

Government should provide for the hsppiness of the people<br />

only by<br />

their pursuits secure.<br />

msking<br />

There have been several attempts recently to show the importance of Hobbes<br />

34. Leviathan, p. 376, cf. De Cive. ch. 13, para. 4.<br />

35. Leviathan, p. 376.


240 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

for the founding of the American republic. The affinity<br />

of principles is greater<br />

with Hobbes than with Locke or the classical republican tradition,<br />

and extends<br />

not only to Hamilton, Madison and the Federalist, but slso, snd quite centrally,<br />

to Jefferson and the Declaration. One could pursue this affinity<br />

further with<br />

regard to natural equity, inalienable rights, and the civil (not natural) basis<br />

of property, for which Hobbes is the indispensable source of ideas that proved<br />

crucial to the conception of the republic realized through the Revolution.<br />

The essentisl point here is thst the stste for Hobbes secures something<br />

like s nstural right to endesvor, to life not ss survivsl but ss "a continusll<br />

snother."<br />

progresse of the desire, from one object to By definition, the goods<br />

thst sre the object of this 'pursuit of hsppiness' could not be determined by<br />

the stste or by s consensus, or by snyone for snyone else. A clear implication<br />

of Hobbes's conception of desire is that even the individual concerned cannot<br />

determine, once and for all, the good that he pursues, for defining<br />

and interests is itself part of the pursuit, of experience seen as endeavor.<br />

our ends<br />

A further implication, disturbing to many, reflects s psrsdox in Hobbes's<br />

conception of endesvor in his empiricsl psychology. The object of desire is<br />

the efficient csuse of desire, that is, desire is a passion or passive response<br />

rather than s voluntsry sction, yet objects are not desired becsuse they sre<br />

good but good becsuse desired. This circulsrity<br />

represents not<br />

inconsistency<br />

but insight on Hobbes's psrt, since it reflects an undenisble festure of humsn<br />

experience. Recognition of this circulsrity in experience is sn essentisl fsctor in<br />

the relstivism proper to true tolerance of<br />

diversity<br />

of vslues. It slso supports<br />

sn openness to the future which snticipstes thst goods snd gosls unknown<br />

to the present will emerge from humsn sctivity.<br />

With their spprecistion of the interdependence of pursuit snd plessure,<br />

Bscon snd Hobbes introduced s tendency, later brought to full fruition by<br />

Dewey and other pragmatists, to relativize the distinction between means and<br />

ends, and to deny the intrinsic superiority and the fixity<br />

of ends. A similar<br />

trait has been noted in the Jeffersonian conception of human practice<br />

submitted to sustsined criticism<br />

and<br />

in The Lost World of Thomas Jefferson.<br />

For Dsniel Boorstin " Jeffersonisns [sre] men immersed in sction, who were<br />

reticent snd inexplicit sbout the ends of their own sctivity."37 In whst Boorstin<br />

36. See the essay cited in note 18, which was first given as a paper in 1976 at the Bicentennial<br />

Meeting of the American Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies. Frank M. Coleman, Hobbes and<br />

America: Exploring the Constitutional Foundations (Toronto, 1977) has a critical, but superficial<br />

and<br />

leveling view both of Hobbes and of the 'constitutional foundations.' A far better treatment<br />

is George Mace, Locke, Hobbes, and the Federalist Papers: An Essay on the Genesis of the<br />

American Political Heritage (Carbondale, 1979), which claims that Hobbes is more relevant than<br />

Locke not only for Madison and Hamilton but for Jefferson as well. See my reviews of these two<br />

works and of Richard Tuck, Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge,<br />

1979), in The Eighteenth Century: A Current Bibliography, n.s. 6, for 1980. Tuck is illuminating<br />

on Hobbes, but mistaken in contending that the influence of natural rights theory<br />

was finished<br />

by Rousseau.<br />

37. The Lost World of Thomas Jefferson (Boston, i960), p. 148. Subsequent quotations are<br />

from pp. 149, 197, 199L, 53, and 226. See also pp. 198, 203, 214 and 239s.


changed.40<br />

Concept'<br />

for<br />

Enlightenment,'<br />

sctivity."<br />

Menschengeschichte,"<br />

others."<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 241<br />

sees as s new sort of theodicy, actually one characteristic of the Englightenment,38<br />

"the Jeffersonian explsined evil, not ss intended to msgnify good, but<br />

ss designed indirectly<br />

to promote<br />

Boorstin links this orientstion with prsgmstism, but sees it ss s spirit which<br />

"stifled the very desire of men to know the gosl towsrd which they were<br />

moving."<br />

"Jeffersonisn politicsl science .<br />

. was not concerned with duties<br />

because it has left the moral ends of the human community vaguely implicit<br />

in<br />

nature."<br />

Boorstin notes thst "concepts of the 'public interest' . . . were<br />

thought,"<br />

strikingly<br />

absent from Jeffersonian political but construes this simply<br />

as an inadvertent flaw, not s deliberate revision of republicsnism.<br />

Clsiming<br />

that "Jefferson never seriously<br />

mind might fit a msn to discover the proper ends of<br />

suggested that cosmopolitanism and breadth of<br />

society,"<br />

Boorstin fsils<br />

to recognize thst Jefferson had discarded the premise of classical political<br />

thought that the proper ends of<br />

society could and should be determined.<br />

Similsrly Boorstin finds "strikingly<br />

little discussion of hsppiness in the<br />

humsnistic sense of the well-being of the individusl" in Jeffersonisn writing,<br />

perhaps because by 'humanistic' Boorstin means 'normative', while Jefferson<br />

felt that setting goals of individual pursuit was precisely<br />

the concern of the<br />

"unique individual" which Boorstin accuses him of ignoring. "Even the concept<br />

of hsppiness was virtuslly emptied of its personsl<br />

Boorstin clsims,<br />

but this rsther reflects s Jeffersonisn tendency to define hsppiness only formslly<br />

in public terms since its 'personsl' thst.39<br />

mesning<br />

wss to be just<br />

A tug-of-wsr between public service snd privste fulfilment is projected in<br />

Jefferson's letters throughout his csreer. For example, sssured that he has now<br />

done his part for his country, he writes to Monroe in 1782,<br />

If we are made in some degree for others, yet in a greater are we made for ourselves.<br />

It were<br />

contrary to feeling<br />

and indeed ridiculous to suppose a man has less right in<br />

himself than one of his neighbors or all of them put together. This would be slavery<br />

the preservation of which our government has been<br />

and not that liberty<br />

.<br />

38. E.g. Immanuel Kant, "Ueber das Misslingen aller philosophischen Versuche in der Theodizee,"<br />

in Werke, ed. W. Weischedel (Darmstadt, 1966), VI: 105-24, which follows up the argu<br />

ment of "Mutmasslicher Anfang der<br />

Werke VI: 85-102, esp. pp. 92, ioif.,<br />

that justifies the loss of Eden on these grounds. The moral order of the world is not to be judged<br />

by<br />

contemplative reason, standing back from its entanglements, since our obligation to act is part<br />

of the reality. As already for Leibniz, and for Johnson as a critic of 'philosophical' theodicy,<br />

man's relation to providence must be practical not intellectual. See my essays, "Readings of<br />

Rasselas: 'Its Most Obvious Moral' and the Moral Role of<br />

Literature,"<br />

Enlightenment Essays 7,<br />

no. 1/2, (Spring 1976): 17-39, and "Johnson and Hume Considered as the Core of a New<br />

'Period<br />

of the<br />

Transactions of the Fifth International Congress on the<br />

Enlightenment I (Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century, 190), pp. 189-96.<br />

39. In his dialogue, "My Head Heart,"<br />

and My in the context of a defense of American<br />

sociability, Jefferson emphasizes the respect for privacy: "There is not a country on earth, where<br />

there is greater tranquility; where the laws are milder, or better obeyed; where every one is more<br />

attentive to his own business, or meddles less with that of<br />

12, 1786, Papers X: 447.<br />

40. <strong>May</strong> 20, 1782, Papers VI: i8sf.<br />

To Maria Cosway, October


proud.43<br />

242 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

That liberty is essentially private. It is the liberty<br />

which entered the world<br />

of political thought with Hobbes, who derived it both from nstursl right snd<br />

from 'the silence of the lsws'. In Montesquieu this personsl liberty, secured<br />

by civil lsw, hss become 'politicsl liberty'. The clsssicsl republicsn identifica<br />

tion of<br />

liberty<br />

with political life in the sense of dedication to the public good<br />

has been completely<br />

reversed. The very idea of a public welfsre thst requires<br />

the suppression or sscrifice of privste interest hss become<br />

questionsble.41<br />

The [Spsrtsn or Roman] republican conception of virtue, like the stoic<br />

philosophical conception, is defined by its antagonism to just the sort of ap<br />

petite that is celebrated as basic to human life by Bacon, Hobbes and their<br />

Enlightenment 'followers'. Desire, fed by an active imsginstion, lesds to the<br />

proliferation of artificial needs. Instead of seeing<br />

this process as a threat to<br />

the integrity of the personality and attempting to undermine it by<br />

an internal<br />

discipline an approach which Rousseau adopted at certain points most prom<br />

inent writers of the Enlightenment affirmed the open-ended chsrscter of desire<br />

snd urged thst it be controlled snd corrected only<br />

in snd through experience<br />

snd socisl intercourse.42 The ongoing socisl constitution of selfhood was not<br />

only finally appreciated as a fact, as a<br />

determinability<br />

that could not be avoided<br />

by any absolutization of autonomy, but the openended<br />

experiential character of the self provided the basis for a profound under-<br />

socially interdependent and<br />

stsnding<br />

of individuslity.<br />

Pursuit includes sn element of effort, the meeting and overcoming of re<br />

sistance, which itself gives s certsin vslue to sctivity.<br />

Lessing represented<br />

this Enlightenment sense of endesvor or enterprise when he wrote:<br />

Not the truth in whose possession any man is, or thinks he is, but the honest effort he<br />

has made to find out the truth, is what constitutes the worth of a man. For it is not<br />

through the possession but through the<br />

inquiry after truth that his powers expand, and<br />

in this alone consists his ever growing perfection. Possession makes calm, lazy,<br />

The 'hsppiness of<br />

pursuit'<br />

certsinly borrows something from the plessursble<br />

snticipstion of s gosl, but also involves enjoyment of the effort itself.<br />

The pursuit of happiness can be misconstrued as a chase after an ever<br />

receding goal only if one identifies hsppiness with the end, the cessstion,<br />

of pursuit,<br />

or what Hobbes termed "the repose of s mind<br />

satisfied<br />

It makes<br />

41. In chapter 21 of Leviathan, pp. 266f., Hobbes shows that the 'liberty' which is celebrated<br />

by the classical republican tradition is not that of individuals, but of states, their constituted power<br />

"to resist, or invade other<br />

people."<br />

In a letter of October 31, 1823, Jefferson wrote, "The govern<br />

ment of Athens, for example, was that of the people of one city making laws for the whole<br />

country subjected to them. That of Lacedaemon [Sparta] was the rule of military monks over<br />

the laboring class of the slavery."<br />

people, reduced to abject Writings XV: 482. See my paper,<br />

"The Critique of Classical Republicanism and the<br />

Understanding of Modem Forms of Polity in<br />

Vico's New Science," Clio 9 (Spring 1980): 393-418.<br />

42. See the essays cited in note 38 preceding.<br />

43. "Eine Duplik," in Lessing, Werke, ed. H. G. Gopfert (Munich, 1970-79), VIII: 32f.


'<br />

'pursuit'<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 243<br />

a great difference whether one sees desire in s negstive or s positive light,<br />

ss a state opposed to or akin to fulfilment. In the pssssge quoted, Lessing,<br />

as a good Leibnizian, conceived of perfection as an open-ended progressive<br />

quality, a denial of the perfected, closed off,<br />

as a process is characteristic of the Enlightenment.<br />

finished;44 this idea of perfectio<br />

Pssssges embodying this perspective could be cited from Montesquieu,<br />

Diderot, even Roussesu, from Johnson or Burke ss well ss Hume, from Schiller<br />

or Herder ss well as Lessing. But there is one figure, ususlly considered<br />

crucisl to the Enlightenment, who poses sn obstscle to this general characterizstion:<br />

Locke. The conative psychology<br />

that was so essential to empiricism<br />

in Bacon and Hobbes, and the corresponding conception of humsn nsture,<br />

sre fsr less evident in Locke thsn in Leibniz. This is psrticulsrly importsnt<br />

for the topic under consideration here becsuse Locke has been claimed recently<br />

as the prime source of Jefferson's idea of the pursuit of happiness. A confrontstion<br />

with this opposing interpretstion of 'pursuit' will provide sn spt<br />

conclusion.<br />

III.<br />

'HAPPINESS'<br />

VS. PURSUIT<br />

In Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence, Gsrry Wills<br />

devotes s chapter to snslyzing the term 'pursuit', giving<br />

emphssis to "elements<br />

necessity,"<br />

of determination snd<br />

ss in the phrase<br />

"'necessity determines to<br />

the pursuit of<br />

bliss.'"<br />

His main source of examples, this one included, is a<br />

single chapter from Locke's Essay concerning<br />

work, Wills suggests, and not the political treatises,<br />

Human Understanding. This<br />

was the significant Locke<br />

for the eighteenth century, the one who formed a triad with Bacon and Newton.<br />

model'<br />

A 'Newtonian determines the conception of pursuit focused on by<br />

Wills, the csussl necessitstion of a universal gravitation of wills that are irresistably<br />

moved desire.45<br />

by<br />

the objects of<br />

'Necessary'<br />

In the chapter headed<br />

from the phrase "when in the course<br />

of human events it becomes necessary<br />

Wills claimed thst "the Declarstion's<br />

opening<br />

is Newtonisn. It lsys down the<br />

lsw."<br />

Out of a sequence of observed results, a pattern emerges, and is stated as a law.<br />

The revolution of the colonies, like the revolving of heaven's bodies, is a process<br />

open to scientific observation and description. Jefferson has come to describe it.46<br />

44. I emphasize this neglected aspect of Leibniz in a review in Eighteenth-Century Studies<br />

12, no. 3 (Spring<br />

1979): 433-38.<br />

45. Inventing America, p. 241 Contrast Hamowy (note 7 preceding), pp. 511-16.<br />

46. Inventing America, p. 94 In his discussion of<br />

Wills quotes a<br />

telling passage<br />

from Bacon's Advancement. "It is order, poursuite. sequence, and interchange of application,<br />

which is mighty in<br />

of<br />

the original metaphor.<br />

But Wills reduces the laws of nature, including those of the 'state<br />

to laws of physics or mechanics far too literally to catch the liveliness and power of


244 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Accordingly Wills devotes that chapter to a discussion of 'mechanical phi<br />

losophy'<br />

in the eighteenth century, as if in explanation of the Declaration's<br />

opening.<br />

In an earlier psper I hsve srgued, on the contrary, thst this reference to<br />

'necessity'<br />

in the course of humsn events is sn sppeal to the law of nature<br />

in the sense of the nstursl right of self-preservstion ,<br />

vidusl but to s people in thst 'state of<br />

spplied not to sn indi<br />

nature'<br />

that prevails between nations.<br />

In the same vein Alexander Hamilton hsd srgued esrlier, in Hobbesisn terms,<br />

thst "when the first principles of civil<br />

society sre violsted, snd the rights<br />

of s whole people sre invsded,<br />

.<br />

lsw of nsture.<br />

. men msy<br />

then betske themselves to the<br />

We might note in psssing that Hamilton adopts this srgument from Blackstone<br />

snd contrasts it with doctrines supposedly tsken by his opponent Sesbury<br />

from the sinister 'Mr. Hobbes' This should suggest how Hobbes csme to hsve<br />

no overt influence in Revolutionsry Americs, although his ideas, working<br />

through Priestley or Blackstone, Hume, Hutcheson or Locke and often in a<br />

direction that cut across the main tendencies of these writers<br />

had a decisive<br />

impact. This is also the case with Locke's conception of the causal neces<br />

sitation thst determines 'pursuit', for Locke's mechsnics of motivstion derives<br />

directly, but tscitly, from Hobbes.<br />

the<br />

I would not dissgree when Wills claims that Locke's denial of 'freedom of<br />

will'<br />

is not<br />

only consistent with but material to an understanding of pursuit.<br />

As he says, "The will is determined by its<br />

object."<br />

There is, however, a subtle<br />

but important difference in the way this ides is taken by Hobbes and by<br />

Locke, leading<br />

to a major difference in their conceptions of pursuit. Locke<br />

understands motivation principally in terms of 'uneasiness', that is, in negative<br />

terms:<br />

What determines the will?<br />

The motive, for continuing in the same State or<br />

Action, is only the present satisfaction in it; The motive to change is always some<br />

uneasiness: nothing setting us upon the change of State, or upon any new Action,<br />

but some uneasiness. This is the great motive that works on the Mind to put it upon<br />

will.4"<br />

Action, [i.e.] determining of the<br />

In the long chapter 'Of Power', on which Wills bases his argument, Locke<br />

adopts a quasi-Hobbesian conception of motivation, but deprived of the open<br />

snd<br />

forwsrd-urging quality that characterizes 'endeavor' in Hobbesian psy-<br />

47. See the beginning of the essay cited in note iS preceding. The passage from Hamilton is<br />

quoted in Gerald Stourzh, Alexander Hamilton and the Idea of Republican Government (Stanford,<br />

1970), p. 10, cf. pp. 15-22. In a letter to J. B. Colvin. September 20, 1810, Writings XII:<br />

419, Jefferson says, "The law of self-preservation authorizes the distressed to take a supply of<br />

force. In all these cases, the unwritten laws of necessity, of self-preservation, and of the public<br />

safety, control the written laws of meum and tuum .<br />

"<br />

that is, civil laws of property.<br />

48. An Essay concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford. 1979), p.<br />

249. This is para. 29 of Book II, Ch. 21, to which further references will be made<br />

by paragraph<br />

within parentheses in the text. On 'uneasiness', para. 31-34.


'good'<br />

good'<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 245<br />

chology. For Hobbes conatus is not reducible to a self-preservative urge nor<br />

is it regulated<br />

by an essentially negative 'uneasiness-principle'.49 The determinist<br />

implications of the causal conception of motivation thus are fsr more restrictive<br />

in Locke thsn in Hobbes, snd Locke himself is clesrly not<br />

happy<br />

with such<br />

implications. He revised the chspter st several stsges in later editions, intro<br />

ducing a different conception of freedom, which is mixed, most uncomfortsbly,<br />

with the residue of the Hobbesisn conception.<br />

The new spprosch msy seem to complicste, but in fsct bresks with, the<br />

model tsken from mechsnics or grsvitstion theory, snd it does this by intro<br />

ducing the notion that the mind can suspend motives that are weighing or<br />

pulling<br />

on it. This is a variant of the epoche which classical sceptics and<br />

stoics claimed to be able to exercise on their own passions and desires. In<br />

contrast to Hobbes, then, for whom the will is simply the lsst desire, the<br />

cumulstive result of the process of deliberation ss a libration of<br />

competing<br />

(mutually corrective and interacting) motive objects or projected courses of<br />

sction, Locke sees the will ss<br />

"perfectly distinguished from desire" (30).<br />

Thus, while it msy<br />

seem s plsusible msxim that 'the greatest good determines<br />

the<br />

will,'<br />

Locke concludes "that good, the greater good, though apprehended<br />

and acknowledged to be so, does not determine the will, until our desire, raised<br />

proportionably to it, makes us uneasy in the it"<br />

want of (35).<br />

In the maxim which Locke is correcting, the Hobbesian relativist definition<br />

of 'good' was presupposed:<br />

wss whst wss desired, the 'grester<br />

thst which exerted the grester sttrsction (cf. 42). Locke has introduced a new<br />

normative element,<br />

a determination of<br />

'good'<br />

from without, and this is decisive<br />

for all those passages cited by Wills, though Wills either fails to see this or<br />

omits to acknowledge it. Wills's interpretation is thus damaged because Locke<br />

has in effect brought about an opposition between his idess of<br />

'hsppiness'<br />

snd pursuit.<br />

"Wherever there is uneasiness, there is desire," writes Locke, "for we con<br />

stantly desire hsppiness; and whatever we feel of uneasiness, so much, it<br />

is certain, we want [i.e. lack] of happiness" (39). This shows more than<br />

how removed Locke is from any idea of the happiness of pursuit. Locke sees<br />

in the unavoidsble concern with hsppiness the possibility of leverage to mske<br />

whst he considers to be 'the grestest a predominating determinant of the<br />

will, that is,<br />

a more constant cause of uneasiness. "How much soever Men sre<br />

in earnest, snd constant in pursuit of hsppiness. [Wills cites this statement<br />

as the first use of the formula]; yet<br />

they msy have a clear view of good,<br />

great and confessed good, without being<br />

concern'd for it or moved by it,<br />

if they think they csn mske up their hsppiness it"<br />

without (43).<br />

In the psrsgrsph<br />

preceding Locke hsd resffirmed the Hobbesisn perspective.<br />

"Whst hss sn sptness to produce Plessure in us is thst we csll . .<br />

'good', for<br />

49. Many writers on Hobbes, from Dilthey<br />

and Tonnies on, confuse his use of the term<br />

with that of Spinoza, who conflates conatus with the urge to self-preservation.


'msss'<br />

will'<br />

motion."50<br />

'should'<br />

246 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

no other resson, but for its sptness to produce Plessure .<br />

in us, wherein<br />

consists our happiness" (42). It is spparent that this can only<br />

be made con<br />

sistent with the succeeding<br />

confessed<br />

paragraph if we understand that the "grest snd<br />

good"<br />

is rsther known to be apt to produce grest hsppiness not to<br />

the one concerned but to someone else (like Locke)<br />

for'<br />

the other person.<br />

who 'knows whst's good<br />

Locke is in fsct tslking sbout lukewsrm Christisns who, "sstisfied of the<br />

possibility of s perfect, secure, snd<br />

lssting<br />

nonetheless "not moved by this greater apparent<br />

hsppiness in s future<br />

stste,"<br />

sre<br />

good."<br />

He wants them to use<br />

the stoic-sceptic<br />

capacity to stand back from the motives that are actually<br />

working on them, so as to achieve "a careful and constant pursuit of true<br />

and solid happiness" (51, another of Wills's examples, torn from its context).<br />

They must not only<br />

of pursuit.<br />

interrupt but break through the constant determination<br />

Wills elides the main bent of Locke's composite approach in order to as<br />

similate to the 'Newtonian<br />

beyond all earthly pursuits<br />

will. "Freedom is the<br />

with s smsll<br />

model'<br />

the attraction which ultimate good<br />

bliss<br />

should (but evidently does not) exert on the human<br />

cspscity,"<br />

Wills writes, "to resist the pull of things<br />

of hsppiness but grest proximity, in order to be true<br />

to the ultimste gosl of<br />

'resl' hsppiness."<br />

Although remote, 'true snd solid<br />

hsppiness'<br />

should exert a greater pull because of its magnitude, Wills would<br />

have the model imply. But then he must simply<br />

overlook the fact that this<br />

model has no way of accommodating such a<br />

"'Pursuit'<br />

is here used<br />

[he claims] as response to the gravitational<br />

tug of a determining<br />

object. In<br />

the push-pull pain-pleasure world Locke describes, the attraction of happiness<br />

gives that constant, that determination of reality, on the basis of which one<br />

can build a science of human<br />

I make no objection to such a program of 'human<br />

science'<br />

In an earlier<br />

essay I maintained that Hobbes's conception of motivation, which leads him to<br />

a denial of 'free far more consistent than that of Locke, also provides<br />

a sound basis for understanding and<br />

improving human freedom.51 But Hobbes's<br />

view of the social world on the model of a mechanics of<br />

interacting motive<br />

forces, attractive and repulsive, is not a "push-pull pain-pleasure<br />

as Locke describes. Locke was<br />

only<br />

world"<br />

such<br />

led to posit his second conception of<br />

freedom because his own version of motivation-modelled-on-mechanics made<br />

man seem more the victim of experience. Hobbes, on the contrary, with his<br />

parallel application of the concept<br />

'endesvor'<br />

in his sdsptation of Galilean<br />

mechanics and in his analysis of mind and motivation in terms of 'inner<br />

motions', far from reducing the lstter to the former, showed how freedom<br />

50. Inventing America, p. 242.<br />

51. "Materialism and Freedom,' Studies in Eighteenth-Century Culture 7 (1978): 193-212,<br />

esp. pp. 202ff.


goods."<br />

nece<br />

The Pursuit of Happiness in Jefferson, Bacon and Hobbes 247<br />

could snd must be understood ss adequate determination of our motives by<br />

our experience and of our actions<br />

by<br />

our<br />

motives.52<br />

In this respect, as in others, Leibniz was very much a follower of Hobbes,<br />

as is evident in his critical responses to Locke and to Samuel Clarke. The<br />

point of the 'endeavor' concept in the motivstion<br />

is nicely brought out<br />

analogy between mechanics snd<br />

by<br />

one of his snswers to the lstter:<br />

properly speaking, motives do not act upon the mind, as weights do upon a<br />

balance; but it is rather the mind that acts by virtue of the motives, which are its<br />

dispositions to act. And therefore to pretend, as the author does here, that the mind<br />

prefers sometimes weak motives to strong ones, and even that it prefers that which is<br />

indifferent before motives; this, I say, is to divide the mind from the motives, as if<br />

they .<br />

dispositions to act, by<br />

were outside the mind<br />

and as if the mind had, besides motives, other<br />

virtue of which it could reject or accept the<br />

motives."<br />

Where Locke maintains that, "whilst we are under any uneasiness, we cannot<br />

apprehend ourselves happy, or in the way to it; pain and uneasiness being,<br />

happiness"<br />

by every one, concluded and felt to be inconsistent with (36),<br />

Leibniz counters that "it is essential to the happiness of created beings; their<br />

hsppiness never consists in complete sttsinment, which would mske them<br />

insensste and stupefied, but in continual and uninterrupted progress towards<br />

greater<br />

The consistent Hobbesian conception of freedom not from but through the<br />

determinstion of our motives snd sctions, ss grounded in the concept 'endeavor',<br />

thus fully<br />

anticipates Jefferson's idea of the pursuit of happiness and its<br />

anslogues<br />

in the Continentsl Enlightenment. Initiative and<br />

risk-taking are as es<br />

determined or driven. In his<br />

sential to this sense of endeavor as is being<br />

dialogue, "My Head and My<br />

Heart,"<br />

Jefferson counterposes calculation of<br />

possibility against enthusiasm, relsting the first to the effort to svoid psin,<br />

the second to the urge to positive plessure, snd hss the Hesrt claim credit<br />

Necessity"<br />

52. In "Of Liberty and Hobbes answers the charge that his view of human action<br />

would make deliberation or consultation useless: "It is the consultation that causeth a man, and<br />

necessitateth him to choose to do one thing<br />

rather than another, and<br />

is not in vain, and indeed the less in vain by<br />

how much the election is more<br />

therefore consultation<br />

Hobbes, Body, Man, and Citizen, ed. R. S. Peters (New York, 1962), p. 256. I have argued<br />

that Schiller, in a critical inversion of Kantian transcendentalism, arrives at a similar identification<br />

of freedom and determination, "The Morality of the Sublime: Kant Schiller,"<br />

and Studies in<br />

Romanticism 19 (Winter 1980): 497-514, esp. pp. 5i3f.<br />

53. Para. 15 of Leibniz's answer to Clarke's Fourth Reply, Leibniz, Selections, ed. Philip<br />

P. Wiener (New York, 1951), p. 241 I touch on this aspect of Leibniz's continuity with Hobbes<br />

Leibniz,"<br />

in "The Separation of Reason and Faith in Bacon and Hobbes, and the Theodicy of Journal of the History of Ideas 42. no. 4 (October-December, 1981): 607-28. See Leibniz,<br />

New Essays on Human Understanding, tr. Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett (Cambridge,<br />

1981), pp. 169, 172 and 186, on<br />

or 'disquiet'.<br />

'endeavor'<br />

and pp 164-66, 183 and 'uneasiness'<br />

188-89 on


248 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

for the success of the Revolution: "We put our existence to the hszsrd, when<br />

the hazard seemed sgsinst us,<br />

snd we ssved our<br />

country."54<br />

Even before the Revolution he hsd derived the<br />

colonists'<br />

rights from their<br />

emigration, "rights thus acquired at the hazard of their lives and loss of their<br />

fortunes."<br />

Esrly<br />

settlers of the New World hsd responded to the call 'plus<br />

ultra,'<br />

which drew them beyond the limits of settled experience, the Straits<br />

of Gibrsltsr of the known politicsl world. In s sense<br />

they<br />

'state of<br />

nsture'<br />

in exercising<br />

a right, which nature has given to all men, of departing from the country<br />

hsd sought out a<br />

in which<br />

chance, not choice, has placed them, of going in quest of new habitations, and of<br />

there establishing new societies, under such laws and regulations as, to them, shall<br />

happiness.55<br />

seem most<br />

likely to promote public<br />

A nstursl, inslienable right to the pursuit of happiness was affirmed in their<br />

venture.<br />

54. To Maria Cosway, October 12, 1786, Papers X: 451. Jefferson is clearly both 'head'<br />

and 'heart'; his richly ambivalent relation to stoicism needs further study. Sec his letter to John<br />

Adams, April 8, 1816, Writings XIV: 467.<br />

55. "A Summary View of the Rights of British America," Papers I: 122.


The Lion and the Ass:<br />

A Commentary on the Book of Genesis (Chapters 35-37)<br />

Robert Sacks<br />

St. John's College, Annapolis and Santa Fe<br />

CHAPTER XXXV<br />

I. AND GOD SAID UNTO JACOB, ARISE, GO UP TO BETH-EL, AND DWELL THERE:<br />

AND MAKE THERE AN ALTAR UNTO GOD, THAT APPEARED UNTO THEE WHEN<br />

THOU FLEDDEST FROM THE FACE OF ESAU THY BROTHER.<br />

What he learned in the city of Shechem forced Jacob to return to Beth-el,<br />

the scene of his dream. It now sppesrs to him ss though life under the condi<br />

tions announced in the dresm will not be possible.<br />

By<br />

virtue of their circum<br />

cision the Hivites hsd become followers of the New Wsy, snd their murder<br />

constituted the fratricide which Jacob had hoped to avoid. Jacob is forced to<br />

return to the scene of the former dream hoping<br />

sage of the first dream more explicit.<br />

that God would make the mes<br />

2. THEN JACOB SAID UNTO HIS HOUSEHOLD, AND TO ALL THAT WERE WITH<br />

HIM, PUT AWAY THE STRANGE GODS THAT ARE AMONG YOU, AND BE CLEAN,<br />

AND CHANGE YOUR GARMENTS:<br />

Jacob begins his journey back to Beth-el by having his house put away<br />

their strange gods and cleanse themselves. It may be that he suspected Rachel<br />

of being in possession of Labsn's gods snd surely<br />

wss aware of the relation<br />

ship between that difficulty<br />

snd the trouble which he ssw in Chspter<br />

Thirtyfour.<br />

Cleansing,<br />

which is the antidote for defilement as discussed in the commen<br />

tary to Gen. 34:11, is accomplished in a combination of at least three wsys<br />

wster, time, snd sscrifice. One of the fundamental ways of cleansing appears<br />

in the following verse: And upon whatsoever any of them, when they<br />

are dead,<br />

doth fall, it shall be unclean; whether it be any vessel of wood, or raiment,<br />

or skin, or sack, whatsoever vessel it be, wherein any work is done, it must<br />

be put into water, and it shall be unclean until the even; so it shall be<br />

cleansed (Lev. 11:32). Cleansing is done by washing in water as in the days<br />

of the Flood. Only water, in its kinship to chaos, is sufficient to carry away<br />

with it everything which is superfluous. The object itself, however, is not con<br />

sidered clean until evening, that strange moment when distinctions become less<br />

real. Evening, which had arisen by itself as an uncreated mixture of the light<br />

and the darkness and had been considered the beginning of the world's inability


250 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

to remain within clear confines, now, precisely<br />

because of its undefined chsr<br />

scter, provides for the possibility<br />

of s chsnge in character.<br />

We had our first glimpse of the double role that water is capable of playing<br />

when we were<br />

considering the Philistines and their relation to David in the<br />

commentsry to Gen. 23:1. Those men, lately come from the ses, tsught Dsvid<br />

respect for the Ark ss well ss the srt of wsr. We shall return to the double sig<br />

nificance of water in the commentary to Gen. 49:10 by considering the lions<br />

which stood at the base of the great lsvsbo thst held the wsters of sblution<br />

in front of Solomon's Temple.<br />

Often things csnnot be clesnsed<br />

immedistely snd time is required: But if she<br />

bear a maid child, then she shall be unclean two weeks, as in her separation:<br />

and she shall continue in the blood of her purifying threescore and six days<br />

(Lev. 12:5).<br />

Cleansing is the opposite of defilement, which we discussed in the com<br />

mentary to Gen. 34:11. In the Book of Exodus it is used over and over again<br />

to describe the pure gold which was used to make the utensils for the Tent of<br />

Meeting<br />

and the Ark itself (see Ex. Chapters 22 and 28). In this context the<br />

word pure means refined by<br />

fire until all of the dross has been removed (see<br />

Mai. 3:3). The gold used for the Ark is intentionally<br />

not gold in its natural<br />

state. Purified gold had to be used in making the Ark because gold as found<br />

in nature is a mixture and hence not adequate for man.<br />

Partly<br />

for these reasons<br />

and psrtly becsuse of most men's resction to thst world of mixtures, especislly<br />

during the time of sscrifice, a shsrp<br />

line must be drawn between that world<br />

and the artful world in which sacrifice becomes possible.<br />

Defilement in itself is never considered sinful. It is part of the world and<br />

must be lived with. The grestest sin, however, is to confuse the two reslms<br />

by psrtsking in the sscrificisl meal while in a state of defilement. For such an<br />

act there is no cleansing: there is only banishment (see Lev. 7:21).<br />

3. AND LET US ARISE, AND GO UP TO BETH-EL; AND I WILL MAKE THERE AN<br />

ALTAR UNTO GOD, WHO ANSWERED ME IN THE DAY OF MY DISTRESS, AND<br />

WAS WITH ME IN THE WAY WHICH I WENT.<br />

Jacob will now return to the God who was with me in the way which I<br />

went. Jacob's manner of<br />

describing<br />

God at this point is somewhat curious. It<br />

seems almost to indicate that God has been following man. Up<br />

has followed the path which<br />

lay<br />

to now Jscob<br />

ahead of him and God has come along. That<br />

wsy led to the city of Shechem snd the difficulties which Jscob met there.<br />

4. AND THEY GAVE UNTO JACOB ALL THE STRANGE GODS WHICH WERE IN<br />

THEIR HAND, AND ALL THEIR EARRINGS WHICH WERE IN THEIR EARS; AND<br />

JACOB HID THEM UNDER THE OAK WHICH WAS BY SHECHEM.<br />

Before returning to Beth-el Jscob purifies his house by burying<br />

their strange<br />

gods. There sppesrs to be s reference here to Chspter Thirty-one. Jscob, st


The Lion and the Ass 251<br />

lesst st this point, suspects thst Lsbsn's gods were indeed stolen<br />

by<br />

one of his<br />

household. He buried these gods together with the esrrings of which we will<br />

spesk in s moment under the oak which was by Shechem.<br />

The use of the definite srticle is peculisr snd seems to indicate the exis<br />

tence of a psrticular snd fsmous oak near Shechem, and indeed there was such<br />

an osk.<br />

Drsmsticslly spesking it wss s very<br />

old osk which lasted throughout<br />

most of Israel's history. Following its history in msny<br />

of the English transi<br />

tions of the Bible is, however, sometimes confusing becsuse the word for oak<br />

is often translated/?/^.<br />

So fsr ss one csn tell the oak under which Jscob buried the strange gods<br />

wss the osk of Moreh where Abrsm built his first sltsr to the Lord sfter he<br />

left Haran. And Abram passed through the land unto the place of Shechem<br />

and to the oak<br />

of Moreh. And the Canaanite was then in the land (Gen.<br />

12:6). Moses uses the osk of Moreh as a signpost when he gives the people<br />

directions to Mount Gerizim and Mount Ebel (Deut. 11:3), and it was under<br />

this tree that Joshua wrote and set up the Book of the Lord (Josh. 24:24). In<br />

spite of all of these noble enterprises the foreign gods which<br />

lay buried under<br />

this tree finally came to the surface. Abimelech, the son of Gideon, whose story<br />

wss told in the commentsry to Gen. 34:11, wss crowned<br />

king by the oak of the<br />

pillar that was in Shechem (Judg. 9:6). The osk becomes even more significsnt<br />

when one remembers that immediately after the crowning of King Abimelech,<br />

Jothsm gsve his fsmous psrsble of the trees, which is perhsps the most theo<br />

reticsl srgument sgainst<br />

kingship in the Bible (Judg. 9:7-15; see also the com<br />

mentary to Gen. 34:11).<br />

Earrings slso plsy<br />

s seessw role in the development of the Bible. The gold<br />

from esrrings wss used by Asron to build the Golden Cslf (Ex. 32:2), but it<br />

wss also used<br />

by Bezaleel to build the Ark (Ex. 35:22). The last-time they<br />

are mentioned is in connection with the Ephod which Gideon msde sfter he<br />

hsd refused the kingship. The Ephod is then referred to ss s<br />

thing which<br />

became a snare unto Gideon and unto his house (Judg. 8:27). It msy hsve<br />

collected enough of the people into one group to hsve msde Abimelech 's king<br />

ship possible, snd its power smong the people certsinly gsve force to Abime<br />

lech's contention thst if he were not msde king the sons of Gideon would tske<br />

power (Judg. 9:2). In s slightly lsrger context Gideon's privste Ephod may<br />

have set a precedent for the private Ephod of Micah which played such an im<br />

portant part in the decline of the Jubilee Year. It led to the first private wor<br />

ship away from the people, who were to have all gathered together at the House<br />

of the Lord (see commentary to Gen. 15:17).<br />

5. AND THEY JOURNEYED: AND THE TERROR OF GOD WAS UPON THE CITIES<br />

THAT WERE ROUND ABOUT THEM, AND THEY DID NOT PURSUE AFTER THE<br />

SONS OF JACOB.<br />

6. SO JACOB CAME TO LUZ, WHICH IS IN THE LAND OF CANAAN, THAT IS,<br />

BETH-EL, HE AND ALL THE PEOPLE THAT WERE WITH HIM.


252 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

7. AND HE BUILT THERE AN ALTAR, AND CALLED THE PLACE EL-BETH-EL:<br />

BECAUSE THERE GOD APPEARED UNTO HIM, WHEN HE FLED FROM THE FACE<br />

OF HIS BROTHER.<br />

This time Jacob hss s ssfe journey, but he returns to Beth-el to where he<br />

fled from the face of his brother. In spite of God's protection, Jscob is still<br />

confused becsuse he sees no wsy of fulfilling the divine plsn of estsblishing s<br />

well-ordered<br />

society<br />

upon s just foundation.<br />

8. BUT DEBORAH, REBEKAH'S NURSE DIED, AND SHE WAS BURIED BENEATH<br />

BETH-EL UNDER THE OAK: AND THE NAME OF IT WAS CALLED ALLON-<br />

BACHUTH.<br />

Deborah, Rebekah's nurse, was buried beneath another famous oak. The<br />

author again speaks of the oak. as if it were an oak that we should recognize.<br />

In order to understsnd this verse it will be necesssry to remind ourselves of<br />

Rebeksh's character. She was the good womsn who quietly<br />

csred for blind old<br />

wss csrried through Isaac<br />

Isssc most of his life snd ssw to it thst the blessing<br />

and delivered safely into the hands of Jacob, even though Isaac was not fully<br />

swsre of whst he hsd done. The womsn buried under the oak in Beth-el wss<br />

even more removed from the divine plsn than Rebekah. She was the woman<br />

who cared for Rebekah herself when she was a very young<br />

child. The oak at<br />

Beth-el lived for a long time. It was the oak under which the man of God was<br />

found by the Prophet after his encounter with King Jeroboam. This was the<br />

Josiah three hundred nineteen<br />

young man who predicted the coming of King<br />

years too early (see commentary to Gen. 20:7).<br />

When the lion and the ass gusrded the body of the young man of God under<br />

this osk<br />

they were guarding a promise which would not be fulfilled for many<br />

years to come. The same long-range care is symbolized<br />

by the nurse. This oak<br />

stands in opposition to the oak at Shechem which concealed the gods that came<br />

to light in the days of Abimelech, the son of Gideon. But the oak at Beth-el<br />

lasted much longer than the oak at Shechem and its promise was fulfilled by<br />

King Josiah.<br />

Time, snd the wsy in which it csn concesl snd revesl, preserve snd destroy,<br />

is part of the answer to Jacob's fears and doubts.<br />

The oak is called in Hebrew Allon-bachuth, the oak of tears. The significance<br />

of this name will be discussed in the commentsry<br />

to Gen. 45:14.<br />

9. AND GOD APPEARED UNTO JACOB AGAIN, WHEN HE CAME OUT OF PADAN-<br />

ARAM, AND BLESSED HIM.<br />

10. AND GOD SAID UNTO HIM, THY NAME IS JACOB: THY NAME SHALL NOT<br />

BE CALLED ANY MORE JACOB, BUT ISRAEL SHALL BE THY NAME: AND HF<br />

CALLED HIS NAME ISRAEL.<br />

I I .<br />

AND GOD SAID UNTO HIM, I AM GOD ALMIGHTY: BE FRUITFUL AND MUL-


The Lion and the Ass 253<br />

TIPLY;<br />

A NATION AND A COMPANY OF NATIONS SHALL BE OF THEE. AND<br />

KINGS SHALL COME OUT OF THY LOINS;<br />

12. AND THE LAND WHICH I GAVE ABRAHAM AND ISAAC, TO THEE I WILL<br />

GIVE IT, AND TO THY SEED AFTER THEE WILL I GIVE THE LAND.<br />

The silent God hss finslly spoken sgain, and yet one msy also say<br />

that He<br />

hss not spoken. Jscob hsd slresdy schieved the nsme Israel sfter his wrestling<br />

mstch (Gen. 32:28). He knew very<br />

well thst he hsd been sent<br />

by God Al<br />

mighty snd thst he would become a company of nations (Gen. 28:3). The lsnd<br />

hsd been promised to him and to his fathers many times (Gen. 28:13), and he<br />

himself had already understood that he would be the father of kings (Gen.<br />

28:18 and commentsry). Appsrently, there is nothing<br />

new in the words of God.<br />

Appsrently, God is still silent.<br />

13. AND GOD WENT UP FROM HIM IN THE PLACE WHERE HE TALKED WITH<br />

HIM.<br />

14. AND JACOB SET UP A PILLAR IN THE PLACE WHERE HE TALKED WITH HIM,<br />

EVEN A PILLAR OF STONE: AND HE POURED A DRINK OFFERING THEREON,<br />

AND HE POURED OIL THEREON.<br />

15. AND JACOB CALLED THE NAME OF THE PLACE WHERE GOD SPAKE WITH<br />

HIM BETH-EL.<br />

The history<br />

is a<br />

fascinsting<br />

of pillars snd the role it plays in the development of the people<br />

and curious subject. Jacob was the first great builder of pillars.<br />

He built the first one at Beth-el after<br />

waking from his dream. (Gen. 28:18, 22)<br />

and even mentions it once to his wives (Gen. 31:13). He built another one as a<br />

permanent memory of his sgreement with Lsbsn (Gen. 31:45-52), snd he will<br />

build two in the present chspter<br />

one to commemorate the death of Rschel.<br />

one to commemorate the present moment and<br />

Moses slso built s pillar at the time he invited the sons of Aaron, Nadab<br />

and Abihu, to share his vision, and we remember well the disastrous effects<br />

of thst moment (see Ex. 24:9 snd commentary to Gen. 15:9). That was the last<br />

legitimate pillar ever raised in the New Wsy. One chapter esrlier Moses hsd<br />

slready<br />

commanded the people to smash the pillars which were dedicated to<br />

other gods when<br />

they enter into the new land (Ex. 23:24). In Leviticus they<br />

are commanded not to build any<br />

pillars (Lev. 26:1); and in the Book of Deuter<br />

onomy they are told not only to burn the existing pillars with fire but they<br />

are specifically told not to build any to God because their worship<br />

should be<br />

limited to the place which I shall choose (Deut. 12:3-5), the phrase which<br />

became so important for us in the commentary<br />

to Gen. 15:9. The text even<br />

goes so fsr ss to ssy the Lord hates pillars (Deut. 16:22).<br />

The first illegitimate pillar was built by Absalom in self-commemoration<br />

(II Sam. 18:18), and immediately<br />

after Jeroboam's revolution there were pillars<br />

built on every high hill, and under every green tree (I Kings 14:23).


254 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Under the influence of his wife, Jezebel, Ahab became a great builder of<br />

pillars to Baal (II Kings 3:2). In that sense<br />

they became the counterpart in the<br />

southern kingdom to the altar which Jeroboam built at Beth-el in the northern<br />

kingdom. Although Jehu and Hezekiah began the work of<br />

tearing<br />

(II Kings 10:27 and 18:4), their final destruction came in the reign of Josiah,<br />

them down<br />

one verse prior to the highest point in the book when he destroyed the altar at<br />

Beth-el, long the symbol of a divided nation (II Kings 23:14).<br />

Perhsps the best wsy of understsnding the radical change in the Biblical atti<br />

tude toward pillars is to consider the present text more deeply by comparing<br />

it with Jacob's last journey<br />

to Beth-el (Gen. 28:18). On that occssion he poured<br />

oil on the pillar, symbolizing his awareness that there would be snother dsy in<br />

which the formslities snd rigor of<br />

kingship<br />

snd priesthood would come to his<br />

people. This time he sdds a libation of wine.<br />

Up<br />

until this point Jacob had forgotten the wine. In other words the one<br />

thing Jacob had forgotten is forgetting itself (see commentaries to Gen. 9:21,<br />

22, and 19:31).<br />

Understanding the verse in this way<br />

begins to reveal the full<br />

meaning of Verse Eight in which Deborah, Rebekah's nurse, died. Jacob had<br />

forgotten that ideas can sleep while life continues. Man's ability to forget and<br />

to remember is the means which will allow the New Way to be established in<br />

spite of the fears which Jacob felt at the end of Chapter Thirty-four. There sre<br />

times when men must fight their brothers, snd while scars of those battles will<br />

never<br />

completely disappear, the battles themselves will be forgotten and life<br />

will once more be possible.<br />

For reasons which will become evident, it is proper that something should<br />

be said at this point about what moderns might call our method of<br />

reading the<br />

Bible. It is difficult to speak of a method in the sense of s tool with which<br />

we come to the book, other than the notion that one should begin by assuming<br />

that a book is written with intelligence until the opposite is shown. Nonethe<br />

less it is clear that a certain way<br />

has developed. It began in the days of<br />

Abrahsm when by chance we noticed that the places in which he built altars<br />

became important in later times. Following the indication that the Bible wished<br />

to be read in such a manner, we tried to recall everything that happened in a<br />

given place or to a given group of men whenever their names appeared, and in<br />

general a story evolved. In one sense our task was msde essy because of the<br />

modern invention of the concordance. In another sense we have seriously failed<br />

to participate in the Bible when we used that book.<br />

If we had not had the concordance, reading the Bible would have been a<br />

slow process of remembering and forgetting<br />

which would have duplicated life<br />

as the author understood it. The author's way is not merely a literary device.<br />

It duplicstes his understsnding of men snd their wsys. Men live by traditions<br />

which bury themselves deep into the land only<br />

to arise from time to time for<br />

good or for bad. At times they are forgotten and then suddenly<br />

reappesr on<br />

the surfsce. The Bible is not only sn sttempt to lay the roots of 3 tradition;


The Lion and the Ass 255<br />

it is also a dramatic showing-forth of how such traditions are possible, but one<br />

cannot see that presentation without, at least in some sense, participating in it.<br />

1 6. AND THEY JOURNEYED FROM BETH-EL; AND THERE WAS BUT A LITTLE<br />

WAY TO COME TO EPHRATH; AND RACHEL TRAVAILED, AND SHE HAD HARD<br />

LABOUR.<br />

17. AND IT CAME TO PASS, WHEN SHE WAS IN HARD LABOUR, THAT THE<br />

MIDWIFE SAID UNTO HER, FEAR NOT: THOU SHALT HAVE THIS SON ALSO.<br />

l8. AND IT CAME TO PASS, AS HER SOUL WAS IN DEPARTING, (FOR SHE DIED)<br />

THAT SHE CALLED HIS NAME BEN-ONE BUT HIS FATHER CALLED HIM<br />

BENJAMIN.<br />

The son which she had asked for has finally come, but Rachel, even on her<br />

death bed, csnnot rejoice in birth; the nsme she gave to her son means the<br />

son of my sorrow. This time Jacob can no longer accept Rachel's way and<br />

re-names the child the son of my<br />

right hand.<br />

19. AND RACHEL DIED, AND WAS BURIED IN THE WAY TO EPHRATH, WHICH<br />

IS BETHLEHEM.<br />

20. AND JACOB SET A PILLAR UPON HER GRAVE THAT IS THE PILLAR OF<br />

RACHEL'S GRAVE UNTO THIS DAY.<br />

21 . AND ISRAEL JOURNEYED,<br />

AND SPREAD HIS TENT BEYOND THE TOWER OF<br />

EDAR.<br />

22. AND IT CAME TO PASS, WHEN ISRAEL DWELT IN THAT LAND, THAT<br />

REUBEN WENT AND LAY WITH BILHAH HIS FATHER'S CONCUBINE: AND<br />

ISRAEL HEARD IT. NOW THE SONS OF JACOB WERE TWELVE:<br />

Now that Rachel is desd Reuben sleeps with her hsndmsid, Bilhsh. He sssumes<br />

thst at the desth of Rschel the connection between his father and Bilhah<br />

became even less than it hsd been previously. One might csll this relstionship<br />

sn extremely mild esse of incest. For the full story of Reuben see the com<br />

mentary<br />

to Gen. 49:3.<br />

23. THE SONS OF LEAH; REUBEN, JACOB'S FIRSTBORN, AND SIMEON, AND<br />

LEVI, AND JUDAH, AND ISSACHAR, AND ZEBULUN:<br />

24. THE SONS OF RACHEL: JOSEPH, AND BENJAMIN:<br />

25. AND THE SONS OF BILHAH, RACHEL'S HANDMAID; DAN, AND NAPHTALL<br />

26. AND THE SONS OF ZILPAH, LEAH'S HANDMAID; GAD AND ASHER: THESE<br />

ARE THE SONS OF JACOB, WHICH WERE BORN TO HIM IN PADAN-ARAM.<br />

27. AND JACOB CAME UNTO ISAAC HIS FATHER UNTO MAMRE, UNTO THE<br />

CITY OF ARBAH, WHICH IS HEBRON, WHERE ABRAHAM AND ISAAC SOJOURNED.<br />

So old Isaac is still alive. It has been msny years since we have seen him,<br />

and by<br />

now most of us had either forgotten him or thought that he was dead.


256 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

This is the third time death has come to s msjor chsrscter in the book. The<br />

first msjor chsrscter to die wss Ssrsh; she died st the sge of<br />

127<br />

yesrs (Gen.<br />

23:1), seven yesrs longer thsn the life thst wss granted to msn sfter the<br />

Flood (Gen. 6:3). Strangely enough Isaac was sixty<br />

years old at the birth of<br />

Jacob, which would mean that his life after the birth of Jacob was precisely<br />

120 years. In a more complicated way the same thing is true of Abraham. He<br />

died st the sge of 175 (Gen. 25:1). Now Isaac was born when Abraham was<br />

99, and Sarah died when Isaac was 40 (Gen. 25:20). If one allows one year for<br />

mourning, that would mean that Abraham was 140 when he married Keturah,<br />

or that he lived with Keturah for 35<br />

years. Now Ishmael was born when<br />

Abraham was 86, and therefore we may<br />

presume that he was conceived when<br />

Abraham was 85. In the commentary to Gen. 25:1 we showed that Abraham<br />

had two lives one which he led as a private man and the other which he led<br />

as the founder of the New Way. If one presupposes that his private life lasted<br />

from his birth to the conception of Ishmael and was resumed sgsin when he<br />

msrried Keturah, the length of that life was 85 yesrs plus 35 yesrs or exsctly<br />

120 yesrs, the length of life which God prescribed to msn.<br />

There sre<br />

interesting differences in the two esses which completely reflect<br />

the chsrscters of Abraham and Isaac. The part of Abraham's life which was<br />

devoted to the New Wsy lssted until he hsd seen his son safely<br />

married. It<br />

included the care he took in preserving the Way. Isaac's private life began at<br />

the birth of his son. Once he had passed on the seed his work was<br />

essentially<br />

over. Abraham's private life was full and rich; it produced many<br />

grest nstions<br />

and would have commsnded our respect even if he had not been chosen to<br />

establish the New Way, but Isaac would have remained unknown.<br />

Moses died at the age of 120; in his case there was no distinction between<br />

the two lives.<br />

28. AND THE DAYS OF ISAAC WERE AN HUNDRED AND FOUR-SCORE YEARS.<br />

29. AND ISAAC EXPIRED, AND DIED, AND WAS GATHERED UNTO HIS PEOPLE,<br />

BEING OLD AND FULL OF DAYS: AND HIS SONS ESAU AND JACOB BURIED HIM.<br />

As in the case of Abraham, Isaac is buried by both of his sons. Again his<br />

death seems to be private and detached from the New Way (see Gen. 25:9).<br />

CHAPTER XXXVI<br />

I .<br />

NOW THESE ARE THE GENERATIONS OF ESAU, WHO IS EDOM.<br />

2. ESAU TOOK HIS WIVES OF THE DAUGHTERS OF CANAAN; ADAH THE<br />

DAUGHTER OF ELON THE HITTITE, AND AHOLIBAMAH THE DAUGHTER OF<br />

ANAH THE DAUGHTER OF ZIBEON THE HIVITE;<br />

3. AND BASHEMATH ISHMAEL'S DAUGHTER, SISTER OF NEBAJOTH.


The Lion and the Ass 257<br />

Chapter Thirty-six, the chspter<br />

desling with the descendsnts of Essu, is by<br />

fsr the most artless chapter of the entire book and perhaps the most artless<br />

chspter in the whole of the Bible. Hittites will become Hivites, women will<br />

suddenly become men, nsmes will sppesr from nowhere like rabbits out of hsts,<br />

snd brothers who slmost hsve identicsl names will suddenly become one. There<br />

are two reasons for this artlessness. First, the author, as it were, presents the<br />

history of Essu as if it had been preserved by his own children. In doing<br />

reproduces the artless chsrscter of Esau himself. There is no<br />

long<br />

so he<br />

tradition con<br />

cerning Ishmael. The way of the wild ass is not a way that keeps records.<br />

But Esau, as a strange mixture between the New Way and the wild ass, does<br />

keep records. However, they tend to get scrambled a bit.<br />

The other reason is more complicated. By his apparent artlessness the author<br />

reveals the nature of his own art. These chapters are a reasonable facsimile of<br />

traditions as they come down through the people snd may<br />

not be so unlike the<br />

mass of material which must have faced our author himself.<br />

The problem immediately<br />

presents itself in these first verses. Esau had mar<br />

ried three women. The first wss Judith the dsughter of Beeri, the Hittite; the<br />

second Bsshemath the daughter of Elon the Hittite (Gen. 26:34); and the third<br />

wss Mshalsth the dsughter of Ishmsel (Gen. 28:9). Suddenly, Judith's name<br />

becomes Adah who is now considered the dsughter of Elon the Hittite, who<br />

hsd been the father of Bashemsth. Bsshemsth, in the mesntime, hss become<br />

Aholibamsh the dsughter of Ansh, the dsughter of Zibeon the Hivite. And<br />

Mshslsth's nsme hss become Bsshemath, just to round things off. To make<br />

things even more difficult Anah will turn out to be male and a descendant of<br />

Seir, rather thsn being<br />

a Hivite who was supposed to have been a Hittite. We<br />

shall see more of this three-ring<br />

circus as we go along.<br />

4. AND ADAH BARE TO ESAU ELIPHAZ; AND BASHEMATH BARE REUEL;<br />

5. AND AHOLIBAMAH BARE JEUSH, AND JAALAM, AND KORAH: THESE ARE<br />

THE SONS OF ESAU, WHICH WERE BORN UNTO HIM IN THE LAND OF CANAAN.<br />

6. AND ESAU TOOK HIS WIVES, AND HIS SONS, AND HIS DAUGHTERS, AND<br />

ALL THE PERSONS OF HIS HOUSE, AND HIS CATTLE, AND ALL HIS BEASTS,<br />

AND ALL HIS SUBSTANCE WHICH HE HAD GOT IN THE LAND OF CANAAN; AND<br />

WENT INTO THE COUNTRY FROM THE FACE OF HIS BROTHER JACOB.<br />

7. FOR THEIR RICHES WERE MORE THAN THAT THEY MIGHT DWELL TOGETHER;<br />

AND THE LAND WHEREIN THEY WERE STRANGERS COULD NOT BEAR THEM<br />

BECAUSE OF THEIR CATTLE.<br />

There seems to be some question about the time of Esau's migration to Seir<br />

since in the earlier chapter he sppesrs to hsve occupied that country before<br />

Jacob's return.<br />

8. THUS DWELT ESAU IN MOUNT SEIR: ESAU IS EDOM.<br />

9. AND THESE ARE THE GENERATIONS OF ESAU THE FATHER OF THE EDOMITES<br />

IN MOUNT SEIR:


258 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

10. THESE ARE THE NAMES OF ESAU'S SONS;<br />

ELIPHAZ THE SON OF ADAH<br />

THE WIFE OF ESAU, REUEL THE SON OF BASHEMATH THE WIFE OF ESAU.<br />

1 1 . AND THE SONS OF ELIPHAZ WERE TEMAN, OMAR, ZEPHO, AND GATAM,<br />

AND KENAZ.<br />

Eliphsz's first-born son. Temsn. is mentioned ss the fsther of the tribe to<br />

which that other Eliphsz from the Book of Job belongs (Job 2:11), but none of<br />

the other sons mentioned in Verse Eleven ever sppesrs in the books with which<br />

we hsve been desling<br />

except for Kensz.<br />

We may<br />

not take the direct route to understanding this verse, but like the<br />

Children of Israel, who feared the giants and were forced to take the longer<br />

route which lasted forty years, we, too, must make a<br />

long<br />

excursion. Our fortyyear<br />

journey<br />

also begins in the thirteenth chapter of the Book of Numbers with<br />

the list of spies who were sent out to view the new land. Let us consider<br />

them individually.<br />

The tribe of Reuben sent Shammus the son of Zsccur whose grsndfsther is<br />

unknown. The tribes of Simeon sent Shsphst the son of Hori. The tribe of<br />

Judsh sent Caleb the son of Jephunneh, and Issachar sent Igal the son of Joseph,<br />

whose grandfather is also unknown. Ephraim sent the famous Joshua, son of<br />

Nun, but even his grandfather is unknown. There is little sense in going<br />

through the rest of the list. In only one case can the geneology<br />

of the spies be<br />

trsced bsck beyond the second generation. This is a very<br />

peculiar circumstance<br />

to find in a book which relies so<br />

hesvily<br />

lines the importsnce of fsmily<br />

mskes matters most strange indeed.<br />

on tradition snd which so often under<br />

trees. The fsct thst this is even true of Joshus<br />

At this point we must make a second detour to understsnd something about<br />

the character of Joshua. Soon after the Israelites had escaped Pharaoh's srmy,<br />

they were sttscked by the Amslekites. At thst point the son of Nun suddenly<br />

sppesred in the text for the first time snd becsme the leader of the army in<br />

battle (Ex. 17:9-14).<br />

Little was heard of him again until Nadab and Abihu, the sons of Aaron,<br />

had that strange and somewhat vulgarized vision of God which played such a<br />

role in the formation of the great gap<br />

between Moses and the people. It was<br />

then that Joshua wss chosen to sccompsny Moses, snd from thst time on he<br />

stood on the other side of the gsp<br />

together with Moses (Ex. 33:1 1). It wss he<br />

who first told Moses the significsnce of the cries thst were<br />

coming<br />

from the<br />

csmp during the affair of the Golden Calf (Ex. 32:17), and he agsin wsrned<br />

Moses when Lldsd snd Midsd were prophesying in the middle of the csmp.<br />

Before becoming the successor to Moses his great virtue seems to have been his<br />

sensitivity to the dangers of wildness.<br />

Aside from Joshua, Caleb was the only spy<br />

who wss convinced thst the<br />

Children of Israel hsd the prowess snd stsmins to fsce the gisnts. When they<br />

returned, the other spies described the besuties of the lsnd snd the horrors of


The Lion and the Ass 259<br />

the gisnts. But Csleb ssid: Let us go up<br />

at once and possess it; for we are<br />

well able to possess it (Num. 13:30). Nonetheless the people becsme frightened<br />

and revolted. It was at that time that the Lord decreed that the Children of<br />

Israel would be forced to wander<br />

forty years in the desert because they<br />

were not<br />

yet able to face the giants.<br />

Only Caleb, the servant of God, together with<br />

Joshua, wss sllowed to live through that journey<br />

(Num. 24:22-25).<br />

As we mentioned at the beginning of this digression nothing<br />

to see the promise fulfilled<br />

is known about<br />

the fathers of any of the spies with the exception of Jephunneh, the father of<br />

Caleb. Jephunneh was s Kenizzite (Num. 32:12) snd hence s direct descendsnt<br />

of the fifth son of Eliphsz, the son of Essu, just ss Csleb's son-in-lsw,<br />

Othniel,<br />

the first of the Judges, wss himself s Kenizzite (Josh. 15:17<br />

3:9)-<br />

snd Judg.<br />

This rsther<br />

shocking<br />

turn of sffsirs makes a certain amount of sense in the<br />

light of the second chapter of Deuteronomy, in which it is pointed out that<br />

while Israel suffered in slavery for four hundred years in Egypt, Esau was able<br />

to conquer the land of the Horims who seem either to be giants or at least to<br />

be in close contact with giants (see Deut. 2:12, 21-23). In Caleb the son of<br />

Jephunneh, a direct descendsnt of Essu, we see one side of Essu's chsracter.<br />

Essu hss the stamina and prowess which Israel lscked, but in the next com<br />

mentary<br />

we shall meet another descendsnt snd see snother side of thst chsracter.<br />

12. AND TIMNA WAS CONCUBINE TO ELIPHAZ ESAU'S SON; AND SHE BARE TO<br />

ELIPHAZ AMALEK: THESE WERE THE SONS OF ADAH ESAU'S WIFE.<br />

Eliphsz hsd snother son<br />

by s concubine nsmed Timns, but the general sub<br />

ject of concubines will be discussed in the following<br />

chspter. Our present<br />

problem is to discuss Israel's relationship to that other son, Amalek.<br />

The country<br />

of Amalek was first mentioned as having been captured by<br />

Chedorlsomer in Chapter Fourteen during the time that he wss fighting the<br />

gisnts. Amslek, ss we know, wss not s gisnt, in spite of the fsct thst he will<br />

often be sssocisted with them. Our tssk will be to understsnd thst kinship ss<br />

well ss to see whst distinguishes them.<br />

After the Children of Israel successfully eluded the srmy of Phsrsoh by<br />

crossing the Ses of Reeds they<br />

revolted becsuse of stsrvstion. Moses success<br />

fully quelled the revolt, and God promised to provide manna for the starving<br />

people.<br />

The people then arrived at a place called Raphidim where there was a second<br />

revolt, this time over the lsck of wster. Just sbout the time wster wss pro<br />

vided from s rock, the Amslekites sttacked from the rear. This was the begin<br />

ning<br />

of a war which was to last for centuries. The Amalekites, being descen<br />

dants of Esau, were of course much more closely<br />

related to Israel than either<br />

the Moabites or the Syrians, whom we have mentioned on many occasions.


260 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

They<br />

were the brothers who were to have welcomed Israel and to have provided<br />

them with easy<br />

access to the Promised Land so that it would not have been<br />

necesssry to tske the lsnd of the Ammonites. Had this plan worked the Jordan<br />

River would have formed the eastern border, and the unity of the people would<br />

have been assured. For as we remember, it was<br />

simply<br />

the largeness of the<br />

country<br />

which forced the eastern provinces to build the first sepsrste sltar.<br />

The Amalekites were to have been one of the first to receive the New Way<br />

in fulfillment of the fundamental promise.<br />

By being the first people to attack<br />

Israel they made it clear that so long as they<br />

would never be fulfilled (Ex. 17:8).<br />

lived the universal promise<br />

The critical meeting between Moses and Jethro in which it was determined<br />

that the New Way should be a way<br />

of written law took place in Raphidim<br />

immedistely sfter this bsttle (Ex. 19:2). By relsting these two incidents, the<br />

suthor seems to indicste the grest difference between the Amslekites snd the<br />

gisnts.<br />

The gisnts sre the irrstionsl forces sround us whom we csn escape by means<br />

of borders snd covensnts but whom we can never conquer. The Amalekites on<br />

the other hand are our own brothers.<br />

In their revolt, the Children of Israel showed that the wsters of chsos still<br />

churned<br />

deeply<br />

within them. If the firmament is intended to hold back the<br />

waters of the universe and borders are to hold back the chaotic waters of the<br />

Philistines, these laws were intended to contain the chaotic waters within<br />

the hearts of the people. The Amalekites, who were closer in kin than either<br />

the Maobites or the Midianites, are like the waters within our souls just<br />

as the giants are the waters beyond the expanse. Since they are psrt of us they<br />

cannot be excluded by mere borders.<br />

Their cowsrdly sttsck from the resr wss the first indicstion thst the originsl<br />

method of spresding the New Wsy<br />

vis their nesrest of kin would not succeed.<br />

The cowsrdliness of the sttsck led to God's decision thst the Amslekites should<br />

be trested as the men who lived before the Flood. His words were as follows:<br />

Write this for a memorial in a book, and rehearse it in the ears of Joshua:<br />

for will I utterly blot out the remembrance of Amalek from under heaven<br />

(Ex. 17:14).<br />

These people next showed up as living among the giants and were seen by<br />

the spies who brought back the reports concerning the invincibility of the new<br />

land (Num. 13:28,29).<br />

After God rebuked the people for their revolt in the face of the gisnts, He<br />

turned to Csleb snd called him My servant becsuse he alone would have been<br />

able to face the giants. The author takes that opportunity<br />

to remind us sgsin<br />

thst the Amslekites were<br />

living smong the giants, but we must remind our<br />

selves that Caleb too was a son of Esau.<br />

The following morning the men woke up<br />

and saw the Promised Land right<br />

over the hill. With a sudden burst of courage<br />

they decided to attack imme-


The Lion and the Ass 261<br />

diately without waiting the appointed forty years, but their courage came too<br />

late and<br />

they were defeated by the Amalekites, who chased them to a city<br />

called Horma (Num. 14:40-46).<br />

In the commentary to Gen. 49:5 we shall discuss the strange desth of Aaron.<br />

Thst desth hsd s profound effect on the people, snd<br />

immedistely<br />

sfter he died<br />

they were sble to fsce the Amslekites snd regain the city of Horma. That<br />

battle, while it did not mean that Israel had become giant-killers, allowed<br />

them to set off with confidence to the land of<br />

King Sihon.<br />

In that wonderful but brief period<br />

following<br />

the death of Joshua when it<br />

looked as though the Children of Israel could rule themselves under God<br />

without king or lesder, Judsh snd Simeon recaptured Horma with esse.<br />

There were several skirmishes between Israel snd the Amalekites during the<br />

times of the Judges. The first sttsck csme shortly sfter the death of Othniel,<br />

the Kenizzite. Thus, the same theme has occurred again. The Kenizzites were<br />

descendants of Esau. So long<br />

as Othniel was alive the Amalekites were no<br />

problem. Israel's best protection sgainst the evil side of Esau<br />

the Amalekites<br />

had always been a son of Esau himself, and Othniel the Kenizzite was such a<br />

man. There were a few more skirmishes, but in general the situation was quiet<br />

until the reign of<br />

King Saul.<br />

After Saul's first battle with the Philistines there wss snother brief bsttle<br />

with the Amslekites, who hsd appsrently tsken the opportunity<br />

to conquer<br />

Israelite lsnd during the Philistine war (I Sam. 14:48), but it was sometime<br />

later that the Amalekite wsrs becsme serious.<br />

Ssul's kingship hsving been well estsblished, Ssmuel reminded him of the<br />

divine decree sgsinst the Amalekites.<br />

Before the battle Ssul wsrned the Kennites, who were st that time living<br />

among the Amalekites, to leave so thst they<br />

would not be injured in the bsttle.<br />

The Kennites, whom we remember from the commentsry to Gen. 25:1, were<br />

descendsnts of Hobsb,<br />

Moses'<br />

fsther-in-lsw (Judg. 4:11). For the second time<br />

the text hss msde s connection between the Amslekites snd Jethro.<br />

Ssul was proud of his success in the fields that day, but he spared the life<br />

of<br />

Agsg their king<br />

God: And Saul said, They<br />

snd ssved the best of the cattle to present as a sacrifice to<br />

have brought them from the Amalekites: for the<br />

the oxen, to sacrifice unto the<br />

people spared the best of the sheep and of<br />

Lord thy God; and the rest we have utterly destroyed (I Sam. 15:15)- Saul's<br />

words of excuse to Ssmuel sre quite moving, but Ssmuel only snswers, Hath<br />

the Lord as great delight in burnt offerings and sacrifices as in obeying the<br />

voice<br />

of the Lord? Behold, to obey<br />

is better than sacrifice, and to hearken<br />

than the fat of<br />

rams (1 Ssm. 15:22). As s result<br />

Agsg wss hscked to pieces by<br />

Ssmuel, snd the kingship<br />

The sympsthetic way in which Saul's position is presented makes it evident<br />

wss tsken from the line of Ssul.<br />

that the suthor is swsre thst the esse of Amslek is s strange sffsir which must<br />

sppesr monstrous. It only becomes intelligible when we reslize thst we sre not


262 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

dealing with history<br />

but with a book about the nature of peoples and their<br />

wsys. Amslek csnnot be thought of ss s foreign race which is to be wiped<br />

out but as an internal counterpart of the external giant. Looked at in that way<br />

we can see why<br />

serve what must<br />

ultimately<br />

there are facets which might tempt even a decent man to pre<br />

be destroyed.<br />

During the early days of his rise to power, David, vassal to King Achish<br />

in Ziklag, pretended to his lord that he and his men had attacked Israel. But<br />

the truth is that during<br />

kites (I Sam. 27:8).<br />

While Saul was<br />

fighting<br />

this period David had begun his conquest of the Amale<br />

his last battle with the Philistines the Amalekites<br />

attacked the camp at Ziklag. When David returned he found Ziklag in ashes, all<br />

his belongings captured, and his wives tsken prisoner. But he wss sble to defest<br />

the Amslekites, free his wives, snd recspture his belongings with only 3<br />

smsll bsnd of men.<br />

Although King Ssul lost his throne for preserving Amslekite csttle ss a sacri<br />

fice to the Lord, David took possession of all the Amalekite goods and dis<br />

tributed them equally among all of his men, to those who fought and to those<br />

who did not fight. The pass3ge resds 3S follows:<br />

And David came to the two hundred men, which were so faint that they could not<br />

follow David, whom<br />

they had made also to abide at the brook Besor: and thev went<br />

forth to meet David, and to meet the people that were with him: and when David<br />

came near to the people, he saluted them. Then answered all the wicked men<br />

of<br />

Belial, of those that went with David, and said, Because they went not with us, we<br />

will not give them ought of the spoil that we have recovered, save to every<br />

man his<br />

wife and his children, that<br />

they may lead them away, and depart. Then said David.<br />

Ye shall not do so, my brethren, with that which the Lord hath given us. who hath<br />

preserved us, and delivered the company that came against us into our hand. For<br />

who will hearken unto you in this matter? But as his part is that goeth down to the<br />

battle, so shall his part be that tarrieth by the stuff: they<br />

shall part alike. And it was<br />

so, from that day forward .<br />

this day. (I Sam. 30:21-25)<br />

Among<br />

that he made it a statute and an ordinancefor Israel unto<br />

those to receive the spoils were the men of Horma (I Sam. 30:30).<br />

This insistence upon justice is intended as a revision of the simple ban on<br />

Amalekite goods which had been placed upon Saul.<br />

As we related in the commentsry to Gen. 14:4, Ssul wss wounded during<br />

his last Philistine war and asked his armor bearer to relieve his suffering<br />

with<br />

his sword, but the armor bearer refused (I Sam. 31:4). Two days later a man<br />

sppesred st Dsvid's camp to report Saul's death. According to his account,<br />

Saul asked him to do the same service<br />

by holding the sword, and the young<br />

man complied. When David discovered that the young<br />

man was an Amalekite<br />

his reaction was no weaker than Samuel's when he met Agag. As in the esrlier<br />

occssion the Amalekite youth was portrayed ss s decent msn. His exsct words<br />

were ss follows:


The Lion and the Ass 263<br />

He said unto me again, Stand, I pray thee, upon me, and slay me: for anguish is<br />

come upon me, because my life is yet whole in me. So I stood upon him, and slew<br />

him, because I was sure that he could not live after that he wasfallen: and I took<br />

the crown that was upon his head, and the bracelet that was on his arm, and have<br />

brought them hither unto my lord. (II Sam. 1:9-10)<br />

As in the esse of Ishmsel, something<br />

of value was understood to be closely<br />

bound up<br />

with the Amalekites and with the Amalekite in the hesrt of Israel,<br />

even though it could not remain. What makes the Bible an interesting<br />

book is<br />

its awareness of that value. The tradition of the Amalekites lasted for many<br />

centuries. Haman, the villain in the Book of Esther, was a descendant of<br />

Agag<br />

(Esther 3:10), and the hero, Mordecsi, wss s descendsnt of Kish, the Benjsminite,<br />

the fsther of<br />

King<br />

Ssul (Esther 2:5).<br />

13. AND THESE ARE THE SONS OF REUEL: NAHATH, AND ZERAH, SHAMMAH,<br />

AND MIZZAH: THESE WERE THE SONS OF BASHEMATH ESAU'S WIFE.<br />

14. AND THESE WERE THE SONS OF AHOLIBAMAH, THE DAUGHTER OF AHAH<br />

THE DAUGHTER OF ZIBEON, ESAU'S WIFE: AND SHE BARE TO ESAU JEUSH.<br />

AND JAALAM, AND KORAH.<br />

15. THESE WERE DUKES OF THE SONS OF ESAU: THE SONS OF ELIPHAZ THE<br />

FIRST BORN SON OF ESAU: DUKE TEMAN, DUKE OMAR, DUKE ZEPHO, DUKE<br />

KENAZ.<br />

l6. DUKE KORAH, DUKE GATAM,<br />

AND DUKE AMALEK: THESE ARE THE DUKES<br />

THAT CAME OF ELIPHAZ IN THE LAND OF EDOM; THESE WERE THE SONS OF<br />

ADAH.<br />

The author goes through this list of the sons of Esau once again in order to<br />

show the kind of government<br />

they lived under. Apparently, there was no unity<br />

among the sons of Esau, who lived in small communities each ruled by its own<br />

duke.<br />

This repetition revesls snother difficulty<br />

within the tradition. If the list of<br />

the sons of Eliphsz, the son of Adsh, given in Verses Fourteen and Fifteen is<br />

compared with the list given in Verse Eleven one can see thst Korah, the son<br />

of Aholibamah, hss suddenly become s son of Eliphsz. This confusion is probsbly<br />

intentionsl on the psrt of the author because it reminds us of a similar<br />

difficulty in Israel hsving to do with Korah, the Levite (see Num. 16 and<br />

17, and commentary to Gen. 20:7).<br />

17. AND THESE ARE THE SONS OF REUEL ESAU'S SON: DUKE NAHATH, DUKE<br />

ZERAH, DUKE SAMMAH, DUKE MIZZAH: THESE ARE THE DUKES THAT CAME<br />

OF REUEL IN THE LAND OF EDOM: THESE ARE THE SONS OF BASHEMATH<br />

ESAU'S WIFE.<br />

18. AND THESE ARE THE SONS OF AHOLIBAMAH ESAU'S WIFE: DUKE JEUSH,<br />

DUKE JAALAM, DUKE KORAH: THESE WERE THE DUKES THAT CAME OF<br />

AHOLIBAMAH THE DAUGHTER OF ANAH, ESAU'S WIFE.


264 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

19. THESE ARE THE SONS OF ESAU, WHO IS EDOM, AND THESE ARE THEIR<br />

DUKES.<br />

Verse Seventeen is in perfect sgreement with Verse Thirteen snd Verse<br />

Eighteen is in perfect sgreement with Verse Fourteen except thst it must be<br />

remembered thst Ansh was Aholibamah's mother.<br />

20. THESE ARE THE SONS OF SEIR THE HORITE, WHO INHABITED THE LAND:<br />

LOTAN, AND SHOBAL, AND ZIBEON. AND ANAH,<br />

21. AND DISHON, AND EZER, AND DISHAN: THESE ARE THE DUKES OF THE<br />

HORITES, THE CHILDREN OF SEIR IN THE LAND OF EDOM.<br />

Zibeon was the grsndfsther of Essu's wife Aholibsmsh, but her mother<br />

Ansh hss suddenly become her uncle. It is slso peculisr thst there should be<br />

two brothers nsmed Dishsn snd Dishon.<br />

22. AND THE CHILDREN OF LOTAN WERE HORI AND HEMAN: AND LOTAN'S<br />

SISTER WAS TIMNA.<br />

Lotsn's sister, Timns, wss the mother of Amslek, st lesst for the time being.<br />

23. AND THE CHILDREN OF SHOBAL WERE THESE: ALVAN, AND MANAHATH,<br />

AND EBAL, SHEPHO,<br />

AND ONAM.<br />

24. AND THESE ARE THE CHILDREN OF ZIBEON; BOTH AJAH AND ANAH: THIS<br />

WAS THAT ANAH THAT FOUND THE MULES IN THE WILDERNESS, AS HE FED<br />

THE ASSES OF ZIBEON HIS FATHER.<br />

25. AND THE CHILDREN OF ANAH WERE THESE: DISHON, AND AHOLIBAMAH<br />

THE DAUGHTER OF ANAH.<br />

Ajah may have been the father of Saul's famous concubine, Rizpah, with<br />

whom Ishbosheth sccused Abner of hsving slept. This sccusstion wss the immediste<br />

csuse of Abner' s decision to lesve Ishbosheth snd join the forces of<br />

Dsvid (II Ssm. 3:8 and commentary to Gen. 23:1). Rizpah was also the<br />

mother of the sons of Saul whom David hung in order to avoid the famine<br />

which was sent because of the deeds which the house of Saul had done against<br />

the Gibeonites (II Sam. Chap. 21 and commentary to Gen. 22:6).<br />

Anah, the son of Zibeon, was the mother of Aholibamah, the wife of Esau.<br />

Dishon, the son of Anah, was also her brother or his brother as you wish, but<br />

as we shall soon see he was two brothers all in one.<br />

26. AND THESE ARE THE CHILDREN OF DISHAN; HEMDAN, AND ESHBAN, AND<br />

ITHRAN, AND CHERAN.<br />

27. THE CHILDREN OF EZER ARE THESE; BILHAN, AND ZAAVAN,<br />

AND AKAN.<br />

28. THE CHILDREN OF DISHAN ARE THESE; UZ, AND ARAN.<br />

29. THESE ARE THE DUKES THAT CAME OF THE HORITES; DUKE LOTAN, DUKE<br />

SHOBAL, DUKE ZIBEON, DUKE ANAH.


The Lion and the Ass 265<br />

Dishon has finally become Dishan and the chsos is complete.<br />

30. DUKE DISHON, DUKE EZER, DUKE DISHAN: THESE ARE THE DUKES THAT<br />

CAME OF HORI, AMONG THEIR DUKES IN THE LAND OF SEIR.<br />

After s brief period of unificstion the brothers hsve now become two sgain.<br />

31. AND THESE ARE THE KINGS THAT REIGNED IN THE LAND OF EDOM, BE<br />

FORE THERE REIGNED ANY KING OVER THE CHILDREN OF ISRAEL.<br />

32. AND BELA THE SON OF BEOR REIGNED IN EDOM: AND THE NAME OF HIS<br />

CITY WAS DINHABAH.<br />

33. AND BELA DIED. AND JOBAB THE SON OF ZERAH OF BOZRAH REIGNED IN<br />

HIS STEAD.<br />

34. AND JOBAB DIED. AND HUSHAM OF THE LAND OF TEMANI REIGNED IN<br />

HIS STEAD.<br />

35. AND HUSHAM DIED, AND HADAD THE SON OF BEDAD, WHO SMOTE MID<br />

IAN IN THE FIELD OF MOAB, REIGNED IN HIS STEAD: AND THE NAME OF HIS<br />

CITY WAS AVITH.<br />

36. AND HADAD DIED, AND SAMLAH OF MASREKAH REIGNED IN HIS STEAD.<br />

37. AND SAMLAH DIED, AND SAUL OF REHOBOTH BY THE RIVER REIGNED IN<br />

HIS STEAD.<br />

38. AND SAUL DIED,<br />

AND BAAL-HANAN THE SON OF ACHBOR REIGNED IN<br />

HIS STEAD.<br />

39. AND BAAL-HANAN THE SON OF ACHBOR DIED, AND HADAR REIGNED IN<br />

HIS STEAD: AND THE NAME OF HIS CITY WAS PAU; AND HIS WIFE'S NAME<br />

WAS MEHETABEL, THE DAUGHTER OF MATRED, THE DAUGHTER OF MEZAHAB.<br />

The kings who ruled over Edom turn out to be a potpourri of names found<br />

throughout the whole of history. One can find a man named Saul, and Baalam's<br />

father is there, as well as the famous king<br />

of Syria.<br />

40. AND THESE ARE THE NAMES OF THE DUKES THAT CAME OF ESAU, AC<br />

CORDING TO THEIR FAMILIES, AFTER THEIR PLACES BY THEIR NAMES: DUKE<br />

TIMNA, DUKE ALVAH, DUKE JETHETH.<br />

41. DUKE AHOLIBAMAH, DUKE ELAH, DUKE PINON,<br />

42. DUKE KENAZ, DUKE TEMAN, DUKE MIBZAR,<br />

43. DUKE MAGDIEL, DUKE IRAM: THESE BE THE DUKES OF EDOM, ACCORD<br />

ING TO THEIR HABITATIONS IN THE LAND OF THEIR POSSESSION: HE IS ESAU<br />

THE FATHER OF THE EDOMITES.<br />

This list purports to be a summstion of the chapter in which the names of<br />

the sons of Esau are restated. It contains well known sons such as Kenaz and<br />

Teman. However, Timns snd Aholibsmsh hsve become transvestites,<br />

snd God<br />

only knows where the Dukes Elsh, Pinon, Mibzsr, snd s couple of the others<br />

csme from.


266 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

This comedy<br />

of errors concludes the discussion of the sons of Essu. As we<br />

ststed st the beginning of the chspter, it is intended to show the results of sn<br />

unweeded gsrden.<br />

Only one thing<br />

must be sdded.<br />

The book of<br />

Deuteronomy begins with the following verses:<br />

These be the words which Moses spake unto all Israel on this side Jordan in the<br />

wilderness, in the plain over against the Red Sea between Paran, and Tophel, and<br />

Laban, and Hazeroth, and Dizahab .<br />

the way of mount Seir unto Kadesh-barnea.) (Deut. i : i ,2)<br />

(There are eleven days' journey from Horeb by<br />

Scholsrs hsve often wished to delete Verse Two, since it mskes no sense<br />

geographically, not realizing that the author was concerned with more than<br />

geography in the simple sense of the word.<br />

Moses to the people.<br />

Deuteronomy presents itself as sn address given by<br />

It is a repetition in speech of the deeds contsined in the former books. In that<br />

sense it is the beginning<br />

of tradition as such. This speech which began the<br />

oral tradition in Israel, was delivered by the way of mount Seir, the unweeded<br />

garden of traditions. One day the author would pick his pen up<br />

for the last<br />

time. Perhaps he wondered whether the generations to follow would also be<br />

come lost in the desert and wander into the land of Seir.<br />

CHAPTER XXXVII<br />

I .<br />

AND JACOB DWELT IN THE LAND WHEREIN HIS FATHER WAS A STRANGER,<br />

IN THE LAND OF CANAAN.<br />

On msny occssions we have spoken of the four hundred years in Egypt.<br />

Actually<br />

it is not clear from what point one is to begin the count. The relevant<br />

passages from Genesis read:<br />

And he said unto Abram, Know of a surety that thy<br />

seed shall be a stranger in a<br />

land that is not theirs, and shall serve them: and<br />

they shall afflict them four hundred<br />

years; and also that nation whom<br />

they<br />

shall serve will I judge: and afterward shall<br />

they come out with great substance. And thou shalt go to thy fathers in peace; thou<br />

shalt be buried in a good old age. But in thefourth generation they<br />

again: for the iniquity of the Amorites is not yetfull. (Gen. 15:13-16)<br />

shall come hither<br />

However it is not possible to reconstruct the time sequence in Egypt. The<br />

closest that one can come is arrived at through the<br />

following verses:<br />

And these are the names of the sons of Levi according to their generations: Gershon,<br />

and Kohath, and Merari: and the years of the life of Levi were an hundred thirty and<br />

seven years. The sons of Gershon; Libni, and Shimi, according to theirfamilies.<br />

And the sons ofKohath; Amram, and Izhar, and Hebron, and Uzziel: and the rears<br />

of the life of Kohath were an hundred thirty and three years. And the sons of Merari:<br />

Mahali and Mushi: these are thefamilies of Levi according to their generations.


The Lion and the Ass 267<br />

And Amram took him Jochebed hisfather's sister to wife; and she bare him Aaron<br />

and Moses: and the years of the life ofAmram were an hundred and<br />

thirty<br />

years. (Ex. 6:16-20)<br />

and seven<br />

Now since Kohath wss born before Levi went to Egypt, it is obvious the<br />

four hundred yesrs must have included the time which wss spent in Canaan<br />

as well.<br />

The word stranger or sojourner is used here to remind us that Jacob will<br />

not be able to spend the whole of his life in the Promised Land.<br />

2. THESE ARE THE GENERATIONS OF JACOB. JOSEPH, BEING SEVENTEEN<br />

YEARS OLD, WAS FEEDING THE FLOCK WITH HIS BRETHREN: AND THE LAD<br />

WAS WITH THE SONS OF BILHAH, AND WITH THE SONS OF ZILPAH, HIS FA<br />

THER'S WIVES: AND JOSEPH BROUGHT UNTO HIS FATHER THEIR EVIL REPORT.<br />

Verse Two is difficult to translste becsuse of the rather subtle use it mskes<br />

of particles. The two psrticles involved sre eth snd be. The first particle is<br />

usually the sign of a direct object but may<br />

also mean with. The second one<br />

usually means in or among, but may be used to show the direct object of<br />

verbs such as ruling or caring for. The direct object of the verb meaning to<br />

care for a flock usually requires the particle eth. The same two particles ap<br />

pear with the same verb in Verse Twelve, which<br />

clearly<br />

must be translated:<br />

And his brethren fed his father' s flock in Shechem. For the reader who knows<br />

no Hebrew the conclusion of these reflections may be summed up<br />

if the particles are taken in the same sense as<br />

they<br />

Twelve of the present chapter,<br />

the generations of Jacob. Joseph, being<br />

as follows:<br />

must be taken in Verse<br />

then Verse Two must be translsted: These are<br />

seventeen years old, shepherded his<br />

brothers among the sheep though he was a lad, that is the sons of Bilhah and<br />

the sons ofZilpah, his father' s wives.<br />

The words which sre translsted evil report seem to refer to something which<br />

frightened Joseph rsther thsn to something evil. At sny rate the only<br />

other time<br />

the words sre used is in the description of the report which the spies brought<br />

bsck regsrding the gisnts (Num. 13:32 snd 14:36,37).<br />

3. NOW ISRAEL LOVED JOSEPH MORE THAN ALL HIS CHILDREN, BECAUSE HE<br />

WAS THE SON OF HIS OLD AGE: AND HE MADE HIM A COAT OF MANY COLOURS.<br />

4. AND WHEN HIS BRETHREN SAW THAT THEIR FATHER LOVED HIM MORE<br />

THAN ALL HIS BRETHREN, THEY HATED HIM,<br />

AND COULD NOT SPEAK PEACE<br />

ABLY UNTO HIM.<br />

Verses Three and Four contain the kernel of the problem which shall face<br />

us for the remainder of the book. After the vision at Beth-el Jacob realized<br />

that a solid snd well defined order would be necesssry in the life of his people.<br />

This order would require s preference for the eldest son. At the ssme time<br />

Jscob believed his youngest son to be the most cspsble, snd he wss slso st-


AND<br />

268 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

trscted to Joseph's youth, psrtly becsuse Jscob himself wss the youngest son<br />

snd psrtly because of the heroic streak in his .character.<br />

The elegant coat which he presented to Joseph seems almost calculated to<br />

cause the brothers' anger. It wss such s cost thst Tsmsr wore; not the Tamar<br />

that we shall meet in the next chspter but Dsvid's dsughter, who wss abused<br />

by her half-brother, Amnon (II Sam. 13:12).<br />

For further reference it should be noted that because of his extreme youth,<br />

Benjamin is not yet considered as being<br />

one of the brothers.<br />

5. and joseph dreamed a dream,<br />

and he told it his brethren: and<br />

they hated him yet the more.<br />

6. and he said unto them, hear, i pray you, this dream which i have<br />

dreamed:<br />

7. for, behold, we were binding sheaves in the field, and lo, my<br />

sheaf arose, and also stood upright; and, behold, your sheaves<br />

stood round about,<br />

and made obeisance to my sheaf.<br />

8. and his brethren said to him, shalt thou indeed reign over us?<br />

or shalt thou have dominion over us? and they hated him yet the<br />

more for his dreams, and for his words.<br />

The book leaves the symbols of dresms uninterpreted, snd though the mesn<br />

ing is relstively clesr there is no indicstion why<br />

these specific symbols are<br />

used. The word for sheaf<br />

never appears again in the books with which we<br />

have been dealing. However, the notion of<br />

binding may imply the unity<br />

tribe.<br />

of each<br />

9. AND HE DREAMED YET ANOTHER DREAM, AND TOLD IT HIS BRETHREN,<br />

AND SAID, BEHOLD, I HAVE DREAMED A DREAM MORE; AND, BEHOLD, THE<br />

SUN AND THE MOON AND THE ELEVEN STARS MADE OBEISANCE TO ME.<br />

IO.<br />

AND HE TOLD IT TO HIS FATHER, AND TO HIS BRETHREN: AND HIS FA<br />

THER REBUKED HIM, AND SAID UNTO HIM, WHAT IS THIS DREAM THAT THOU<br />

HAST DREAMED? SHALL I AND THY MOTHER AND THY BRETHREN INDEED<br />

COME TO BOW DOWN OURSELVES TO THEE TO THE EARTH?<br />

Given the author's way of relating the world to the human soul, the dream<br />

may be intended literally ss well ss metaphorically. During his rulership in<br />

Egypt Joseph, to a large extent, wss sble to rule over the fsmine; snd if he<br />

csn rule over fsmine, he rules over nature,<br />

down to him.<br />

and the sun and the moon do bow<br />

1 1 .<br />

HIS BRETHREN ENVIED HIM: BUT HIS FATHER OBSERVED THE MATTER.<br />

12. AND HIS BRETHREN WENT TO FEED THEIR FATHER'S FLOCK IN SHECHEM.<br />

13. AND ISRAEL SAID UNTO JOSEPH, DO NOT THY BRE I HREN FEED THE FLOCK<br />

IN SHECHEM? COME, AND I WILL SEND THEE UNTO THEM. AND HE SAID<br />

TO HIM, HERE AM I.


The Lion and the Ass 269<br />

14- AND HE SAID TO HIM GO I PRAY THEE, SEE WHETHER IT WILL BE WELL<br />

WITH THY BRETHREN, AND WELL WITH THE FLOCKS; AND BRING ME WORD<br />

AGAIN. SO HE SENT HIM OUT OF THE VALE OF HEBRON, AND HE CAME TO<br />

SHECHEM.<br />

Israel sent Joseph to his brothers in Shechem though he hsd observed their<br />

feeling towsrd him. Shechem wss the city in which they hsd slresdy killed<br />

their brothers the Hivites snd in which<br />

they<br />

could kill sgain.<br />

The words Go, I pray thee and Here am I race through the reader's mind.<br />

They are bits and fragments of a conversation he had heard once before. God<br />

was<br />

asking Abraham to kill his only son, and now it looks as though the same<br />

thing will happen again.<br />

Ever since the sffsir st Shechem Jscob knew thst the new land could not be<br />

established without bloodshed. He can see no other solution to the problem<br />

posed<br />

by the eminence of his youngest son. Jacob, like Abraham, was sacrific<br />

ing his dearest son and only hoped that through this sacrifice his sons, after<br />

reflecting on the horrors of their own deeds, would be able to pull themselves<br />

together and form s just society.<br />

Nesr the end of the dsys of the Judges there wss s series of incidents<br />

which mske it evident thst Jacob's fesrs, while<br />

they could be put to sleep,<br />

would one day awaken. First, there was the war between Joseph's two sons<br />

Ephraim and Manassah, during the judgeship of Jephthah, in which forty-two<br />

thousand men of Ephraim were killed (Judg. 12:6). Now as we have pointed<br />

out before, the days of the Judges were a constant struggle in which Israel<br />

would be conquered, a Judge would arise to free them, but at his death another<br />

enemy<br />

would arise. After the deaths of the Ephraimites there was a series of<br />

three Judges who reigned in peace. The only time in which this record was<br />

approached was when two Judges peacefully led Israel after the kingship of<br />

Abimelech.<br />

The problem came to light sgsin, but this time it sffected Joseph's younger<br />

brother Benjamin more directly. The massacre of the Benjaminites at the end<br />

of the Book of Judges made it evident to sll thst Israel desperately needed s<br />

king. In s somewhst more mitigsted<br />

wsy<br />

the same theme reoccurred when Saul<br />

finally united the people by hewing the yoke of oxen and sending<br />

to all the tribes as a call to arms against the Ammonite.<br />

the pieces<br />

15. AND A CERTAIN MAN FOUND HIM, AND. BEHOLD, HE WAS WANDERING<br />

IN THE FIELD: AND THE MAN ASKED HIM, SAYING, WHAT SEEKEST THOU?<br />

l6. AND HE SAID, I SEEK MY BRETHREN: TELL ME,<br />

I PRAY THEE, WHERE<br />

THEY FEED THEIR FLOCKS.<br />

17. AND THE MAN SAID, THEY ARE DEPARTED HENCE: FOR I HEARD THEM<br />

SAY. LET US GO TO DOTHAN. AND JOSEPH WENT AFTER HIS BRETHREN, AND<br />

FOUND THEM IN DOTHAN.


270 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Fortunately<br />

the brothers had left Shechem before Joseph's arrival and had<br />

gone to Dothan. When Joseph srrived st Shechem he wss met<br />

by s mysterious<br />

msn whose identity is not revealed. Therefore, we do not know whether it was<br />

the man with whom Jacob wrestled that lonely evening<br />

or not (Gen. 32:24).<br />

Nor do we know whether it was one of the men who stood in front of Abra<br />

ham's tent (Gen. 18:2).<br />

Dothan, the city in which Joseph was not killed, was also the scene of the<br />

famous war that wasn't in the time of Elisha (II Kings 6:13 and the com<br />

mentary<br />

to Gen. 31:45).<br />

l8. AND WHEN THEY SAW HIM AFAR OFF, EVEN BEFORE HE CAME NEAR<br />

UNTO THEM, THEY CONSPIRED AGAINST HIM TO SLAY HIM.<br />

19. AND THEY SAID ONE TO ANOTHER, BEHOLD, THIS DREAMER COMETH.<br />

20. COME NOW, THEREFORE. AND LET US SLAY HIM, AND CAST HIM INTO<br />

SOME PIT; AND WE WILL SAY, SOME EVIL BEAST HATH DEVOURED HIM: AND<br />

WE SHALL SEE WHAT WILL BECOME OF HIS DREAMS.<br />

21. AND REUBEN HEARD IT, AND HE DELIVERED HIM OUT OF THEIR HANDS;<br />

AND SAID, LET US NOT KILL HIM.<br />

22. AND REUBEN SAID UNTO THEM, SHED NO BLOOD, BUT CAST HIM INTO<br />

THIS PIT THAT IS IN THE WILDERNESS, AND LAY NO HAND UPON HIM; THAT<br />

HE MIGHT RID HIM OUT OF THEIR HANDS, TO DELIVER HIM TO HIS FATHER<br />

AGAIN.<br />

Given the fact that Reuben slept with his father's wife in Gen. 35:22, it is<br />

surprising that he should be the one to try<br />

and save his brother's life. It is<br />

even more<br />

surprising that he should sttempt the most pious solution returning<br />

the son to his fsther. These sre part of the fragments of Reuben's life which<br />

we shall<br />

try to piece together in the commentary<br />

to Gen. 47:5.<br />

23. AND IT CAME TO PASS, WHEN JOSEPH WAS COME UNTO HIS BRETHREN,<br />

THAT THEY STRIPT JOSEPH OUT OF HIS COAT, HIS COAT OF MANY COLOURS<br />

THAT WAS ON HIM.<br />

24. AND THEY TOOK HIM,<br />

AND CAST HIM INTO A PIT: AND THE PIT WAS<br />

EMPTY, THERE WAS NO WATER IN IT.<br />

When the author says And the pit was empty, there was no water in it,<br />

he has in mind Chapter Twenty-six, Verse Thirty-seven, in which Isaac finally<br />

found wster after all his diggings. If finding water was Isasc's great act then<br />

the availability<br />

of such underground sources seems to be related to the hidden<br />

springs of tradition. The implication is thst from at lesst one point of view<br />

those sources have dried up<br />

and Joseph will have to begin again.<br />

25. AND THEY SAT DOWN TO EAT BREAD: AND THEY LIFTED UP THEIR EYES<br />

AND LOOKED, AND BEHOLD, A COMPANY OF ISHMAELITES CAME FROM GIL


The Lion and the Ass 111<br />

EAD, WITH THEIR CAMELS BEARING SPICERY AND BALM AND MYRRH, GOING<br />

TO CARRY IT DOWN TO EGYPT.<br />

The caravan of Ishmaelites is csrrying spicery<br />

and balm and myrrh to be<br />

sold in Egypt. The brothers do not reslize thst in thirty-five yesrs they them<br />

selves will be msking the ssme trip, carrying spicery<br />

and balm and myrrh<br />

(see Gen. 43:1 1 ,<br />

and for the calculation see the commentary<br />

to Gen. 47:28).<br />

26. AND JUDAH SAID UNTO HIS BRETHREN, WHAT PROFIT IS IT IF WE SLAY<br />

OUR BROTHER AND CONCEAL HIS BLOOD?<br />

27. COME, AND LET US SELL HIM TO THE ISHMAELITES, AND LET NOT OUR<br />

HAND BE UPON HIM; FOR HE IS OUR BROTHER AND OUR FLESH. AND HIS<br />

BRETHREN HEARD HIM.<br />

While Reuben's plan was the more pious, Judah's plan seems to be the<br />

wiser. This wisdom is displayed in several ways. First of all, he realizes that<br />

if Joseph were to return to his father's house, the same problems would arise<br />

again. He is also wise enough to realize thst Joseph is cspsble of msnsging<br />

his own sffsirs even in difficult circumstsnces. Perhsps his greatest wisdom is<br />

revealed in the twofold nature of the sppesl which he makes to his brothers.<br />

If was<br />

only after he had shown them that they would gain nothing by the<br />

murder of their brother that he appealed to the natural abhorrence of fratricide.<br />

He sppesls both to whst is lowest in them and to what is highest. Without the<br />

appeal to the lowest, they would not have heard the highest,<br />

sppesl to the highest they<br />

would hsve lesrned nothing.<br />

snd without the<br />

28. AND THERE PASSED BY MIDIANITES, MERCHANTMEN; AND THEY DREW<br />

AND LIFTED JOSEPH OUT OF THE PIT, AND SOLD JOSEPH TO THE ISHMAELITES<br />

FOR TWENTY PIECES OF SILVER: AND THEY BROUGHT JOSEPH INTO EGYPT.<br />

This passage has caused great difficulties over the centuries.<br />

According to<br />

Verse Twenty-eight, whoever drew Joseph out of the pit sold him to the Ish<br />

maelites, who in turn sold him to the Egyptians. This is essentially<br />

in agree<br />

ment with Gen. 39:1, which states that Potiphar bought Joseph from the<br />

Ishmaelites. One problem remains. According to Verse Thirty-six of the present<br />

chapter, it was the Midianites who sold Joseph to Potiphar. In addition we must<br />

ask ourselves why<br />

the Midianites are mentioned in the present verse. So far as<br />

the present author can see, there exist three possible solutions to the problem.<br />

The traditional solution given by<br />

the Rabbis is that the brothers took Joseph<br />

out of the pit and sold him to the Midianites, who in turn sold him to the<br />

Ishmaelites, in which case we are to interpret the present verse as saying that<br />

the brothers sold Joseph to the Ishmaelites via the Midianites, snd thst in Verse<br />

Thirty-six the Midisnites sold Joseph to Potiphsr vis the Ishmselites. The mod<br />

ern solution to the difficulty is to assume that there were originally two texts.<br />

accord-<br />

According to one of them the brothers sold him to the Midianites, but


272 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

ing to the other they<br />

sold him to the Ishmaelites. This position makes the<br />

further assumption that the redactor was careless or stupid.<br />

There is one other possibility which should be exsmined, though it too hss<br />

its difficulties. Since the Midisnite merchsnts sppear right before the words<br />

they drew, the normsl wsy of interpreting<br />

Verse Twenty-eight would be to<br />

sssume<br />

thst it wss the Midisnites who drew Joseph out of the pit snd sold him to<br />

the Ishmaelites. Under this assumption Verse Thirty-six would then be inter<br />

preted as it was by the Rsbbis. This interpretstion would slso sccount for Gen.<br />

42:22, in which Reuben ssys, Spake I not unto you, saying, Do not sin against<br />

the child; and ye would not hear me? Therefore, behold, also is his blood re<br />

quired. Reuben obviously hss in mind whst he hsd said in Verse Twenty-two<br />

of the present chapter, and therefore one would sssume thst he is thinking more<br />

sbout placing Joseph in the pit rather than about selling him into slavery. In<br />

Gen. 42:13 the brothers, thinking of Joseph, merely say And one is not. The<br />

phrase is ambiguous becsuse it could mesn either one is not with us or one no<br />

longer exists, thst is to ssy, he is dead. If the latter interpretation is intended,<br />

this would imply that the brothers did in fact believe that an evil beast found<br />

Joseph in the pit and devoured him. However if the first interpretation is in<br />

tended, no conclusions can be reached. In any case, even after<br />

they hsve fully<br />

repented the brothers never spesk of themselves ss hsving sold Joseph into<br />

slavery.<br />

Taking the Midianites, merchantmen ss the subject of the verb drew would<br />

mske sense if we sssume thst the Midisnites, who were<br />

psssing by, ssw the<br />

brothers put Joseph into the pit snd thst the ssme plsn occurred to them ss<br />

hsd occurred to Judsh.<br />

In the mesntime, since Reuben hsd intended to return to the pit secretly in<br />

order to free Joseph, it is more thsn likely<br />

in such a way<br />

thst he would have arranged matters<br />

thst their meal would have taken plsce st some distsnce from<br />

the pit, sllowing him to relesse Joseph without being noticed.<br />

This explsnstion would slso sccount for the fsct thst even sfter<br />

they repent<br />

the brothers never sdmit to selling<br />

Joseph. If it wss the Midisnites who took<br />

Joseph out of the pit then it is more thsn likely that the brothers believed their<br />

own story about the wild animal. Because of Verse Thirty-six many<br />

of the<br />

ancient commentaries assumed that the Ishmaelites bought Joseph from the<br />

brothers and then sold him to the Midianites. This assumption mskes more<br />

sense thsn the modern sssumption of s corruption in the text, but it, too, is<br />

unnecesssry, ss we have seen. One need only<br />

assume that in Verse Thirty-six<br />

the author means that the Midianites sold Joseph into Egypt indirectly by sell<br />

ing him to the Ishmaelites.<br />

The difficulty with this interpretation lies in Chapter Forty-five, Verses Four<br />

and Five, in which Joseph clearly speaks of his brothers as<br />

having<br />

into Egypt. Two possibilities remain. If Joseph's statement is to be taken lit<br />

sold him<br />

erally, one must reject the present hypothesis, in which case one is left with


The Lion and the Ass 273<br />

the ambiguities in the present verse, in which the subject of the verb drew<br />

seems to be the Midisnites. The other possibility<br />

will be discussed in the<br />

commentsry<br />

to Gen. 45:3.<br />

Although there msy be no clesr wsy of solving the present difficulty, several<br />

other notions present themselves for our consideration. No mstter how one<br />

resds the present chspter it seems to be importsnt to the suthor thst the Mid<br />

isnites were present snd were thus swsre of the internsl conflicts within Israel.<br />

This msy in part account for their lster actions. On the other hand, since the<br />

Ishmaelites are so rarely mentioned in the Bible one feels obliged to give an<br />

account of their presence. It may be that the author wished to connect Joseph's<br />

journey over desert country<br />

with the wild ass.<br />

29. and reuben returned unto the pit; and, behold, joseph was not<br />

in the pit; and he rent his clothes.<br />

30. and he returned unto his brethren, and said, the child is not;<br />

and i, whither shall i go?<br />

31. and they took joseph's coat, and killed a kid of the goats, and<br />

dipped the coat in the blood;<br />

32. and they sent the coat of many colours,<br />

and they brought it<br />

to their father; and said, this have we found: recognize i pray you<br />

whether it be thy son's coat or no.<br />

33. and he recognized it, and said it is my son's coat; an evil beast<br />

hath devoured him; joseph is without doubt rent in pieces.<br />

34. and jacob rent his clothes, and put sackcloth upon his loins,<br />

and mourned for his son many days.<br />

35. and all his sons and all his daughters rose up to comfort<br />

him; but he refused to be comforted: and he said, for i will go<br />

down into the grave unto my son mourning. thus his father wept<br />

FOR HIM.<br />

After having heard Judsh, the brothers csnnot sctuslly bring<br />

tell the lie in speech, but Jscob draws the ssme conclusion<br />

devoured him.<br />

themselves to<br />

an evil beast hath<br />

It is difficult to know whst Jacob meant by the words evil beast. After God<br />

presented the plan for the Jubilee Year on which so much depended, He said<br />

the following:<br />

And I will give peace in the land and ye shall lie down, and none shall make you<br />

afraid: and I will rid evil beasts out of the land, neither shall the sword go through<br />

your land. (Lev. 26:6)<br />

Ezekiel hss Leviticus in mind when he ssys:<br />

Therefore will I save my flock, and they shall no more be a prey: and I willjudge<br />

between cattle and cattle. And I will set up one shepherd over them, and he shall<br />

feed them, even David; he shallfeed them, and he shall be their shepherd. And I the


274 <strong>Interpretation</strong><br />

Lord will be their God. And my<br />

servant David a prince among them; I the Lord have<br />

spoken it. And I will make with them a covenant<br />

ofpeace, and will cause the evil<br />

beasts to cease out of the land; and they shall dwell safely in the wilderness, and<br />

sleep in the woods. (Ez. 34:22-25)<br />

Ezekiel'<br />

s comment seems to be right<br />

the evil beasts sre men. Jscob in this<br />

verse is slso thinking of men snd only hopes the evil beasts will be quieted.<br />

Verse Thirty-five is full of strange psssions. The fsther will not be comforted<br />

becsuse he believes thst his comforters sre slso the murderers. The sons wish<br />

to comfort becsuse they sre not sure in whst wsy they sre guilty<br />

wsy they are innocent. The story is further complicated by<br />

brothers may now believe their own lie.<br />

snd in whst<br />

the fact that the<br />

36. AND THE MIDIANITES SOLD HIM INTO EGYPT UNTO POTIPHAR, AN OFFICER<br />

OF PHARAOH'S AND CAPTAIN OF THE GUARD.<br />

The last verse of Chapter Thirty-seven begins life again in Egypt. It has s<br />

double function. Not only does it sssure us thst we will hesr more of Joseph,<br />

but it will slso force us to see Chapter Thirty-eight as part of the Joseph<br />

story.


Thumos''<br />

Forthcoming Articles<br />

Barbara Tovey<br />

Anne M. Cohler<br />

A. Anthony Smith<br />

Robert Sscks<br />

Robert L. Stone<br />

Shskespesre's Apology for Imitstive Poetry: The<br />

Tempest snd The Republic<br />

Montesquieu's Perception of his Audience for The<br />

Spirit of the Laws<br />

Ethics snd Politics in the World of Jurgen Hsbermss<br />

The Lion snd the Ass: s<br />

Commentsry<br />

Genesis (Chspters 38-39)<br />

Index to <strong>Interpretation</strong>, Volumes 1-10<br />

on the Book of<br />

Discussion<br />

Thomss West<br />

Response to Stewart Umphrey's "Eros and<br />

Reviews<br />

Michsel A. Gillespie<br />

Heidegger'<br />

s<br />

"Being and Time" and the Possibility of<br />

Political Philosophy by<br />

Mark Blitz<br />

Short Notices<br />

Will Morrisey<br />

Rousseau's Emile<br />

Introduction, Translation and<br />

Notes by Allan Bloom; Rousseau's Reveries<br />

Translation, Preface, Notes and Interpretive Essay<br />

by Charles E. Butterworth; Plato's "Phaedrus" by<br />

Ronna Burger; The Political Philosophy of the<br />

Frankfurt School by George Friedman; Aristotle on<br />

Political Reasoning by Larry Arnhart


ISSN 0020-9635

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!