Prace komisji nauk.pdf - Instytut Filologii Angielskiej Uniwersytetu ...

Prace komisji nauk.pdf - Instytut Filologii Angielskiej Uniwersytetu ... Prace komisji nauk.pdf - Instytut Filologii Angielskiej Uniwersytetu ...

ifa.uni.wroc.pl
from ifa.uni.wroc.pl More from this publisher
08.02.2014 Views

Whereas, this traditional and simple description of the term predicate seem may appear faulty, especially after introducing theta roles into our discussion. The revised definition may be that predicate is a part of the predicate-argument structure in which some property (predicate) is ascribed to an individual (argument), where the property is a kind of theta role assigned by the predicate to the argument. Thus, in the structure She is happy in which the property (being happy) is ascribed to an individual (she). It may be clearly seen that the linking verb be in She is happy does not participate in assigning the theta role to the subject She because it cannot exist alone without an adjective. Note that the sentence (6) is void because there is not an adjective placed after the verb be. (6) *She is. Sentence (6) can only exist as an implicit complement in the structure (7): (7) He is not happy, but she is. The verb be cannot be considered as a theta role assigner because there is not any uniformity in the type of the theta role borne by the subject NPs, although there is a grammatical agreement between it and inflectional forms of be. In the sentences (8) – (12) the NP subject bear different theta roles: (8) We were angry. - Experiencer (9) They were robbed. - Patient (10) She is unlikely to win the competition. - Agent (11) They were given an apple. - Recipient (12) He was sure to achieve a win-win solution. - Benefective In the examples above the linking verb be is followed by adjectives or participial passive verbs. On the ground that the NPs subject borne different theta roles we may conclude that be does not determine them. It is only responsible for carrying a given theta role from the phrase following be to the subject of the sentence. This 182

characteristic of be has important implication for the rest of our reasoning because it give us the possibility to claim that it does not constitute a part of a predicate. Predicate is not formed by be (or its inflectional forms) and an adjective phrase but only by the adjective phrase. The argument-predicate relation of the sentence (8) is provided by (13): (13) EXPERIENCER(we) angry However, this analysis is incomplete without pointing out the exact position of the NP inside the whole adjective phrase. To be more precise it does not inform us whether the NP takes the place of external or internal argument. There is visible difference between both kinds of arguments. It is worth noticing that internal arguments receive their theta roles within the immediate expansion of the category of the predicate, whereas external arguments get their theta roles indirectly, what means that their theta role assigner is located outside the immediate expansion of the category of the predicate, however, it is still placed inside the maximal expansion of the category of the predicate. Taking into consideration the position of NP - external argument in verb phrases, we may conclude that the position of specifier inside adjective phrases is also occupied by NP. It thus appears that it must be an external argument of the whole phrase. Above-mentioned claim can be justified by analyzing sentences (14) and (15): (14) They were disappointed. (15) They like their children. In sentence (14) the relation between the external predicate they and predicate disappointed is exactly the same as the relation of they to like their children in (15). This similarity is visible in (16) and (17) in which internal positions of subjects are represented: 183

characteristic of be has important implication for the rest of our reasoning because<br />

it give us the possibility to claim that it does not constitute a part of a predicate.<br />

Predicate is not formed by be (or its inflectional forms) and an adjective phrase but<br />

only by the adjective phrase. The argument-predicate relation of the sentence (8) is<br />

provided by (13):<br />

(13) EXPERIENCER(we) angry<br />

However, this analysis is incomplete without pointing out the exact position<br />

of the NP inside the whole adjective phrase. To be more precise it does not inform<br />

us whether the NP takes the place of external or internal argument. There is visible<br />

difference between both kinds of arguments. It is worth noticing that internal<br />

arguments receive their theta roles within the immediate expansion of the category<br />

of the predicate, whereas external arguments get their theta roles indirectly, what<br />

means that their theta role assigner is located outside the immediate expansion of<br />

the category of the predicate, however, it is still placed inside the maximal<br />

expansion of the category of the predicate. Taking into consideration the position of<br />

NP - external argument in verb phrases, we may conclude that the position of<br />

specifier inside adjective phrases is also occupied by NP. It thus appears that it<br />

must be an external argument of the whole phrase. Above-mentioned claim can be<br />

justified by analyzing sentences (14) and (15):<br />

(14) They were disappointed.<br />

(15) They like their children.<br />

In sentence (14) the relation between the external predicate they and predicate<br />

disappointed is exactly the same as the relation of they to like their children in (15).<br />

This similarity is visible in (16) and (17) in which internal positions of subjects are<br />

represented:<br />

183

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!