17.01.2014 Views

Catherine's essay - Cardiff University

Catherine's essay - Cardiff University

Catherine's essay - Cardiff University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Where Are The Women?<br />

Are women systematically excluded from the political process?<br />

The relationship between feminism and the political process is one that is intricate, multifaceted<br />

and often fraught (Squires, 2006). Despite sharing similar preoccupations – that of<br />

rights, of representation and of participation – feminist scholars maintain that access to<br />

participatory, liberal democracy remains restricted for large percentages of the population<br />

(Phillips, 1991). Although the degree to which this is true varies, it is acknowledged that<br />

globally, women do not participate politically to the same extent as men (Kittilson and<br />

Schwindt-Bayer, 2012). Whilst the breadth of this discourse is too large to include within one<br />

<strong>essay</strong>, it is possible to identify a trend from the deconstruction of this phenomenon. This<br />

trend is deftly summed up by feminist theorists Susan Bourque and Jean Grossholtz:<br />

“The politics is a man’s world is a familiar adage; that political science as a discipline<br />

tends to keep it that way is less well accepted, but perhaps closer to the truth.”<br />

(Bourque and Grossholtz, 1974, cited by Phillips 2001, pp. 225)<br />

This <strong>essay</strong> will examine the validity of the claim that women are misrepresented within<br />

political theory and, as a result, marginalised in the political process.<br />

That politics is primarily regarded as a ‘male’ pursuit is widely recognised within academic<br />

literature. Heather Savigny and Lee Marsden (2011) explain that certain traits are valued by<br />

Western political culture: rationality, calculation, aggression, autonomy and leadership. In<br />

order to participate in political leadership, one must display these qualities regardless of<br />

whether one is male or female. However, they emphasise that the characteristics synonymous<br />

with political leadership are also those that are regarded as ‘male.’ Traits such as dominance,<br />

decisiveness and shrewdness stand diametrically opposed to the more ‘female’ traits such as<br />

passivity, sensitivity and nurturing.<br />

This construction of masculinity and femininity is a crucial point. Judith Butler (1990) neatly<br />

describes this in her book Gender Trouble, explaining that whilst one’s sex has certain fixed<br />

characteristics, the construction of one’s gender – how ‘male’ one is or how ‘female’ one is –<br />

is a social construct that is independent of biological constraint. The wider ramifications of<br />

this are also impossible to contain within one <strong>essay</strong>. They are included here as a means by<br />

which to frame Savigny and Marsden’s explanation of political behaviour. In order to<br />

participate in political leadership, women must cast off their constructed femininity and adopt<br />

a more masculine persona. Douglas Ponton (2010) considers the case of Margaret Thatcher.


He argues that she adopted strategies to accentuate her physical femininity, such as her<br />

hairstyle. However, her manner, her persona and even her speaking voice were carefully<br />

constructed to take on a more ‘masculine’ identity.<br />

The propagation of gendered behaviour traits is a keystone for Simone de Beauvoir’s theories<br />

regarding power and gender identity. In The Second Sex (1949), Beauvoir describes how<br />

women have been systematically constructed as secondary to male dominance – the ‘Other’<br />

as she describes it. By virtue of biology and historical materialism and aided by contributions<br />

from the arts, literature, science and politics, Beauvoir argues that being ‘male’ has been<br />

established as the norm, and as the ideal. As a logical progression, ‘female’ can only exist in<br />

relation to this and is therefore secondary. This is an assumption that can be traced back to<br />

the political philosophy of Aristotle, widely regarded as the foundation of Western political<br />

culture (Green, 1993).<br />

The consequences of this are explained by Gayle Leatherby (2003). This construction of the<br />

female as ‘the Other’ is exacerbated by a society built on a posteriori knowledge acquired by<br />

men, leading to a patriarchy, by which we mean the assumption that masculinity is more<br />

suited to the task than femininity, within all academic areas of the arts, media, literature,<br />

science and social sciences. Rosi Braidotti (2003) claims that in exposing the construction of<br />

women as ‘the Other,’ Beauvoir has exposed the fallacy that the accepted philosophical<br />

thinking is universal. She demonstrates that what is considered the norm is in fact patriarchal.<br />

Beauvoir was not the first to examine this form of patriarchy. In his work The Subjection of<br />

Women (1896), John Stuart Mill not only acknowledges the presence of patriarchal structures,<br />

but describes them as a legal subordination that is reprehensible. Mill posits that equilibrium<br />

between men and women exists in theory alone. It has never been put into practice. Since<br />

patriarchal society remains uncontested, it logically follows that patriarchy as the ideal is<br />

nothing but a theory and is not based on reasoned debate or argument. He asserts that<br />

patriarchy is the natural result of the law of force, in which physical strength equates to<br />

power. Mill argues that, if this is so, it is not only an assault on reason but as distasteful as<br />

slavery and as racism. The assumption that certain people cannot do certain things is one that<br />

is fallible and “if we accept this, we ought to act as if we believe it” (p.225).<br />

Feminism and politics remain separate, if interlinking, disciplines. Kristie McLure (1992)<br />

acknowledges that feminism has failed to produce a proliferation of opportunities for women


in male-dominated areas. She explains this by stating that, within the discipline of political<br />

science, ‘feminism’ indicates an interest in the divergence between the accepted genders. It<br />

does not, in itself, point to a singular struggle or acknowledge the wide array of perspectives<br />

that have since opened up. Jane Sawicki (1991) explains that it is insufficient to ask “What do<br />

women want?” as this question encapsulates a diverse set of intersections between race, class,<br />

age and culture. As Valerie Bryson (1992) puts it, whilst alienation is experienced on all<br />

political levels, it is unsatisfactory to compare the alienation experienced by liberated, white<br />

American women with the alienation experienced by disenfranchised black American<br />

women. This is a level of inequality that is not necessarily included in political research.<br />

Bourque and Grossholtz (1974) frame the argument thusly: that the undertaking of data<br />

analysis by predominantly white, affluent males has resulted in political activity consequently<br />

taking on a persona that reflects a Western social construction of masculinity. This is turn has<br />

grouped all other marginalised persons together and concludes that they are politically<br />

disempowered of their own volition. They examine three studies regarded as seminal and<br />

quoted widely (These being The American Voter, Angus Campbell et al; The Civic Culture,<br />

Gabriel Almond and Sidney Verba; and Political Life, Robert Lane.) These were contrasted<br />

with research articles authored by female researchers that were found to have a different<br />

perspective. Incidentally, the female researchers were found to have greater realist or<br />

normative perceptions. This is, however, incidental, and the conclusion is drawn that the<br />

political scientist cannot help but allow their world view to influence the conclusions that<br />

they draw. Elizabeth Meehan (1986) acknowledges that the discipline is dependent upon the<br />

knowledge that we have acquired. However, for it to be truly useful, it must inclusive.<br />

The same findings were affirmed by Sue Tolleson-Rhinehart and Susan Carroll (2006), who<br />

found that not only does political science support the gendering of political attitudes, but that<br />

this has a detrimental effect upon the research conducted. In a historical overview of the<br />

emergence of political science as a discipline, they found that assumptions such as ‘men are<br />

political and women are not’ prevailed, and that this in turn left political science ill-equipped<br />

to deal with emerging issues, gender parity being one of them.<br />

Feminist theorist Carole Pateman claims that this assumption that men are political and<br />

women are not is linked to the exercising of power in both public and the private spheres. She<br />

posits that the Western social construction of gender roles has meant that masculinity is<br />

largely played out in the public sphere whereas femininity is more confined to the private


arena (Pateman, 1976; Pateman and Mills, 1988; Pateman and Mills, 2007). As politics is<br />

also conducted in the public arena, it is a natural conclusion that politics is perceived as a<br />

masculine pursuit, with women represented by their association with men. Furthermore, in<br />

maintaining this public/private dichotomy, politics intrinsically excludes the interests of<br />

women (Pateman and Mills, 1988). Amy Caiazza (1997) discusses this in depth and<br />

concludes that if feminism is ignored as political theory, then politics cannot be truly<br />

understood. For Savigny and Marsden (2011) this issue of gendering holds the key for<br />

explaining the divide between political science and feminism. They claim that feminism<br />

rejects traditional constructs of gender on many levels whether this is a post-colonial<br />

rejection of ‘female’ as a non-classed, non-racial asexualised group or the challenges issued<br />

by post-modernists and constructivists to traditional notions of gender roles (Savigny and<br />

Marsden, 2011).<br />

The execution of power is perhaps worth exploring at this juncture. The concept of power as<br />

a hierarchical structure was reconceptualised by Michel Foucault, who theorised that power is<br />

displayed and executed in all relationships (Foucault, cited by Lynch 2011). Lynch explains<br />

that for Foucault, power must be understood as a force born of struggles, confrontations and<br />

transformations. It is upheld by support systems and the schema in which they take effect. In<br />

his work Panopticisim, Foucault hypothesised that political power is exercised by each<br />

individual through the very smallest of actions, all of which work together to create<br />

discourse. So, for Foucault, the male-gendering of political research is a result of a power<br />

struggle that renders women inadequate for politics. Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz<br />

(1962) develop this concept to hypothesise that the hierarchies and power exercised within<br />

social sciences are cyclical, that they feed into one another and thereby political science<br />

remains largely separate to developments made in feminism.<br />

This is not to say however that it remains so. Raewyn Connell (2006) acknowledges that,<br />

whilst feminism’s initial complaint that social science was gender-ignorant was valid,<br />

sufficient progress has been made for the state of patriarchy to be re-valued. Sharon Krause<br />

(2011) concurs, stating that the field of social science has diversified greatly as a result of<br />

feminisms and that this has led to an expansion of our understanding. Lynne Segal (1999)<br />

advises that, just as feminism has diversified, we should allow this diversification to filter<br />

into all fields of social sciences. There is certainly some evidence to suggest that, whilst


women still fail to hold the highest positions available within academia, more women are<br />

publishing academic articles (Evans and Bucy, 2010).<br />

The theory that diversification is required for effective research has led to a field of study<br />

known as ‘intersectionality.’ Cho et al (2013) explain that Intersectionality Studies examines<br />

the dynamics of difference. It emerged as a response to the criticisms of feminist and antiracist<br />

scholars, as a method to counter the singular thinking that has prevailed within social<br />

scientific research. Walby et al (2012) give a detailed history of its emergence as a field of<br />

study, citing key theorists such as Kimberlé Crenshaw, Leslie McCall and Ange-Marie<br />

Hancock. For example, Crenshaw argued that not only is it inadequate to assume that the<br />

concerns of a white American male are comparable to those of a black American female, but<br />

that the experiences of those women can be negated by the inaction of anti-racism and<br />

feminism. For Crenshaw, then, considering all people to be of race, class, gender, sexuality<br />

and history is part of the ethical considerations of any effective social scientific researcher.<br />

Of course, this approach is not without limitation. McCall (2005, cited by Walby et al 2012)<br />

warns that the preference for fluidity over rigid categories makes data analysis difficult and<br />

threatens to destabilize the quality of the research. Indeed, inclusivity presents a great deal of<br />

problems, to both the research design and the structure of analysis (Walby, et al 2012).<br />

However, these problems are not insurmountable. Elizabeth Cole (2009) reminds us that<br />

translating the theory of intersectionality into practice does not require a new set of methods,<br />

but rather a restructuring of the methods already in use so that they can incorporate<br />

inclusivity in order to improve research. Intersectionality allowed Deborah Schultz (2012) to<br />

examine the Romani-Gadže Feminist Alliance activity in its multi-cultural entirety and learn<br />

some valuable lessons on the manner in which feminists in the Balkan states are combatting<br />

issues such as ethnic hatred, violence against women and extreme social exclusion. Similarly,<br />

it has allowed Gina Miranda Samuels and Fariyal Ross-Sheriff (2008) to study the<br />

internalised notions of femininity as shaped by societal attitudes, by studying the political<br />

empowerment of Afghan women at home in Afghanistan as compared to Afghan women as<br />

refugees in Pakistan. These are two examples of a stable research design that demonstrate the<br />

fluidity that an intersectional approach allows.<br />

In conclusion, the gender identities currently accepted within our societies are social<br />

constructs that dictate the way we are expected to conduct ourselves. We have introduced the<br />

theory that politics has also been constructed as a ‘male’ pursuit and not suitable to a ‘female’


temperament. We also briefly examined the idea that the researcher is inherently affected by<br />

their personal experiences and that this, in turn, affects the quality of the research. However,<br />

the advances made by feminism have done little to improve the ratio of men and women<br />

working in political research. This is supposed to be a result of the fact that feminism has<br />

thrown wide the net of diversity and that the methods currently in use must be adapted in<br />

order to be inclusive. If we fail to recognise each research subject as a racial, gendered,<br />

classed and sexual being, we invalidate our research and ultimately propagate assumptions of<br />

gender bias, sexism, racism and class conflict.


REFERENCES<br />

Bachrach, P. and Baratz, M. S. (1962) Two Faces of Power. The American Political Science<br />

Review 56(7) pp.947 - 952<br />

Bourque, S. C. and Grossholtz, J. (1974) Politics an Unnatural Practice: Political Science<br />

Looks at Female Participation. Politics and Society 4(2) pp. 225 – 266<br />

Braidotti, R. (2003) Feminist Philosophies. In: Eagelton, M. (ed.) (2003) A Concise<br />

Companion to Feminist Theory. Oxford: Blackwell<br />

Bryson, V. (1992) Feminist Political Theory: An Introduction. Hampshire: Macmillan<br />

Butler, J. (1990) Gender Trouble. In: Gould, C. (1997) Key Concepts in Critical Theory:<br />

Gender. New York: Humanity Books<br />

Caiazza, A. (1997) Inclusion and Exclusion: Feminism’s Relationship with Political Science.<br />

Southeastern Political Review 25(4) pp. 659 – 683)<br />

Cho, S., Williams – Crenshaw, K., McCall, L. (2013) Toward a Field of Intersectionality<br />

Studies: Theory, Applications and Praxis. Signs 38(4) pp. 785 – 810<br />

Cole, E.R. (2009) Intersectionality and Research in Psychology. American Psychologist 64(3)<br />

pp. 170 - 180<br />

Connell, R. W. (2006) Gender and the State. In: Nash, K. and Scott, A. (eds.) (2006) The<br />

Blackwell Companion to Political Sociology. Oxford: Blackwell<br />

Evans, H. K. and Bucy, E. P. (2010) The Representation of Women in Publication: An<br />

Analysis of Political Communication and the International Journal of Press/Politics. Political<br />

Science and Politics 43(2) pp. 295 - 301<br />

Green, P. (1993) Hellenistic Theory and Culture. California: <strong>University</strong> of California Press<br />

Kittilson, M. C. and Schwindt-Bayer, L.A. (2012) The Gendered Effects of Electoral<br />

Insititutions: Political Engagement and Participation. Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong> Press<br />

Krause, S. R. (2011) Contested Questions, Current Trajectories: Feminism in Political Theory<br />

Today. Politics and Gender 7(1) pp. 105 - 111<br />

Leatherby, G. (2003) Feminist Research in Theory and Practice. Oxford: Oxford <strong>University</strong><br />

Press<br />

McLure, K. (1992) The Issue of Foundations: Scientized Politics, Politicised Science and<br />

Feminist Critical Practice. In: Butler, J. and Scott, J.W. (eds.) Feminists Theorize the<br />

Political. London: Routledge


Lynch, R. A. Foucault’s Theory of Power. In: Taylor, D. (ed.) Michel Foucault: Key<br />

Concepts (2011) Durham: Acumen<br />

Meehan, E. (1986) Women’s Studies and Political Studies. In: Evans, J. et al (Eds.) (1986)<br />

Feminism and Political Theory. London; California; New Delhi: SAGE<br />

Mill, J. S. (1869) The Subjection of Women. New York: Prometheus Books<br />

Pateman, C. (1976) Participation and Democratic Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge <strong>University</strong><br />

Press<br />

Pateman, C. and Mills, C. (1988) The Sexual Contract. California: Stanford <strong>University</strong> Press<br />

Pateman, C. and Mills, C. (2007) Contract and Domination. Cambridge: Polity Press<br />

Phillips, A. (1991) Engendering Democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press<br />

Ponton, D. M. (2010) The Female Political Leader: A Study of Gender Identity in the case of<br />

Margaret Thatcher. Journal of Language and Power. 9(2) pp. 195 – 218<br />

Samuels, G. M. and Ross-Sheriff, F. (2008) Identity, Oppression and Power: Feminisms and<br />

Intersectionality Theory. Journal of Women and Social Work 23(1) pp. 5 - 9<br />

Sawicki, J. (1991) Foucault and Feminism: Towards a Politics of difference. In: Shenley,<br />

M.L. and Pateman, C. (eds.) Feminist Interpretations and Political Theory. Cambridge:<br />

Polity Press<br />

Savigny, H. and Marsden, L. (2011) Doing Political Science and International Relations.<br />

Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan<br />

Schultz, D. L. (2012) Translating Intersectionality Theory into Practice: A Tale of Romani-<br />

Gadže Feminist Alliance. Signs 38(1) pp. 37- 43<br />

Segal, L. (1999) Why Feminism? Oxford: Polity Press<br />

Squires, J. (2006) Feminism and Democracy. In: Nash, K. and Scott, A. (2006) The Blackwell<br />

Companion to Political Sociology. Oxford: Blackwell<br />

Tolleson-Rhinehart, S and Carroll, S.J. (2006) “Far From Ideal:” The Gender Politics of<br />

Political Science. The American Political Science Review 100(4) pp. 507 – 513


Walby, S., Armstrong, J. and Strid, S. (2012) Intersectionality: Multiple Inequalities in Social<br />

Theory. Sociology 46(2) 224 - 240

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!