27.12.2013 Views

1 Theorising Agency in International Relations In Hobbes's Wake ...

1 Theorising Agency in International Relations In Hobbes's Wake ...

1 Theorising Agency in International Relations In Hobbes's Wake ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

2001). As the seat of human agency, the <strong>in</strong>dividual has attracted <strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>g attention from IR scholars;<br />

either as, on the one hand, the bearer of rationality (Greenhill 2008, Mercer 2005), or, on the other, as<br />

the site of non-rational yet politically salient phenomena such as emotions (Ross 2006) and their<br />

associated array of identities (Smith 2004; F<strong>in</strong>nemore and Sikk<strong>in</strong>k 2001, Lapid and Kratochwil 1996) and<br />

cultures (Lebow 2008, Jahn 2000; Katzenste<strong>in</strong> 1996).<br />

<strong>In</strong> this article the Hobbesian legacy provides the start<strong>in</strong>g place from which to exam<strong>in</strong>e the<br />

models of the <strong>in</strong>dividual that implicitly or explicitly <strong>in</strong>forms accounts of <strong>in</strong>ternational politics. The<br />

rationalist-reflectivist divide <strong>in</strong> contemporary IR scholarship (Keohane 1988) rests upon divergent<br />

conceptions of the <strong>in</strong>dividual, <strong>in</strong>sofar as the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for reflectivist or, as it has come to be known,<br />

constructivist theoris<strong>in</strong>g was the realisation of the need to unpack the rationalist assumption that actors<br />

are ‘self-<strong>in</strong>terested’, as Alexander Wendt (1999, 215) put it, <strong>in</strong> order to exam<strong>in</strong>e who that self might be.<br />

This is what ushered <strong>in</strong> the concept of the self <strong>in</strong> the appraisal of agency, and the concept of identity for<br />

IR scholarship more broadly. The start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts for my enquiry are thus the rational actor and the self,<br />

the two archetypal <strong>in</strong>dividuals that ground rationalist and constructivist enquiries respectively.<br />

My purpose is to f<strong>in</strong>d a model of the <strong>in</strong>dividual that can provide the foundations for a non<strong>in</strong>dividualist<br />

basis for apprehend<strong>in</strong>g agency <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics; one that is rid of what Wendt (1999,<br />

178) himself termed a ‘rump <strong>in</strong>dividualism’ that cuts across both the rational actor and the self. A third<br />

model is afforded, I suggest, by the concept of the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject socially embedded <strong>in</strong> language that<br />

lies at the core of discourse theory. 3 Vis-à-vis constructivism, the issue is one of ontological consistency<br />

3 Discourse theory comprises three ma<strong>in</strong>, closely connected, components. First, it foregrounds language<br />

as the elementary social bond and consequently, second, a key site of political analysis. It is thus<br />

associated a wide range of methods regrouped under the head<strong>in</strong>g of ‘discourse analyses’ that focus<br />

upon the role of language <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics, which have been extensively elaborated elsewhere<br />

(Epste<strong>in</strong> 2008, Hansen 2006, Bially Mattern 2005, Milliken 1999). What is still lack<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> IR, however, is a<br />

theoretical demonstration of, not just how, but why language centrally matters to the understand<strong>in</strong>g<br />

2


with regards to its own found<strong>in</strong>g project to open up the enquiry <strong>in</strong>to the mutual constitution of the<br />

actors and the structures of <strong>in</strong>ternational politics. My concern, then, is to f<strong>in</strong>d a different basis for a<br />

social theoris<strong>in</strong>g about <strong>in</strong>ternational politics that unravels <strong>in</strong> full the central constructivist <strong>in</strong>sight that<br />

the dist<strong>in</strong>ctness of the social world, as opposed to the natural world, resides <strong>in</strong> that processes of social<br />

construction do <strong>in</strong> fact run, to paraphrase Wendt’s phrase (1999, 92) but where he would not venture,<br />

all the way down. 4 Alexander Wendt’s (1999) foundational effort to elaborate the first comprehensive<br />

social theory for the discipl<strong>in</strong>e, whose role <strong>in</strong> legitimiz<strong>in</strong>g the constructivist research programme cannot<br />

be underestimated, nonetheless harbours a fundamental tension, that h<strong>in</strong>ges on the dist<strong>in</strong>ction<br />

between agency and identity. <strong>In</strong>deed Wendt extensively demonstrates that actors are socially<br />

constructed rather than simply given, as they are <strong>in</strong> rationalist accounts. Yet, build<strong>in</strong>g here on a critique<br />

that has been extensively developed elsewhere (Epste<strong>in</strong> 2010, Neumann 2004, Zehfuss 2001, Lynn Doty<br />

2000, Smith 2000), he also holds off from the very constitutive logic he elaborates <strong>in</strong> the process of<br />

do<strong>in</strong>g so a pre-given, un-constructed self, posited as the seat of identity; and as the site where to<br />

relegate his rump <strong>in</strong>dividualism. <strong>In</strong> other words, the very concept that constructivism so fruitfully<br />

ushered <strong>in</strong>to IR scholarship, identity, is cordoned off from the onset from enquiries <strong>in</strong>to its own social<br />

construction. The tension thus stems from hav<strong>in</strong>g split a priori the actor from the <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong><br />

elaborat<strong>in</strong>g constructivism’s central concept of the self, and leav<strong>in</strong>g that splitt<strong>in</strong>g un-theorised. The<br />

concept of the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject, which theorises the splitt<strong>in</strong>g, addresses that gap. <strong>In</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so it lays the<br />

agency <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics. Thirdly the model of the <strong>in</strong>dividual it harbours is the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject.<br />

(for an extensive development see Howarth 2000).<br />

4 To clarify a common confusion regard<strong>in</strong>g discursive approaches, the pert<strong>in</strong>ent dist<strong>in</strong>ction for social<br />

scientific enquiry is not, notwithstand<strong>in</strong>g the central role it <strong>in</strong>itially played (via Max Weber) <strong>in</strong> found<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the social sciences, between materialism and idealism (see also Parsons 2006, Bially Mattern 2005 and<br />

Epste<strong>in</strong> 2008 for extensive developments). The key import of the social constructionist <strong>in</strong>sight is that it<br />

is, rather, between the (constructed) social and the (given) natural world. Social structures for their part<br />

are both material and immaterial (only even material social structures are constructed through human<br />

<strong>in</strong>teraction rather than given). Importantly, the study of these two types of social structures is<br />

complementary rather than mutually exclusive.<br />

3


foundation for elaborat<strong>in</strong>g a type of social theoris<strong>in</strong>g that eschews <strong>in</strong>dividualism <strong>in</strong> its apprehension of<br />

agency.<br />

The Hobbesian legacy is important to this task for two sets of reasons. First, Hobbes’ state of<br />

nature is the traditional found<strong>in</strong>g myth for the rational actor. It thus provides the start<strong>in</strong>g place for<br />

engag<strong>in</strong>g with IR’s historically prior and explicitly <strong>in</strong>dividualist model of agency. Yet the critique of these<br />

realist and rationalist appropriations of Hobbes, while important, is not new. Hobbes’ political myth is<br />

important, second, because of what it actually tells us about the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s make up. Ever s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

Sigmund Freud’s discovery of the unconscious and the birth of psychoanalysis, myths have played a<br />

central role <strong>in</strong> reveal<strong>in</strong>g collective unconscious structures; for example the myth of Oedipus. Moreover,<br />

the socially embedded <strong>in</strong>dividual is the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g object of psychoanalytic theory. Centr<strong>in</strong>g my analysis on<br />

The Leviathan I show how, with regards to the <strong>in</strong>dividual, Thomas Hobbes and Jacques Lacan, who<br />

largely furthers Freud’s discoveries, proceed down surpris<strong>in</strong>gly similar paths. Acknowledg<strong>in</strong>g this not<br />

only furthers IR theory’s understand<strong>in</strong>g of Hobbes, but enables it to better mobilise Hobbesian <strong>in</strong>sights<br />

regard<strong>in</strong>g agency. Hence strange bedfellows though they may seem at first sight, the theories of Hobbes<br />

and Lacan illum<strong>in</strong>ate one other, the former provid<strong>in</strong>g a narrative illustrat<strong>in</strong>g the relevance of Lacan’s<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g of the structure of the human psyche for political analysis at large, the latter draw<strong>in</strong>g out<br />

how Hobbes’s formulation of the problem of political order reaches deep <strong>in</strong>to the work<strong>in</strong>gs of the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual psyche. <strong>In</strong> engag<strong>in</strong>g with Hobbes’s legacy <strong>in</strong> IR my aim is thus to reveal the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject<br />

that lies buried away <strong>in</strong> IR’s own foundations and how it can help to understand<strong>in</strong>g agency <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong>in</strong>ternational politics.<br />

The article is developed <strong>in</strong> four parts. <strong>In</strong> order to locate my argument I beg<strong>in</strong> by mapp<strong>in</strong>g out the<br />

trajectory of the discipl<strong>in</strong>e’s development under the prism of its relationship to Hobbes, which has<br />

4


evolved largely around the state of nature. 5<br />

I show how, on the one hand, the Hobbesian state of<br />

nature was the site of convergence of realism and rational choice theory that yielded the strong<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividualism characteristic of rationalist approaches. On the other hand it was also the battleground for<br />

efforts to reclaim Hobbes, which have drawn out his own emphasis on sociality and language. I also<br />

show how, notwithstand<strong>in</strong>g the school’s explicit departure from the so-called Hobbesian approaches,<br />

Hobbes’ legacy implicitly resurfaces <strong>in</strong> constructivist efforts to theorise the actor’s ‘self’, where the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual still largely rema<strong>in</strong>s the exemplar for expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g state behaviour. <strong>In</strong> clos<strong>in</strong>g, Carl Schmitt’s<br />

(2008) recently translated analysis of Hobbes’s treatise, which casts the focus upon Leviathan as a<br />

symbol, provides a useful bridge between, on the one hand, IR and political theory, and on the other,<br />

given his relations with realist thought, between a realist-rationalist and a more l<strong>in</strong>guistically-m<strong>in</strong>ded<br />

read<strong>in</strong>g of Hobbes.<br />

The second part of the paper <strong>in</strong>troduces the Lacanian conceptual battery around two key<br />

features of Lacan’s thought, the primacy of the signifier and the category of the symbolic. The latter<br />

concept establishes the two pillars upon which the argument itself subsequently turns, the collective<br />

and the <strong>in</strong>dividual levels. The first movement of the argument itself, which concerns the function of the<br />

symbol of the Leviathan at the collective level, is then developed <strong>in</strong> the third part of the paper. I show<br />

how what the Leviathan designates is the symbolic order at large, that is, the matrix underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g<br />

organized political life. <strong>In</strong> this light, the formulation of the problem of political order that is relevant to<br />

theoris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ter-state relations is to be found, I suggest, not <strong>in</strong> the state of nature, but <strong>in</strong> the other pole<br />

of the narrative. The symbol that Hobbes co<strong>in</strong>s reveals the political order stripped down to its bare<br />

5 One serious objection to my enterprise would the Sk<strong>in</strong>nerian <strong>in</strong>junction to read Hobbes aga<strong>in</strong>st his own<br />

historical context, which is a far cry from enterprises that ‘attempt to use his texts as a mirror to reflect<br />

back at ourselves our current assumptions and prejudices’ (Sk<strong>in</strong>ner 1996, 15). This, however, is a<br />

critique that would validly be addressed to the discipl<strong>in</strong>e as a whole which has constantly sought to<br />

reposition itself <strong>in</strong> relation to Hobbes. ‘The uses and abuses of Hobbes <strong>in</strong> IR’ to paraphrase Mark Heller<br />

(see also Jahn 2000), and the ways <strong>in</strong> which they have shaped the discipl<strong>in</strong>e’s th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about agency, are<br />

explicitly my object here.<br />

5


ones; to the extent that it is directly pert<strong>in</strong>ent to th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about the type of m<strong>in</strong>imalist, anarchical<br />

order that obta<strong>in</strong>s <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>ternational system. <strong>In</strong> this read<strong>in</strong>g, then, the Leviathan designates not a<br />

particular type of political order, conditioned upon sovereignty, but the very condition of possibility of<br />

ordered <strong>in</strong>teractions <strong>in</strong> the first place. It designates, <strong>in</strong> other words, the condition of possibility of<br />

political order itself, whether at the national or <strong>in</strong>ternational level. That s<strong>in</strong>e qua non, without which<br />

there is not anarchy but properly chaos, for Hobbes, is the possibility, not of act<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> concert, nor even<br />

of a common agreement, but of the actors be<strong>in</strong>g able to understand one another. It is the possibility of a<br />

set of shared mean<strong>in</strong>gs exist<strong>in</strong>g between them, however rudimentary; or, <strong>in</strong> other words, of a common<br />

language – that with which a state, for example, understands that war has been declared upon it by<br />

another. 6<br />

The corollary to this argument at the <strong>in</strong>dividual level directly speaks to the issue of conceptions<br />

of the <strong>in</strong>dividual. It is developed <strong>in</strong> the fourth and f<strong>in</strong>al part of the paper. To appraise the Leviathan, not<br />

as the state, nor as the sovereign, but as the condition of possibility or order itself, is to draw out a key<br />

function it holds with<strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s psyche. The Leviathan is, I suggest, the equivalent of Lacan’s<br />

Other, without which the self cannot make itself. It performs the function that designates as the ‘Name<br />

of the Father’ with regards to the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s relationship to language and her entry <strong>in</strong>to sociality.<br />

Consequently the dynamics that drive the <strong>in</strong>dividual to contract with the Leviathan are none other than<br />

those subsequently unravelled by the castration complex <strong>in</strong> Lacanian psychoanalytic theory. Implications<br />

for IR theory are considered <strong>in</strong> clos<strong>in</strong>g and specifically, what it means to apprehend the state as a<br />

speak<strong>in</strong>g subject, rather than a rational actor or a self, <strong>in</strong> the study of <strong>in</strong>ternational politics.<br />

<strong>In</strong> the Leviathan’s <strong>Wake</strong>: from the Rational Actor to the Self<br />

6 While my argumentation will rema<strong>in</strong> state-centric, both for reasons of parsimony and <strong>in</strong> order to<br />

rema<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> keep<strong>in</strong>g with the theories with which it engages, a key implication is that the state need not<br />

rema<strong>in</strong> the centre po<strong>in</strong>t of discursive approaches (see, however, Epste<strong>in</strong> 2010 to move beyond this state<br />

centrism).<br />

6


The Leviathan posits the site of the orig<strong>in</strong>al division of labour between political theory and <strong>in</strong>ternational<br />

relations, which revolves around two related yet dist<strong>in</strong>ct clusters of mean<strong>in</strong>gs. IR, the discipl<strong>in</strong>e that<br />

carved its remit out as the relations between states, considers the Leviathan as the state, envisaged<br />

from without; whereas Political Theory appraises the sovereign, envisaged from with<strong>in</strong>. From there, <strong>in</strong><br />

IR, questions perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to the relationship between the Leviathan and the subject have been largely<br />

black-boxed and attention largely shifted to the other pole of the narrative; such that the Hobbesian<br />

legacy <strong>in</strong> IR has largely revolved around the state of nature rather than the figure of the Leviathan. As<br />

such the Leviathan is, via realist read<strong>in</strong>gs, both taken for granted as the discipl<strong>in</strong>e’s found<strong>in</strong>g currency<br />

yet largely lost from sight. My contention is that return<strong>in</strong>g to appraise it fully as a symbol draws out yet<br />

another level of mean<strong>in</strong>g, beyond the state or the sovereign, that reveals someth<strong>in</strong>g fundamental about<br />

the possibility of <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g politically that is pert<strong>in</strong>ent for understand<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternational order. 7 Before<br />

turn<strong>in</strong>g to that symbol I etch out a very brief history of the discipl<strong>in</strong>e under the prism of the relationship<br />

to Hobbes <strong>in</strong> order to show the ways <strong>in</strong> which the Hobbesian state of nature has explicitly or implicitly<br />

<strong>in</strong>formed conceptions of agency <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics.<br />

Hobbes the Realist<br />

Ever s<strong>in</strong>ce realism first laid claim to Hobbes’s state of nature as its found<strong>in</strong>g myth, the history of<br />

<strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> Theory (IRT) has been punctuated by a succession of efforts to recover Hobbes<br />

7 A note here to clarify my term<strong>in</strong>ology. A symbol is rhetorical trope, used especially <strong>in</strong> religion or art for<br />

example, <strong>in</strong> which representations of concrete objects serve to <strong>in</strong>voke abstract, non-figurable qualities<br />

(associated with the div<strong>in</strong>e, for example). The prefix sym (‘with’) signifies this jo<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g together. The core<br />

question explored as part of the argument itself is, once we suspend these two mean<strong>in</strong>gs conventionally<br />

attributed to it (the state and the sovereign), what else has the Leviathan been jo<strong>in</strong>ed to?<br />

A myth for its part is a literary trope that comprises a narrative, dynamic component and some form of<br />

resolution or denouement (Souriau 1990). I thus use the term ‘myth’ to refer to Hobbes’s ‘state of<br />

nature’, that place that humans leave to form a polity. When referr<strong>in</strong>g to the Leviathan I alternate<br />

between the neutral term ‘figure’ and ‘symbol’, which is thematised as part of the argument itself.<br />

7


away from the ‘Hobbesian tradition’, as it has come to be known. 8 The l<strong>in</strong>chp<strong>in</strong> to the realist claim is the<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al a nalogy drawn <strong>in</strong> Leviathan chapter XIII between <strong>in</strong>dividuals <strong>in</strong> the state of nature and<br />

sovereigns that are seen to stand similarly fac<strong>in</strong>g one another ‘<strong>in</strong> the posture of gladiators; (…) their<br />

weapons po<strong>in</strong>t<strong>in</strong>g, and their eyes fixed on one another’ (Hobbes 1946 [1651], 83). Upon it h<strong>in</strong>ges the<br />

formulation of two found<strong>in</strong>g realist concerns, what drives states to behave as they do, and the problem<br />

of <strong>in</strong>ternational order. Both centrally <strong>in</strong>voke Hobbes’ natural <strong>in</strong>dividual. I consider each <strong>in</strong> turn.<br />

First, Hobbes’ ‘natural man’ [sic] lies at the core of the classical realists’ quests to f<strong>in</strong>d the prime<br />

mover of states, namely the desire for power, the sole ‘mov<strong>in</strong>g force’ driv<strong>in</strong>g the world (Morgenthau<br />

1963, 23, and especially 56l; see also Carr 1946, 112). <strong>In</strong> these realist accounts the wolfish tendencies of<br />

Hobbes’ natural <strong>in</strong>dividual expla<strong>in</strong> the permanent struggle for survival and expansion that characterises<br />

<strong>in</strong>ter-state relations. For Raymond Aron (1966, 72, emphasis <strong>in</strong> orig<strong>in</strong>al), unravell<strong>in</strong>g the logic of the<br />

Hobbesian analogy, ‘<strong>in</strong> the state of nature every entity, whether <strong>in</strong>dividual or political unit, makes<br />

security a primary objective’. <strong>In</strong>voked here, however, is not Hobbes’s <strong>in</strong>dividual per se but rather only<br />

half of it, as it were, that belong<strong>in</strong>g to the state of nature. The other half, Hobbes’ account of the mak<strong>in</strong>g<br />

of the political subject, is explicitly cast off limits as perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to the <strong>in</strong>ternal work<strong>in</strong>gs of the state.<br />

Tak<strong>in</strong>g their cue from Hobbes classical realists thus turned to the <strong>in</strong>dividual to expla<strong>in</strong> state<br />

behaviour. Given the multiple accounts of human nature that have succeeded one another <strong>in</strong> the long<br />

history of political thought, however, together with the many associated states of nature (not least<br />

Rousseau’s and Locke’s), the broader question, <strong>in</strong> terms of assess<strong>in</strong>g Hobbes’ <strong>in</strong>fluence upon the<br />

development of the discipl<strong>in</strong>e at large, is why was Hobbes’ the one that stuck for classical realists? The<br />

resonance of Hobbes’ natural <strong>in</strong>dividual owes, I suggest, not (merely) to its sombre nature that would<br />

8 As is the case with most labels <strong>in</strong> IR, ‘Hobbesian’ has tended to be attributed mostly by other schools,<br />

first by the English school (see notably Bull 1977, V<strong>in</strong>cent 1981) and then constructivists (see Kratochwil<br />

1989, Wendt 1999; see also Walker 1992).<br />

8


have somehow better lent it to realism’s <strong>in</strong>herent pessimism, but rather to the location of this humanstate<br />

analogy <strong>in</strong> the history of political thought. The Hobbesian analogy constitutes the earliest<br />

expression of an awareness of the <strong>in</strong>ternational as a dist<strong>in</strong>ct sphere of political <strong>in</strong>teractions. Hobbes’<br />

expla<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g states by way of <strong>in</strong>dividuals played a key role <strong>in</strong> found<strong>in</strong>g IR as a discrete field of enquiry<br />

because it carved out, not just a dist<strong>in</strong>ct object of enquiry (the <strong>in</strong>ternational), but a style of reason<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

An endur<strong>in</strong>g effect of the Hobbesian legacy, beyond the so-called Hobbesian tradition, was thus to<br />

entrench this analogous juxtaposition of the <strong>in</strong>dividual and the state as a last<strong>in</strong>g trope of IR theoris<strong>in</strong>g. 9<br />

Second, these <strong>in</strong>teractions between these natural <strong>in</strong>dividuals provided the orig<strong>in</strong>al exemplar for<br />

conceptualis<strong>in</strong>g the problem of political order <strong>in</strong> the absence of centralised authority. As Michael<br />

Williams (1996, 213) remarks, ‘the concept of anarchy and the name of Thomas Hobbes often seem<br />

virtuously synonymous’, and the state of nature was where the synonymy was sealed. For classical<br />

realists writ<strong>in</strong>g aga<strong>in</strong>st the backdrop of develop<strong>in</strong>g nuclear arms race, to draw here on an array of<br />

formulations of the problem, ‘manag<strong>in</strong>g peace’ <strong>in</strong> such conditions of anarchy (<strong>In</strong>is’s 1962, 3-10) had<br />

acquired ‘an urgency it never had before’ (Morgenthau 1963, 23); it was thought to be ‘the problem of<br />

the 20 th<br />

century’ (Waltz 1959, 11). Moreover the cold war, a term that was seen to express the<br />

qu<strong>in</strong>tessence of what ‘[Hobbes] took to be the permanent relationship of nations’, acutely brought<br />

home the relevance of his state of nature to contemporary <strong>in</strong>ternational politics s<strong>in</strong>ce, as David Gauthier<br />

(1969, 207) further puts it, ‘the major nuclear powers share the equality of Hobbesian men [sic]– they<br />

can utterly destroy one another’.<br />

9 See also Beate Jahn (2001, xi), who shows the endur<strong>in</strong>g centrality of the state of nature to ‘Liberal as<br />

well as Realist <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> Theory’. I suggest this also has to with the way <strong>in</strong> which the state<br />

of nature foregrounds the <strong>in</strong>dividual as a basis for theoriz<strong>in</strong>g a universal human nature, that is, with the<br />

usefulness of the epistemological trope. Historically Hobbes’ was the first, and arguably both Locke,<br />

Sp<strong>in</strong>oza and Rousseau elaborated their own aga<strong>in</strong>st his.<br />

9


Classical realism thus cast its lenses upon Hobbes’ natural <strong>in</strong>dividual and revealed a highly<br />

atomised <strong>in</strong>ternational system of ever-potentially collid<strong>in</strong>g units like billiard balls to use Wolfer’s (1962,<br />

19) classic metaphor.<br />

The State of Nature and the E- Rational <strong>In</strong>dividual<br />

The state of nature was a key site for the convergence of realism <strong>in</strong> IR and rational choice theory<br />

<strong>in</strong> political science, who further elaborated the tools to study the state, locked <strong>in</strong> as IR’s unit of analysis.<br />

This convergence yielded the strong <strong>in</strong>dividualism that characterises current rationalist traditions<br />

(neorealism and neoliberalist <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism; see Keohane 1988). 10 <strong>In</strong>sofar as these rationalist read<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

have played an important part <strong>in</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g attention away from the role of language and sociality <strong>in</strong><br />

Hobbes’ <strong>in</strong>dividual, it is worth consider<strong>in</strong>g them here at some length here. 11<br />

The Hobbesian state of nature has provided the foundations for theoriz<strong>in</strong>g the rational, self<strong>in</strong>terested<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual (Neal 1987, Hampton 1986, Brams 1985:139-46; Kavka 1983: 17-18; MacLean<br />

1981:339-51; Gauthier 1977, 1969). Specifically, it is considered as the traditional exemplar of the<br />

prisoner’s dilemma situation (Hampton 1986, McLean 1983). Extensive work has thus been undertaken<br />

to model the behaviour of Hobbes’s ‘natural man’ [Sic] as the archetypal ‘e-rational’ (economically<br />

rational) agent, to borrow Patrick Neal’s (1987) expression. The state of nature, rather than the<br />

10 To be clear, I thus use ‘rationalist’ to mean centered upon the utility-maximiz<strong>in</strong>g rational actor, as <strong>in</strong><br />

Keohane (1989), who <strong>in</strong>cluded under this term both neorealism and neoliberal <strong>in</strong>stitutionalism. This is<br />

quite dist<strong>in</strong>ct from the English School’s usage of the term, as entrenched by Mart<strong>in</strong> Wight’s (1992) three<br />

traditions, where ‘rationalism’/the Grotian tradition is opposed to ‘realism’/the Machiavelli or<br />

Hobbesian tradition and to ‘revolutionism’/ the Kantian tradition ( see also V<strong>in</strong>cent 1981, Buzan 2004).<br />

Rationalism is thus, the context of my argument, synonymous with realist thought writ wide.<br />

11 These close l<strong>in</strong>ks are recognized from the other end as well, by rational choice theorists who readily<br />

cross over onto IR’s terra<strong>in</strong>; one recalls here the appendix David Gauthier (1969, 207-212) devotes to<br />

‘Hobbes on <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>’ (for a critique from with<strong>in</strong> political theory, see Malcolm 2002).<br />

10


Leviathan, lies once aga<strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong> focus as it showcases the natural <strong>in</strong>dividual <strong>in</strong> her raw, self-<strong>in</strong>terested,<br />

utility-maximis<strong>in</strong>g form. 12<br />

Patrick Neal <strong>in</strong> his ‘Hobbes and Rational Choice Theory’ identifies <strong>in</strong>dividualism and<br />

<strong>In</strong>strumentalism as two of the theory’s core tenets, which he traces directly to Hobbes. By<br />

‘<strong>in</strong>dividualism’ Neal (1987, 637) means that ‘antecedently def<strong>in</strong>ed selves’ stand prior to all ‘sociopolitical<br />

relations and <strong>in</strong>stitutions’. The <strong>in</strong>dividual is therefore the ‘foundation or <strong>in</strong>dependent variable’ of<br />

rationalist analyses (Neal 1987, 637). These <strong>in</strong>dividuals or ‘separate selves’, moreover, ‘are understood<br />

to be rationally self-<strong>in</strong>terested maximizers of utility’ (Neal 1987, 637-638).<br />

‘<strong>In</strong>strumentalism, then’, Neal (1987, 637) cont<strong>in</strong>ues, ‘must deny that human be<strong>in</strong>gs are <strong>in</strong> any<br />

<strong>in</strong>herent or <strong>in</strong>tr<strong>in</strong>sic sense social be<strong>in</strong>gs’. Further, ‘<strong>in</strong>strumentalism seeks to understand relations <strong>in</strong><br />

terms of selves, not selves <strong>in</strong> terms of relations’ (Neal 1987, 637). Under these rationalist lenses, cast<br />

upon the state of nature, Hobbes becomes, by way of his ‘natural man’ the founder of a ‘radical<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividualism’ that entrenches the <strong>in</strong>dividual and the wide gamut of its behaviour as the legitimate<br />

object of political analysis (Hampton 1986). David Gauthier (1977, 139) for his part captures this<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividualist ontology <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g terms:<br />

‘(…) <strong>in</strong>dividuals human be<strong>in</strong>gs not only can, but must, be understood apart from society. The<br />

fundamental characteristics of men are not products of their social existence….man is social<br />

because he is human, not human because he is social. <strong>In</strong> particular, self-consciousness and<br />

language must be taken as conditions, not products, of society.’<br />

It is noteworthy that Hobbes is once aga<strong>in</strong> a reference po<strong>in</strong>t. Thus Jean Hampton (1986, 6) for her part<br />

writes:<br />

12 To the extent that the Leviathan does enter <strong>in</strong>to the analysis, for example <strong>in</strong> Morton Kaplan (1956,<br />

405), it is to limit any hold it might have on the <strong>in</strong>dividual by conclud<strong>in</strong>g to the absence of any ‘extra<strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

source of obligation’ <strong>in</strong> Hobbes political treaty. Such conclusion however is premised on<br />

Hobbes political subject and his ‘natural man’ be<strong>in</strong>g two different persons, rather than two facets of the<br />

same <strong>in</strong>dividual mov<strong>in</strong>g out of the state of nature, as does Hobbes’ natural man.<br />

11


Gauthier is right to f<strong>in</strong>d <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’s theory a very strong brand of <strong>in</strong>dividualism, one that<br />

regards <strong>in</strong>dividual human be<strong>in</strong>gs as conceptually prior not only to political society but also to all<br />

social <strong>in</strong>teractions<br />

One important implication of the rationalist-<strong>in</strong>dividualist ontology is that language, as all other social<br />

<strong>in</strong>stitutions, is but one <strong>in</strong>strument put to maximiz<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>terests of an e-rational, a-social actor. <strong>In</strong>sofar<br />

as language-based analyses cast the primary focus upon the social bond itself and thus between the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividuals, they stand fundamentally at odds with these <strong>in</strong>dividualist, rationalist analyses. Significantly<br />

these differences were honed on Hobbes’ Leviathan.<br />

Pav<strong>in</strong>g the Way towards Sociality: the English School’s Cooperative Gladiators<br />

The state of nature provided the battleground for the <strong>in</strong>itial attempts to recover Hobbes away<br />

from this <strong>in</strong>dividualist ontology and the billiard board model of anarchy it had yielded. The <strong>in</strong>itial critique<br />

of its ‘uses and abuses <strong>in</strong> IR’ as Mark Heller (1980) put it, was two pronged. First, scholars from both IR<br />

and political theory at large have extensively underl<strong>in</strong>ed the limits Hobbes is careful to set upon his own<br />

analogy immediately after establish<strong>in</strong>g it (see Malcolm 2002, Williams 1996, Kratochwil 1989, V<strong>in</strong>cent<br />

1981, Heller 1980 Bull 1977). 13 That Hobbes himself fell short of extend<strong>in</strong>g the logic of his solution to the<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternational level was not an oversight but rather <strong>in</strong>dicates his awareness of the differences between<br />

that sphere and the state of nature, which has been largely brushed aside as the analogy became<br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly entrenched <strong>in</strong> realist thought .<br />

Second, scholars from the English School tradition more specifically sought to dig up the seeds<br />

of a relatively peaceful <strong>in</strong>ternational society <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’ own state of nature (Bull 1977; V<strong>in</strong>cent 1981,<br />

Boucher 1990; Wight 1992; Williams 1996). They po<strong>in</strong>t to the other dimensions of Hobbes’ ‘natural<br />

man’, beyond his wolfish tendencies, that also govern <strong>in</strong>teractions between Leviathans, notably a<br />

13 The key sentence here fore grounded by critics is ‘it does not follow from it that misery which<br />

accompanies the liberty of particular men’ Hobbes (1946, 83)<br />

12


natural propensity towards cooperation, amongst other ‘articles of peace’ that Hobbes explores <strong>in</strong> his<br />

subsequent chapter fourteen (1946, 84 et seq.). Root<strong>in</strong>g the prospects for <strong>in</strong>ternational cooperation<br />

with<strong>in</strong> Hobbes’s own conception of natural law thus enables them to reclaim this author for the cannon<br />

of <strong>in</strong>ternational law (Bull 1977, V<strong>in</strong>cent 1981; see also Kratochwill 1989 3-4).<br />

The English school sought to reclaim Hobbes as a founder of <strong>in</strong>ternational society. However the<br />

English school has, I suggest, fallen short of be<strong>in</strong>g able to fully mobilise Hobbes as a social theorist, for<br />

two sets of reasons. First, these scholars were restricted <strong>in</strong> their efforts <strong>in</strong> that direction so long as the<br />

state of nature rema<strong>in</strong>ed the terra<strong>in</strong> of their engagement. Centrally, the possibility of a social theoris<strong>in</strong>g<br />

about <strong>in</strong>ternational politics was born of the recognition of a fundamental difference between the laws<br />

of nature and the constructed, historically cont<strong>in</strong>gent and thus non-natural laws govern<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternational<br />

society (see especially Wendt 1999). Hence for all their <strong>in</strong>valuable empirical <strong>in</strong>sights on the work<strong>in</strong>gs of<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternational society, and to echo a common constructivist critique (see for example F<strong>in</strong>nemore 2001),<br />

that thick ontological difference, between natural laws as patterns of regularities and human laws as<br />

social constructs, has rema<strong>in</strong>ed under-theorised <strong>in</strong> the English school. To restate the same po<strong>in</strong>t<br />

somewhat differently, <strong>in</strong> view of his strong structuralist bend, Hobbes lent himself to realist theoris<strong>in</strong>g<br />

about an <strong>in</strong>ternational system (Waltz 1979, see also Williams 1996, Walker 1992). Draw<strong>in</strong>g out the social<br />

dimension of that structure was difficult to achieve while at the same ma<strong>in</strong>ta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the focus exclusively<br />

upon the term of the Hobbesian b<strong>in</strong>ary that designates a-sociality.<br />

My second l<strong>in</strong>e of critique is that, despite a substantial shor<strong>in</strong>g up of the foundations for its<br />

social theoris<strong>in</strong>g by a second generation of scholars <strong>in</strong> the wake of constructivism, the English school has<br />

cont<strong>in</strong>ued to shy away from foreground<strong>in</strong>g the role of language <strong>in</strong> processes of social construction. Bary<br />

Buzan, for example, has significantly expanded the English School’s theoretical toolkit by turn<strong>in</strong>g to<br />

Speech Act theorists and notably John Searle’s (1995) The Construction of Social Reality. Yet even while<br />

13


he mobilises Searle’s dist<strong>in</strong>ction between ‘brute’ and ‘<strong>in</strong>stitutional’ facts to shed further light upon<br />

Headley Bull’s primary <strong>in</strong>stitutions of <strong>in</strong>ternational society, Buzan fall short of br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g Searle’s core<br />

<strong>in</strong>sight to bear upon them that language constitutes the primary social <strong>in</strong>stitution. ‘Language’, writes<br />

Searle (1995, 59), ‘is essentially constitutive of <strong>in</strong>stitutional reality’ and the necessary condition for<br />

<strong>in</strong>stitutions to emerge <strong>in</strong> the first place, s<strong>in</strong>ce without language there is no <strong>in</strong>stitution (see especially<br />

Searle 1995, 59-78). Three out of Bull’s five primary <strong>in</strong>stitutions of <strong>in</strong>ternational society explicitly<br />

foreground language, <strong>in</strong>sofar words oil the work<strong>in</strong>gs of diplomacy, <strong>in</strong>ternational law and even the<br />

balance of power. Language is also arguably constitutive of the other two, s<strong>in</strong>ce war, for one, is a state<br />

of the <strong>in</strong>ternational system that is first declared (and it needs to be declared <strong>in</strong> order to be recognised as<br />

an <strong>in</strong>ter-state war, as opposed to a simple conflict).<br />

<strong>In</strong> sum, to f<strong>in</strong>d the seeds of sociality <strong>in</strong> Hobbes requires, I suggest, look<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stead to the role of<br />

language and to the Leviathan rather than the state of nature alone.<br />

Words <strong>in</strong> the State of Nature<br />

Hobbes’ state of nature lies at the heart of epistemological storms that cont<strong>in</strong>ued to rage with<strong>in</strong><br />

and beyond IR. Aga<strong>in</strong>st early appropriations of Hobbes as ‘the protopositivist’ by rational choice<br />

theorists, <strong>in</strong>terpretive-m<strong>in</strong>ded political theorists emphasised aspects of his thought that posit him<br />

<strong>in</strong>stead as ‘a precursor to the l<strong>in</strong>guistic turn’ (Ball 1985). Hobbes was – not unlike Searle – <strong>in</strong><br />

Terrence Ball’s (1985, 740) words, ‘a th<strong>in</strong>ker acutely aware that social and political reality is l<strong>in</strong>guistically<br />

made’. These broader debates converged with recent constructivist and post-structuralist efforts with<strong>in</strong><br />

IR to tease out some l<strong>in</strong>guistic elements of the Hobbesian state of nature. Friedrich Kratochwil (1989, 3-<br />

6) framed his Hobbesian engagement by way of the norms and rules that <strong>in</strong>here <strong>in</strong> the natural state,<br />

while Michael Williams (1996) focussed on the epistemic agreement that the Leviathans must first come<br />

to <strong>in</strong> order to cooperate. Both factors centre upon language as their primary medium and both authors<br />

14


partake <strong>in</strong> the effort to give their full weight to immaterial factors <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics. Centrally,<br />

Williams (1996, 230) draws out that truth, for Hobbes, is a historically cont<strong>in</strong>gent l<strong>in</strong>guistic construct<br />

that is absent from the state of nature and sealed only by contract<strong>in</strong>g with the Leviathan.<br />

Among post-structuralists David Campbell (1998, 53-60) explicitly apprehends Hobbes’s<br />

treatment of the state of nature as the foundational, performative ‘discourse of danger’ by which<br />

identities are produced through particular strategies of <strong>in</strong>clusion that serve to demarcate a ‘self’ from an<br />

‘other’. His treatment of identity pushes the juxtaposition of the <strong>in</strong>dividual and the state to the limit<br />

s<strong>in</strong>ce they are almost superimposed. This is made possible by the absence of any presumption regard<strong>in</strong>g<br />

the ‘pre-given’ selves of either actor, a perspective afforded by cast<strong>in</strong>g the <strong>in</strong>itial focus upon discourses.<br />

To the extent that these more recent re-engagements with Hobbes <strong>in</strong> IR emphasize, not merely<br />

cooperative elements and sociality, but the role of l<strong>in</strong>guistic phenomena <strong>in</strong> organiz<strong>in</strong>g Hobbes’s world,<br />

my read<strong>in</strong>g is <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong> their wake. The aim here, however, is to mobilise these disparate <strong>in</strong>sights<br />

towards a more systematic social theory of agency.<br />

Mov<strong>in</strong>g away from Hobbes to f<strong>in</strong>d the State’s Self<br />

These exceptions aside, Hobbes has not been central to theoris<strong>in</strong>g self-other relations <strong>in</strong><br />

constructivism, <strong>in</strong>sofar as do<strong>in</strong>g so required depart<strong>in</strong>g from what had been associated with Hobbes <strong>in</strong><br />

rationalist thought. Mov<strong>in</strong>g away from Hobbes to f<strong>in</strong>d the state’s self, however, constructivism also<br />

moved away from the role of language <strong>in</strong> the constitution of the self. A common critique of Wendt’s<br />

social theory is that it ‘forgets about the contribution of language to the social construction of political<br />

reality’ that was centrally <strong>in</strong>tuited <strong>in</strong> constructivism’s early days (Drulak 2010, 77; see notably Kratochwil<br />

1989, Onuf 1989). My po<strong>in</strong>t here concerns more specifically its contribution to the very notion that<br />

Wendt tables, namely, that of the ‘self’ of the state.<br />

15


What did carry over from Hobbes , moreover, is once aga<strong>in</strong> the analogous juxtaposition of the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual and the state that centrally underp<strong>in</strong>s Alexander Wendt’s (1999, 215-245) elaboration of the<br />

notion that the state has a ‘Self’ that constitutes both the seat of a core, fixed identity and the place<br />

from which it enters <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong>teractions with an ‘Other’. After all states, for Wendt (1999, 215, 221), are<br />

people too; this ‘anthropomorphiz<strong>in</strong>g’ of the state is rooted <strong>in</strong> the Hobbesian state of nature. Although<br />

Wendt (215-221) extensively elaborates this concept of personhood as a corporate or collective rather<br />

than an <strong>in</strong>dividual form of agency, this is also the po<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> Wendt’s social theory where the <strong>in</strong>dividual is<br />

split <strong>in</strong> two, between the actor and the self. On the one hand this elaboration serves to stake out<br />

actorhood as the terra<strong>in</strong> upon which to deploy the constitutive logic that characterises enquiries <strong>in</strong>to<br />

processes of social construction. On other hand, by the same token, it serves to hold off the self from<br />

such enquiries. For Wendt, as an actor of <strong>in</strong>ternational politics the state may be socially constructed, but<br />

its’ self is not.<br />

<strong>In</strong> IR at large, the legacy of Hobbes’s Leviathan has largely revolved around the state of nature.<br />

The Leviathan po<strong>in</strong>ts to a bl<strong>in</strong>d spot on the horizon of IR theory, both with<strong>in</strong> the so-called Hobbesian<br />

traditions and those critical of it. Yet the ‘serious engagement with his thought rather than a cursory<br />

dismissal’ to which Michael William’s (1996, 233) enjo<strong>in</strong>s ‘those critical of positivist-<strong>in</strong>spired theories<br />

<strong>in</strong>ternational relation’ requires, I argue, br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g back the other pole of the narrative.<br />

Look<strong>in</strong>g for the Leviathan: The Misadventures of Carl Schmitt<br />

Br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g the figure of the Leviathan back <strong>in</strong> requires stepp<strong>in</strong>g out of IR and <strong>in</strong>to political theory.<br />

To this effect, the figure of Carl Schmitt provides a useful bridge; first, because Schmitt’s own thought<br />

<strong>in</strong>creas<strong>in</strong>gly straddled the two discipl<strong>in</strong>es (see also Schwab 2008); second, <strong>in</strong> view of his recognised<br />

l<strong>in</strong>eage with<strong>in</strong> classical realism, as per Morgenthau’s ‘hidden dialogue’ with him (Scheuerman 1999, 62).<br />

I focus specifically on his The Leviathan <strong>in</strong> the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Mean<strong>in</strong>g and Failure of a<br />

16


Symbol. Schmitt’s perspective is useful for cast<strong>in</strong>g the focus upon the Leviathan as a symbol, that is, as a<br />

l<strong>in</strong>guistic trope, and for operat<strong>in</strong>g the shift from consider<strong>in</strong>g the Leviathan as the symbol of a particular<br />

political order bound up with sovereignty to the symbol of order, at the national and <strong>in</strong>ternational<br />

levels.<br />

Schmitt’s concern, as per his subtitle, is with understand<strong>in</strong>g the true mean<strong>in</strong>g of this ‘strongest<br />

and most powerful image’ <strong>in</strong> the ‘long history of political theories’; one, moreover, that, however ‘rich <strong>in</strong><br />

colorful images and symbols, icons and idols, paradigms and phantasms, emblems and allegories’ has<br />

left many a political theorists ponder<strong>in</strong>g over this particular one (see also Brown 1980, Ball 1985,<br />

Stillman 1995, Spr<strong>in</strong>gborg 1996). Carl Schmitt alone however, to my knowledge, dedicates an entire<br />

book to apprais<strong>in</strong>g it as a symbol, albeit without actually develop<strong>in</strong>g the concept. Schmitt (2008, 19)<br />

sets out to record all the mean<strong>in</strong>gs of this ‘mythical totality’ by glean<strong>in</strong>g references to it, first <strong>in</strong> the text<br />

itself, then <strong>in</strong> the broader historical context of the treatise’s writ<strong>in</strong>g. He f<strong>in</strong>ds only three mentions <strong>in</strong> the<br />

text itself. He does not hide his disappo<strong>in</strong>tment: ‘the explanation is very brief and does not correspond<br />

to the great expectation that a mythical blend<strong>in</strong>g of god and animal, animal and man, man and mach<strong>in</strong>e<br />

evokes’ (Schmitt 2008, 20). Once he has exhausted all possible sources of mean<strong>in</strong>g with<strong>in</strong> and beyond<br />

the text Schmitt concludes to the symbol’s failure; an astound<strong>in</strong>g conclusion, given its deep resonance <strong>in</strong><br />

the history of political thought, Schmitt’s own motivations <strong>in</strong> try<strong>in</strong>g to appraise its power. Schmitt’s<br />

somewhat deflated conclusion appears, rather, to express his own unease <strong>in</strong> the face of profound<br />

ambiguity <strong>in</strong> the ‘old myth’ that ultimately eludes his best efforts to p<strong>in</strong> down all its mean<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

The ambiguity and polysemy at work <strong>in</strong> this symbol, Schmitt senses, is <strong>in</strong>tended by Hobbes;<br />

uncerta<strong>in</strong> though he rema<strong>in</strong>s as to how to tackle it. Schmitt’s approach, I suggest, actually leads him<br />

astray from be<strong>in</strong>g able to grasp the function of the Leviathan <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’s political thought. I propose a<br />

different way of apprais<strong>in</strong>g this mythical totality. Rather than wr<strong>in</strong>g the symbol for all its mean<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

17


with<strong>in</strong> and beyond the text, it is <strong>in</strong>stead to embrace its ambiguousness as a start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t. The Leviathan<br />

operates as the central signifier at work <strong>in</strong> his political treatise; that much Schmitt would not disagree<br />

with, albeit <strong>in</strong> a different language. To cont<strong>in</strong>ue to usher <strong>in</strong> here the l<strong>in</strong>guistic term<strong>in</strong>ology, his is an<br />

effort to map out the field of significations, or ‘signified’, conjured by the signifier. The attitude I<br />

propose, however, is, rather than rather than seek to exhaust its significations, is to appraise how it<br />

operates as an open-ended signifier. This ambiguousness and polysemy are an <strong>in</strong>tegral part of its<br />

constitution as, and this is the core of argument, the master signifier of the symbolic order itself (terms I<br />

am about to expla<strong>in</strong>). As such it cannot be p<strong>in</strong>ned down to one signification nor <strong>in</strong>deed rid of its<br />

ambiguousness. Rather, its ability to condense as many mean<strong>in</strong>gs as possible is central to its function<strong>in</strong>g<br />

as the master signifier that underp<strong>in</strong>s the possibility of signification itself. To develop this argument,<br />

however, I first require <strong>in</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g Lacan’s broader categories of the symbolic and the primacy of the<br />

signifier, <strong>in</strong> order to show the Leviathan constitutes <strong>in</strong> fact the symbol, or signifier, designat<strong>in</strong>g the<br />

political order at large, whether at the national or <strong>in</strong>ternational level.<br />

<strong>In</strong>troduc<strong>in</strong>g Jacques Lacan<br />

From the Symbol to The Symbolic<br />

‘The symbolic’ <strong>in</strong> Lacanian term<strong>in</strong>ology designates the political order at large. What, then, is dist<strong>in</strong>ctive<br />

about this understand<strong>in</strong>g of the social, and why is it pert<strong>in</strong>ent to <strong>in</strong>terpret<strong>in</strong>g Hobbes? Three key<br />

features are helpful to contextualiz<strong>in</strong>g this notion of the symbolic <strong>in</strong> Lacan’s body of thought, namely, its<br />

language-based, cl<strong>in</strong>ical, and developmental dimensions.<br />

First, for Lacan the def<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g characteristic of humans as political animals is speech. The ability to<br />

speak is all at once the basis of all social and political life, and what makes <strong>in</strong>dividual identity, <strong>in</strong>deed all<br />

life as a political animal, possible. Language thus stands at the centre of his theoriz<strong>in</strong>g because it is the<br />

foundation of the social order itself. Here he is uncannily close to Hobbes (1946, 18) when he writes that<br />

18


‘the most notable <strong>in</strong>ventions of all was that of speech (…) without which, there had been amongst men<br />

neither common wealth, no society, nor contract, nor peace, no more than amongst lions, bears or<br />

wolves.’ The centrality of language is the dist<strong>in</strong>ctive feature of Lacanian psychoanalytic thought, a large<br />

part of which developed as a re<strong>in</strong>terpretation of Sigmund Freud’s discoveries <strong>in</strong> order to draw out the<br />

efficaciousness of language. It is also what lends a dist<strong>in</strong>ctively collective, which is to say, political,<br />

dimension to his theoriz<strong>in</strong>g (Stavarkakis 1999, Edk<strong>in</strong>s 1999). If the task of psychoanalytic theoriz<strong>in</strong>g can<br />

be understood as the effort, <strong>in</strong> Freud’s wake, to uncover the deep structures of the human psyche on<br />

the one hand, <strong>in</strong> order to understand, on the other, how the <strong>in</strong>dividual relates (or fails) to the world<br />

around her, then one of Lacan’s key contribution was to draw out the extent to which these two<br />

dimensions, the <strong>in</strong>dividual and the collective, are tightly bound up. That contribution <strong>in</strong> turn rests on his<br />

foreground<strong>in</strong>g language as the primary social bond. Language, that dist<strong>in</strong>ctly human trait, is what leads<br />

humans out of the state of nature and makes all social (<strong>in</strong> Hobbes) and <strong>in</strong>dividual (<strong>in</strong> Lacan) life possible<br />

<strong>in</strong> the first place<br />

Second, although Lacan centrally foregrounds language, it is important to bear <strong>in</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d that his is<br />

fundamentally applied theory. His theoris<strong>in</strong>g is geared towards analytical practice, not towards<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g literary texts or language per se. It mobilises the key <strong>in</strong>sight, common also to speech act<br />

theory, that words do th<strong>in</strong>gs, to echo Aust<strong>in</strong>’s (1962) formulation. Theory and practice are here tightly<br />

bound up as <strong>in</strong> few other contemporary spaces for theoriz<strong>in</strong>g the political. Here too there is a closeness<br />

to the realm of practice that is ak<strong>in</strong> to that of Hobbes who, writ<strong>in</strong>g dur<strong>in</strong>g the English civil war (1642-<br />

1651), stood before a civil order that was com<strong>in</strong>g undone, and thus at a juncture where the task of<br />

political theoriz<strong>in</strong>g was more directly efficacious than <strong>in</strong> these societies today. Both constitute bodies of<br />

thought developed with the press<strong>in</strong>g urgency of an ailment to cure, <strong>in</strong> the political and <strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

body respectively. Lacan’s start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t is thus the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s experience; he sets out to uncover the<br />

deep structures undergird<strong>in</strong>g her relationship to the world around her.<br />

19


This expla<strong>in</strong>s, second, the diachronic or developmental perspective by which he seeks to<br />

understand how an <strong>in</strong>dividual is born <strong>in</strong>to these structures, driven by that imperative to diagnose the<br />

source of her contemporary ailments. <strong>In</strong> this he positions himself <strong>in</strong> a somewhat similar stance to<br />

Hobbes’s, at the orig<strong>in</strong> of the social order. Both similarly develop diachronic perspectives, <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’s<br />

case, to retrace the passage from a pre-social to a social order. <strong>In</strong> Lacan, the trajectory of the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s<br />

development and her account of it become the analytical material itself. Timel<strong>in</strong>es are thus central<br />

operative pr<strong>in</strong>ciples both <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’s treatise and <strong>in</strong> Lacan’s cl<strong>in</strong>ical practice, but theirs are diachronic<br />

rather than historical perspectives s<strong>in</strong>ce history is mythical <strong>in</strong> both <strong>in</strong>stances. What matters is not the<br />

accuracy of the narrative so much as history’s function as a myth at the collective level (<strong>in</strong> Hobbes) or its<br />

narration by the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject as that which the analyst and analysand can work on (<strong>in</strong> Lacan).<br />

The Three Axes of the Lacanian Symbolic<br />

The symbolic is then, is the social order <strong>in</strong> a simplified sense. Hav<strong>in</strong>g etched out the logic of<br />

Lacanian theoris<strong>in</strong>g now enables us to flesh out this complex concept more substantially, along three<br />

axes. It was co<strong>in</strong>ed to capture, first, the ensemble of symbols that constitute a culture, apprehended<br />

as a structured totality. At a more generic level, it designates the matrix or organiz<strong>in</strong>g pr<strong>in</strong>ciple<br />

undergird<strong>in</strong>g all social life. Language and the law are its primary sites of expressions, and they are<br />

tightly bound up. <strong>In</strong>deed, Lacan developed the concept by build<strong>in</strong>g on Freud’s (1913) analysis of the<br />

<strong>in</strong>cest taboo and the role of the father figure as the found<strong>in</strong>g stone for the social order at large. 14 The<br />

father’s <strong>in</strong>itial, symbolic (rather than actually pronounced; and therefore forever potentially<br />

reiterated) pronouncement of the <strong>in</strong>cest prohibition is the mythical found<strong>in</strong>g speech act that, by<br />

draw<strong>in</strong>g the first l<strong>in</strong>e between the forbidden and the authorised, founds the law and thus the<br />

14 To be clear this father figure, or symbolic father, does not refer to the actual, real genitor; but rather<br />

simply to an <strong>in</strong>stance constitutive of the human psyche. As such, there is no implication whatsoever that<br />

this person need be a male; but rather any person who simply takes on this symbolic function <strong>in</strong> the<br />

development of the child.<br />

20


possibility of social life. The symbolic designates the broader grid onto which the <strong>in</strong>dividual is hooked,<br />

as it were, as part of her becom<strong>in</strong>g a social, which is to say political be<strong>in</strong>g. This process of hook<strong>in</strong>g<br />

onto or <strong>in</strong>scription is illustrated by the function of nam<strong>in</strong>g (Lacan 1977, 74). The acquisition of a<br />

proper name marks the moment when the child is <strong>in</strong>scribed <strong>in</strong>to the symbolic order. This is the<br />

constitutive moment for the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s identity, the one that makes possible all ulterior identities.<br />

Centrally, this passage from the biological, or the state of nature, to the social order is operated by a<br />

signifier.<br />

Second, the symbolic constitutes one of three ontological categories that structure the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual’s relationship to the world, or her ‘reality’. It is thus best understood <strong>in</strong> relation to, on the one<br />

hand, ‘the real’ (which is thus not to be confused with ‘reality’), and ‘the imag<strong>in</strong>ary’ on the other. The<br />

category of the real has been considered Lacan’s central contribution to philosophy (Juranville 1984). It<br />

designates that which is irreducible to words and thus to our efforts to apprehend the world around us.<br />

For to know is to put words to th<strong>in</strong>gs; it is an act of symbolisation. The real thus marks the hard limit of<br />

symbolization; grossly simplified, where words flounder. Examples would be the experience of death or<br />

natural disasters. The imag<strong>in</strong>ary and the symbolic for their part stand <strong>in</strong> relation each another as the<br />

orders of nature and culture respectively. The imag<strong>in</strong>ary constitutes the realm of identifications and<br />

imag<strong>in</strong>ary projections. It is what which humans share with animals. <strong>In</strong> the animal k<strong>in</strong>gdom imagos and<br />

lures form an <strong>in</strong>tegral part of the biological mechanisms of survival and reproduction, notably <strong>in</strong> the use<br />

of camouflage. <strong>In</strong> a developmental perspective, the imag<strong>in</strong>ary is where the <strong>in</strong>dividual dwells before she<br />

enters the social order and which she never completely leaves beh<strong>in</strong>d. <strong>In</strong> that sense it rema<strong>in</strong>s the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual’s primary doma<strong>in</strong>, ruled by images and lures, rather than by symbols, which are dist<strong>in</strong>ctly<br />

human trait. The imag<strong>in</strong>ary is thus, as will be shown more extensively <strong>in</strong> the next section, the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual’s very own state of nature.<br />

21


The imag<strong>in</strong>ary is also the site where these primitive projections have been repressed onto an<br />

unconscious level. This <strong>in</strong>vokes the more applied dimension of Lacan’s work, where the symbolic<br />

constitutes, third, the realm of the analytical cure. The cure itself largely consists <strong>in</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g those<br />

imag<strong>in</strong>ary projections lodged <strong>in</strong> the unconscious (especially those revolv<strong>in</strong>g around processes of<br />

identification, see Epste<strong>in</strong> 2010 for an extensive development), which can play the analysand’s despite<br />

herself and at great expense of suffer<strong>in</strong>g, pass <strong>in</strong>to the symbolic order. There they can be worked on<br />

with analyst, fully circumscribed, and ultimately put at a remove. The cure illustrates the extent to which<br />

language is performative for Lacan. It is doubly performative, as both the primary material of and the<br />

medium for the cure. Language both reveals the source of the ailments on the one hand (when the<br />

analysand talks), and it constitutes the means of the therapeutic <strong>in</strong>tervention on the other (the analysts’<br />

<strong>in</strong>tervention). The aim of the cure is the symbolization of the imag<strong>in</strong>ary material expressed <strong>in</strong> the<br />

analysand’s speech. The <strong>in</strong>tervention of the analyst consists <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terrupt<strong>in</strong>g these imag<strong>in</strong>ary projections<br />

<strong>in</strong> which the speaker rema<strong>in</strong>s trapped. The Lacanian analysis thus rests on a particular type of speech<br />

act. 15<br />

To summarise, the symbolic plays out along three key axes <strong>in</strong> Lacan’s thought. It is the realm of<br />

the cure, whose basic operative pr<strong>in</strong>ciple is symbolization. The second and third axes outl<strong>in</strong>e the two<br />

directions <strong>in</strong> which my argument proper will unfold <strong>in</strong> the third and fourth parts of this paper, where I<br />

will show that the Leviathan constitutes the master signifier that enables all signification. These are that,<br />

at the collective level, second, the symbolic designates the social order itself. At the level of <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

experience this corresponds, third, to the Other for the self. Develop<strong>in</strong>g my argument first requires<br />

however, add<strong>in</strong>g another piece to this toolkit, the Lacian notion of ‘primacy of the signifier’ (la primauté<br />

15 The expression used by Ala<strong>in</strong> Juranville (1984), awkward <strong>in</strong> English yet effective, is ‘a speech that takes<br />

action’ (une parole qui prend acte).<br />

22


du signifiant). I expla<strong>in</strong> it <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g section by locat<strong>in</strong>g it with<strong>in</strong> the broader l<strong>in</strong>guistic turn from<br />

which it emerged.<br />

The Primacy of the Signifier<br />

Language then, is foundational to Jacques Lacan’s entire enterprise. He was largely <strong>in</strong>fluenced,<br />

first, by developments contemporary philosophy of language (Heiddegger’s writ<strong>in</strong>gs on speech or<br />

Sprache and Logos <strong>in</strong> particular, see Juignet 2003). These <strong>in</strong> turn need to be understood <strong>in</strong> relation to<br />

the broader shatter<strong>in</strong>g of the correspondence theory of the world that signalled the advent of modern<br />

conceptions of language, which is also at the orig<strong>in</strong>s of constructivism <strong>in</strong> IR. Words were no longer seen<br />

to mirror the th<strong>in</strong>gs they <strong>in</strong>voked; and the (social) world was no longer that fixed referent outside of<br />

language that was ultimately underp<strong>in</strong>ned, <strong>in</strong> a medieval post-Aristotelian ontology, by god itself. The<br />

advent of the l<strong>in</strong>guistic turn was brought on by the realization that words do not merely reveal but<br />

partially constitute the social world. 16 While the term itself tends to be used to characterizes a latemodern<br />

developments <strong>in</strong> the philosophy of languages, it appears, as Terence Ball (1985, 741) has<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ted out ‘almost as a <strong>in</strong>stance of uncoord<strong>in</strong>ated simultaneous discovery’ across the social sciences<br />

and humanities <strong>in</strong> the late 20 th century, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> IR. Or rather, Ball’s argument is that it was <strong>in</strong> fact a<br />

long drawn out discovery that extends back to Hobbes, <strong>in</strong> whom he sees the precursor to this l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

turn <strong>in</strong> late modernity.<br />

Developments <strong>in</strong> structuralism, <strong>in</strong> particular Ferd<strong>in</strong>and de Saussure’s (1916) discoveries <strong>in</strong><br />

structural l<strong>in</strong>guistics (and, later, Claude Levi Strauss’s structural anthropology) comprise the second key<br />

<strong>in</strong>fluence on the emergence of Lacanian thought. Saussure took this modern conception of language one<br />

step further. Work<strong>in</strong>g up close with words, or signs, he showed that the relationship between the word<br />

and the world constitutes the wrong start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t altogether for understand<strong>in</strong>g the mak<strong>in</strong>g of mean<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

16 The term ‘l<strong>in</strong>guistic turn’ is attributed to Richard Rorty’s 1967 anthology The L<strong>in</strong>guistic Turn. Essays <strong>in</strong><br />

Philosophical Method (see Ball 1985), who <strong>in</strong> turn attributes it to Gustave Bergmann.<br />

23


or signification. 17 The word does not reveal the world because, and this was his central contribution, the<br />

relationship between the signifier and the signified is purely arbitrary (l’arbitraire du signe), s<strong>in</strong>ce<br />

different languages feature different signs for the same the same referent. That is, that relationship is<br />

neither given nor automatic; rather it is grounded solely <strong>in</strong> social conventions. As a result language<br />

should be appraised not <strong>in</strong> its relation to the world but on its own terms, as a system of differential<br />

elements. Signs hold no <strong>in</strong>herent mean<strong>in</strong>g outside of the broader signify<strong>in</strong>g system which they implicitly<br />

br<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to play when used; and that mean<strong>in</strong>g is both yielded and exhausted by the play of difference<br />

between them. The mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘hot’ is given by contrast with ‘cold’ and vice versa, and on its own the<br />

phoneme ‘hot’ does not trigger any mean<strong>in</strong>gful association <strong>in</strong> the m<strong>in</strong>d of someone who does not speak<br />

English. Thus mean<strong>in</strong>g, signification, emerges from a cont<strong>in</strong>gent relationship between signifiers.<br />

Lacan’s blended together the l<strong>in</strong>guistic turn <strong>in</strong> philosophy with Saussure’s work on the l<strong>in</strong>guistic<br />

sign, on whose term<strong>in</strong>ology he drew extensively. Saussure’s analysis of language as a structured system<br />

provided the matrix for Lacan’s central contribution to psychoanalytic knowledge, the discovery of the<br />

structure of the unconscious. Contrary to naturalist <strong>in</strong>terpretations that developed <strong>in</strong> the wake of<br />

Freud’s discovery, though his cl<strong>in</strong>ical practice Lacan established that the unconscious was not simply the<br />

recipient of bl<strong>in</strong>d biological drives.<br />

18<br />

<strong>In</strong>stead it too presents a basic structure ak<strong>in</strong> to the structure of<br />

language as revealed by Saussure (l’<strong>in</strong>conscient est structuré comme un language). <strong>In</strong> that sense it<br />

cannot be <strong>in</strong>terpreted as the pre-social or natural site with<strong>in</strong> the human psyche.<br />

The effect of Saussure’s discovery was to cast the focus upon the signifier, and its relationship to<br />

other signifiers, rather than on the relationship between the signifier and the signified. <strong>In</strong> his wake the<br />

17 A sign <strong>in</strong> Saussurian l<strong>in</strong>guistics is composed of a signifier and a signified. Importantly, the signified is<br />

not the real object denoted by the sign – the referent – but a psychological entity, a mental<br />

representation of the object.<br />

18 Which is not to say that Lacan denies that the vital energy mobilized by the drives; but rather these<br />

are not reducible to biological mechanisms alone. What dist<strong>in</strong>guishes them from biological needs is that<br />

they can never be satisfied (see Lacan 1964).<br />

24


signifier takes center stage <strong>in</strong> Lacan. But what is known as ‘the primacy of the signifier’ <strong>in</strong> Lacanian<br />

thought (la primauté du signifiant) implies someth<strong>in</strong>g more. <strong>In</strong> Saussure, the world out there rema<strong>in</strong>s a<br />

distant referent for the signified. Lacan goes one step further still <strong>in</strong> shear<strong>in</strong>g the relationship between<br />

the signifier and the signified, and <strong>in</strong> cast<strong>in</strong>g the focus upon the signifier alone. Lacan f<strong>in</strong>ds that what the<br />

signifier uttered by the <strong>in</strong>dividual is conjur<strong>in</strong>g is not always merely the world out there. Recall here that<br />

his perspective is the <strong>in</strong>dividual and her speech (la parole, <strong>in</strong> the Saussurian term<strong>in</strong>ology), as opposed to<br />

the collective perspective of Saussure and the philosophers of language (la langue). Not only does it not<br />

straightforwardly mirror the world out there (as <strong>in</strong> Saussure 1916), but, for Lacan, that speech also<br />

po<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>in</strong>stead to the <strong>in</strong>ner world of the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject, the unconscious level of <strong>in</strong>articulate desires.<br />

Hence what the signifier can capture, and <strong>in</strong> fact what it alone can capture, is her desire; that same<br />

desire that the analyst seeks to tease out from amidst the mesh of images, identifications, and<br />

repressive mechanisms, <strong>in</strong> order to shepherd it towards symbolization. Bound up as it is with vital<br />

energy and basic needs, that desire is forever express<strong>in</strong>g itself; often at the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s expense, notably<br />

<strong>in</strong> so called Freudian slips or actes manqués. The task of the analyst is thus to hear the desire that<br />

sometimes eludes the analysand and yet expresses itself <strong>in</strong> her speech. The analyst is listen<strong>in</strong>g out for<br />

the key signifiers, expressive of another level of signification, that erupt at times through the<br />

analysand’s speech, and work both at the surface level of what the analysand <strong>in</strong>tends to say (often<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g about the world), while also offer<strong>in</strong>g a w<strong>in</strong>dow onto her unconscious. Piec<strong>in</strong>g these together<br />

she can beg<strong>in</strong> to map out the cha<strong>in</strong>s of significations structur<strong>in</strong>g the person’s desire.<br />

On the one hand Lacan’s analytical thought and practice foregrounds primacy of the signifier, on<br />

the other Hobbes’s political treaty features one primary signifier, the Leviathan. These Lacanian<br />

conceptualizations of the symbolic and the signifier provide the start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts for develop<strong>in</strong>g the first<br />

part of my argument, which is that the Leviathan is the signifier of the symbolic order at large.<br />

25


Part III: The Leviathan as the signifier of the symbolic<br />

<strong>In</strong> this section I show how the Leviathan functions as the signifier of the symbolic order itself, by way of<br />

two different theories of language, that of Lacan and speech act theory. Start<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the state of nature,<br />

argument unfolds follow<strong>in</strong>g the movement of the Hobbesian narrative itself, out of that state.<br />

The State of Nature, Where the Sound and Fury Signify Noth<strong>in</strong>g<br />

An <strong>in</strong>herent disconnect between the signifier and the signified lies at the core of Hobbes’s moral<br />

philosophy and of what John Watk<strong>in</strong>s (1989, 104) has called his ‘humpty dumpty theory of mean<strong>in</strong>g’.<br />

This resonates strongly with Lacan’s conception of language. <strong>In</strong> the state of nature, which, as Watk<strong>in</strong>s<br />

(1989, 104) puts it, ‘consists of a multitude of humpty dumpties’, words mean only what the utterer<br />

<strong>in</strong>tends them to. Consider this well-known passage from Leviathan’s (1946, 32) chapter VI:<br />

But whatsoever is the object of any man’s appetite or desire, that is it which he for his<br />

part calleth good: and the object of his hate and aversion, evil; and of his contempt, vile<br />

and <strong>in</strong>considerable. For these words of good, evil, and contemptible, are ever used with<br />

relation to the person that useth them: there be<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g simply and absolutely so;<br />

nor any common rule of good and evil, to be taken from the nature of the objects<br />

themselves; but from the person of man, where there is not commonwealth; or, <strong>in</strong> a<br />

commonwealth, from the person that representeth it (…)<br />

That, <strong>in</strong> the state of nature, the mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘good’ and ‘evil’ are to be taken from the ‘person of man<br />

[sic]’ po<strong>in</strong>ts uncannily <strong>in</strong> the same direction than Lacan’s signifier. Signifiers here are naturally empty;<br />

and <strong>in</strong> the state of nature they are appropriated by <strong>in</strong>dividuals for whatever suits their purpose, s<strong>in</strong>ce <strong>in</strong><br />

it noth<strong>in</strong>g fixes moral predicates to a set of commonly accepted mean<strong>in</strong>gs of what constitutes the good.<br />

That is precisely the role of the Leviathan. 19<br />

The state of nature is, <strong>in</strong> the strongest possible sense, a space of mean<strong>in</strong>glessness. No collective<br />

action is possible. Humans cannot understand each other s<strong>in</strong>ce the same words hold different mean<strong>in</strong>gs<br />

19 A century ahead of Kant, the Leviathan is also a personification of the Kantian moral imperative and<br />

thus the found<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for the law.<br />

26


for every person. While there are utterances (s<strong>in</strong>ce Hobbes’ natural man seems speak) there is <strong>in</strong> fact no<br />

language, <strong>in</strong> the sense of a collective, transmittable sets of mean<strong>in</strong>g that can provide the basis of a<br />

common understand<strong>in</strong>g and thus for collective action. <strong>In</strong> the state of nature there is only sound and<br />

fury, signify<strong>in</strong>g noth<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

This mean<strong>in</strong>gless or topsy-turvism also constitutes the most robust objection to tak<strong>in</strong>g the state<br />

of nature at face value as the found<strong>in</strong>g paradigm for apprais<strong>in</strong>g the space of <strong>in</strong>ter-state relations.<br />

Tempt<strong>in</strong>g though the image may be that space is not quite populated by ‘a multitude of humpty<br />

dumpties’, and history, as amply emphasized by <strong>in</strong> English School read<strong>in</strong>gs of Hobbes, has provided<br />

sufficient evidence of successful collective action between states. <strong>In</strong> that space language and mean<strong>in</strong>g<br />

still obta<strong>in</strong>; that is, despite the multiplicity of languages, the possibility, if not always the actuality, of a<br />

common understand<strong>in</strong>g rema<strong>in</strong>s.<br />

<strong>In</strong> this read<strong>in</strong>g, what the state of nature represents is the solipsistic world of the <strong>in</strong>fant,<br />

etymologically the pre-speak<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g (<strong>in</strong>-fans). 20<br />

The <strong>in</strong>dividual that Hobbes’ natural <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

captures, then, is not even the child, but the <strong>in</strong>fant, a po<strong>in</strong>t to which I return below. An implication of<br />

that argument here is that apprehend<strong>in</strong>g the state (<strong>in</strong> realism) or the <strong>in</strong>dividual (<strong>in</strong> rational choice<br />

theory) on the model of Hobbes’s ‘natural man’ [sic] is tantamount to <strong>in</strong>fantiliz<strong>in</strong>g them, <strong>in</strong> the sense of<br />

negat<strong>in</strong>g the constitutive and central role of language <strong>in</strong> their ability to act politically.<br />

The Leviathan as The ‘Quilt<strong>in</strong>g Po<strong>in</strong>t’ Fasten<strong>in</strong>g the Social Order<br />

Hobbes’s state of nature thus features the same <strong>in</strong>herently loose relation between the signifier<br />

and signified that characterizes a Lacanian conception of language. <strong>In</strong> Lacan (1956), this constant<br />

slippage is temporarily arrested by what he terms ‘quilt<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts’ (po<strong>in</strong>ts de capiton), or (literally)<br />

upholstery buttons. These constitute key signifiers <strong>in</strong> the discourse of the ‘normal’ (non-psychotic)<br />

20 <strong>in</strong> as <strong>in</strong> prior to; fans as the present participle of fari, to speak.<br />

27


subject that function as anchor<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts, where the signifier and the signified are knotted together. The<br />

analogy here is that the upholstery button is a place where the mattress-maker’s needle has worked to<br />

prevent a shapeless mass of stuff<strong>in</strong>g from shift<strong>in</strong>g about. It becomes the organiz<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t runn<strong>in</strong>g<br />

through broader discourses, a form of overarch<strong>in</strong>g referent po<strong>in</strong>t for multiple <strong>in</strong>dividual utterances; not<br />

unlike the l<strong>in</strong>es radiat<strong>in</strong>g from the upholstery button on the mattress’s surface. While Lacan co<strong>in</strong>ed the<br />

concept to analyse the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s discourse, the concept was developed <strong>in</strong> his wake to analyse political<br />

discourses at large (Laclau and Mouffe 1985, Edk<strong>in</strong>s 1999, Stavrakakis 1999, Zizek 2003). It constitutes a<br />

key signifier that unifies the discursive field, fix<strong>in</strong>g the mean<strong>in</strong>g of otherwise open-ended and often<br />

ambiguous terms, or ‘essentially contested concepts’ as Walter Gallie’s called them (see Gellner 1974<br />

for a discussion), ‘such as ‘freedom’ and ‘democracy’. Slavoj Zizek (2003, 282), for example, shows how,<br />

under communism, certa<strong>in</strong> signifiers, such as ‘democracy’, ‘freedom’ and ‘the state’, acquired a<br />

particular mean<strong>in</strong>g when ‘quilted’ by the signifier/po<strong>in</strong>t de capiton ‘communism’. The same words rang<br />

quite differently <strong>in</strong> the West where they were ‘quilted’ otherwise.<br />

These signifiers, however, designate a political order, not the order underly<strong>in</strong>g the possibility of<br />

politics itself. This is precisely what Hobbes nailed with the Leviathan. What the signifier-Leviathan<br />

designates <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’s political thought is noth<strong>in</strong>g short of the symbolic itself. As such, and albeit to<br />

Schmitt’s dismay, it has to be open-ended, its mean<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>exhaustible. It necessarily eludes all attempts<br />

to p<strong>in</strong> it down to a set number of signified, because it operates as the master signifier that designates<br />

the symbolic at large. Just as the ‘quilt<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t’ is the po<strong>in</strong>t at which a signifier is knotted to the<br />

otherwise <strong>in</strong>determ<strong>in</strong>ate and float<strong>in</strong>g signified, the Leviathan is the <strong>in</strong>stance that fastens the otherwise<br />

ever shift<strong>in</strong>g and always relative mean<strong>in</strong>g of ‘good’ to a fixed, objective and commonly agreed upon set<br />

of understand<strong>in</strong>gs as to what constitutes the Good.<br />

28


Importantly, this needs to be understood aga<strong>in</strong>st Hobbes’s broader theory of language<br />

developed two chapters prior to this passage, <strong>in</strong> his Chapter IV, ‘Of Speech’. Hobbes <strong>in</strong>sistence on the<br />

‘necessity of def<strong>in</strong>itions’ makes it clear that this is a feature of language as a whole and not merely of<br />

moral predicates. This fasten<strong>in</strong>g together of signifiers and signifieds is a precondition for language to be<br />

able to function as the effective social bond that can conta<strong>in</strong> the threat of disorder perta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g to the<br />

natural state. The Leviathan is this fasten<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>stance.<br />

This enables us to revisit <strong>in</strong> a new light is readily most notorious passage of Hobbes (1946, 82)<br />

political treatise for IR, the passage <strong>in</strong> Chapter XIII describ<strong>in</strong>g the state of nature:<br />

<strong>In</strong> such condition, there is no place for <strong>in</strong>dustry; because the fruit thereof is uncerta<strong>in</strong>:<br />

and consequently no culture of the earth; no navigation, nor use of the commodities<br />

that may be imported by the sea; no commodious build<strong>in</strong>g; no <strong>in</strong>struments of mov<strong>in</strong>g,<br />

and remov<strong>in</strong>g, such th<strong>in</strong>gs as require much force; no knowledge of the face of the earth,<br />

no account of time; no arts; no letters; no society; and which is worst of all, cont<strong>in</strong>ual<br />

fear, and danger of violent death; and the life of man [sic], solitary, poor, nasty, brutish<br />

and short.<br />

The grammatical negative, functions here, to draw on a photographic metaphor, as the negative vis-à-vis<br />

the pr<strong>in</strong>t. The f<strong>in</strong>al picture of the state of nature captures exactly <strong>in</strong>verted what makes the symbolic<br />

order itself. <strong>In</strong>deed Hobbes is careful to <strong>in</strong>clude the major card<strong>in</strong>al po<strong>in</strong>ts undergird<strong>in</strong>g social life:<br />

markers of time and space, the possibility of cultivat<strong>in</strong>g the earth and <strong>in</strong>deed all cultural productions,<br />

the possibility of knowledge and <strong>in</strong>deed all peaceful <strong>in</strong>teractions (<strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g at the <strong>in</strong>ternational level).<br />

The Leviathan, <strong>in</strong> turn, is the centre po<strong>in</strong>t of that symbolic order. It both refers to (signifies) and makes<br />

possible the symbolic order itself: it is the master signifier that guarantees the possibility of all<br />

signification.<br />

The Performativity of the Leviathan<br />

The performativity of the symbol Leviathan achieves can also be illum<strong>in</strong>ated from with<strong>in</strong> speech<br />

act theory. It operates on two different levels, on the level of what Hobbes achieved, first, and second,<br />

29


<strong>in</strong> terms of what the Leviathan achieves. With regards to the first, as Patricia Spr<strong>in</strong>gboard (1995, 353)<br />

notes, Hobbes is credited for ‘lexical <strong>in</strong>novation’ by the Oxford English Dictionary for co<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g what<br />

became common currency <strong>in</strong> the English language for represent<strong>in</strong>g the British Commonwealth. His<br />

creative act consisted <strong>in</strong> ty<strong>in</strong>g together the concrete biblical image (the whale) with this abstract political<br />

notion (a commonwealth). As for the second, John Watk<strong>in</strong>s (1989, 111) for his part has underl<strong>in</strong>ed the<br />

ways <strong>in</strong> which speech and action are co-extensive <strong>in</strong> the figure of the Leviathan. 21<br />

‘<strong>In</strong> declar<strong>in</strong>g<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g to be right or wrong, a sovereign is not describ<strong>in</strong>g it or mak<strong>in</strong>g a statement about it. His<br />

declaration is, to use John Aust<strong>in</strong>’s term, a “performative”’. The function of the Leviathan, <strong>in</strong> other<br />

words, is not merely one of reveal<strong>in</strong>g a pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g natural or div<strong>in</strong>e order (as <strong>in</strong> correspondence theory<br />

of the world), but of actual constitution. There are thus two parallel levels of constitution at play.<br />

Hobbes’s sovereigns actually ‘make the th<strong>in</strong>gs they command [sic]’. What the leviathan makes, above all<br />

is the social order itself, that which makes possible all ulterior conventions.<br />

Tak<strong>in</strong>g this l<strong>in</strong>e of argument beyond Watk<strong>in</strong>s (1989) and <strong>in</strong>deed Aust<strong>in</strong> (1962) himself, the type<br />

of performative power implied <strong>in</strong> the sovereign speech act could be said to be pre-locutionary. It is not<br />

simply an act that is supported by social conventions, as <strong>in</strong> illocutionary acts (such as the judge who<br />

pronounces a sentence). Rather, it is one that makes all social conventions possible <strong>in</strong> the first place. It is<br />

also therefore what enables perlocutionary acts to take effect (acts that operate by way of consequence<br />

rather than conventions per se, as <strong>in</strong> offend<strong>in</strong>g someone by <strong>in</strong>sult<strong>in</strong>g them), to name the other key type<br />

of speech act <strong>in</strong> speech act theory. Watk<strong>in</strong>s for his part develops his argument by way of the act of<br />

nam<strong>in</strong>g, compar<strong>in</strong>g the Leviathan’s speech act to that of the clergyman who christens a child.<br />

Remarkably, <strong>in</strong> a Lacanian perspective, the act of nam<strong>in</strong>g is precisely what <strong>in</strong>scribes the child <strong>in</strong>to the<br />

22<br />

22 For a different critique of Watk<strong>in</strong>’s use of performatives see Weiler 1970.<br />

30


symbolic order. This <strong>in</strong>itial <strong>in</strong>scription (whether performed by a clergyman or not) is what makes all<br />

social existence and <strong>in</strong>deed identity possible for the <strong>in</strong>dividual, as we will see <strong>in</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g section.<br />

However the clergyman operates on pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g conventions. The Leviathan, for its part, is the signifier<br />

that ‘names’ the symbolic order; that is, it br<strong>in</strong>gs <strong>in</strong>to existence the symbolic order itself. Thus far ahead<br />

of Lacan, <strong>in</strong> co<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g the symbol Hobbes names the <strong>in</strong>stance that makes all nam<strong>in</strong>g possible. The<br />

Leviathan is, to sum up the argument so far, the signifier that makes all signification possible.<br />

The Leviathan as the Master Signifier that Makes All Signification Possible<br />

The Leviathan as Lacan’s Other<br />

The function that the Leviathan performs at the collective level is that it is the master signifier<br />

that designates the symbolic at large – and thus the very possibility of such a level exist<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the first<br />

place. The second movement of my argument concerns the function it performs at the <strong>in</strong>dividual level. A<br />

key problem for Hobbes was to f<strong>in</strong>d the basis of the relationship between the <strong>in</strong>dividual and the<br />

sovereign with<strong>in</strong> the <strong>in</strong>dividual herself, <strong>in</strong> order to expla<strong>in</strong> and legitimise her entry <strong>in</strong>to the social<br />

contract as an <strong>in</strong>ternal necessity. <strong>In</strong> the words of the historian of political thought Michel Foucault (75,<br />

my translation):<br />

What, <strong>in</strong>deed, was the sovereign (…) for Hobbes? (…) [it was] the <strong>in</strong>stance capable of say<strong>in</strong>g no to<br />

the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s desiderata; the problem then be<strong>in</strong>g how this ‘no’ (…) could be legitimate and<br />

founded <strong>in</strong> this <strong>in</strong>dividual’s very own will.'<br />

Donn<strong>in</strong>g these Lacanian lenses allows us to see the extent to which Hobbes achieves exactly that; and<br />

far more so than Foucault had actually gauged. This part of my argument rests upon the third axis of the<br />

symbolic <strong>in</strong> Lacanian thought, flagged but left under-developed <strong>in</strong> the previous section, the symbolic as<br />

the order of the Other. I first return to flesh out that category <strong>in</strong> order to that show that the Leviathan<br />

designates the Other; which is also to say that it corresponds to the ‘Name of the Father’ <strong>in</strong> the Lacanian<br />

framework.<br />

31


The symbolic, as we have seen, is the order of the Other. The order <strong>in</strong>to which the <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

is <strong>in</strong>itially <strong>in</strong>scribed by be<strong>in</strong>g ‘named <strong>in</strong>to it’ is, <strong>in</strong>itially, fundamentally alien to the speechless <strong>in</strong>fant.<br />

The words that the <strong>in</strong>fant acquires <strong>in</strong>itially belong, quite literally, to a foreign world; an order that<br />

pre-exists it and where these words already hold given mean<strong>in</strong>gs. To learn to speak is to step <strong>in</strong>to this<br />

alien order. The symbolic is that world. It designates the place of the Other, constitut<strong>in</strong>g all at once<br />

the reservoir of pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g signifiers (its ‘treasure chest’ as Lacan (2006, 336) also calls it) and the<br />

orig<strong>in</strong>al addressee, that is, the <strong>in</strong>stance with whom the <strong>in</strong>fant first <strong>in</strong>teracts and <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g with<br />

whom it learns how to speak (the figure of the mother). To speak, to convey mean<strong>in</strong>g (to another<br />

social be<strong>in</strong>g) is only ever to draw upon pre-exist<strong>in</strong>g signifiers. To draw upon, or better said <strong>in</strong> a<br />

Lacanian sense to borrow: becom<strong>in</strong>g a social animal rests on a foundational debt; ‘the Great Debt’ as<br />

Lacan (2006, 74) called it. This is the symbolic debt that one <strong>in</strong>curs <strong>in</strong> borrow<strong>in</strong>g signifiers from the<br />

Other <strong>in</strong> order to be able to be understood, and therefore to be acknowledged as be<strong>in</strong>g part of (and<br />

function<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>) that symbolic order. Lacan (2006, 66-67) emphasises the mythical orig<strong>in</strong> of the<br />

‘symbol’ as both ‘a gift’ and a ‘pact’ that all at once <strong>in</strong>debts and b<strong>in</strong>ds together those who receive it<br />

(the Argonauts <strong>in</strong> his example), creat<strong>in</strong>g the basic social bond. 23<br />

What, then, underwrites this debt, and whence does it draw its power? This ‘stepp<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to’<br />

the Symbolic is not merely the acquisition of a positive, dist<strong>in</strong>ctly human, neurological capacity of<br />

speech a la Chomsky (1981). To the contrary, what Lacan draws out is that it is premised on a<br />

constitutive loss. Alienation with<strong>in</strong> the symbolic order is a basic condition of one’s becom<strong>in</strong>g a social<br />

23 Rites and celebrations, such as Christmas celebrations, offer a good place to observe the symbolic<br />

reproduce itself. The giv<strong>in</strong>g of gifts, to children <strong>in</strong> particular, can be read as <strong>in</strong>stantiat<strong>in</strong>g, with a happy<br />

face, the debt that is be<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>curred by their <strong>in</strong>sertion <strong>in</strong>to the symbolic order, by their becom<strong>in</strong>g<br />

adults (which will then lead them to ‘give back’ to other children <strong>in</strong> order to observe the rite, and<br />

thereby <strong>in</strong> turn partake <strong>in</strong> the further perpetuation of the symbolic).<br />

32


e<strong>in</strong>g. Lacan captures this foundational loss, or lack, with his concept of castration. To be clear, it has<br />

noth<strong>in</strong>g to do with the physical act of mutilation; we are not here <strong>in</strong> the realm of the real here but<br />

rather with<strong>in</strong> the symbolic. This is <strong>in</strong> fact the concept that centrally underp<strong>in</strong>s. It captures the orig<strong>in</strong>al<br />

forsak<strong>in</strong>g that each of us undergoes <strong>in</strong> order to accede to language.<br />

Subsequently, however, we forever uncomfortably straddle these two realms, the realm of<br />

immediate, preverbal experience (the world of raw needs, impulses, frustrations, anger and joy; of<br />

the imag<strong>in</strong>ary and the real); and the mediated realm of the symbolic, <strong>in</strong>to which we must first be<br />

<strong>in</strong>tegrated <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong> order to express that experience. But to be able to express it is also to loose it <strong>in</strong> its<br />

raw, immediate form; here<strong>in</strong> lies the constitutive split that marks the tragedy of the human condition.<br />

Words can never completely convey exactly what the speaker wants to say. For it to be said it must<br />

be mediated by words that belong to everyone, words that hold generic mean<strong>in</strong>gs and are thus<br />

fundamentally ill-fitted for that unique and immediate impulse that led the subject to want to speak<br />

<strong>in</strong> the first place. As Lacan put it <strong>in</strong> his (1977) famous quips, ‘the th<strong>in</strong>g must be lost <strong>in</strong> order to be<br />

expressed’, or aga<strong>in</strong> that ‘speech is the murder of the th<strong>in</strong>g’. The ‘th<strong>in</strong>g’ <strong>in</strong> its orig<strong>in</strong>al, raw<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividualised form must be rel<strong>in</strong>quished so as to be fitted <strong>in</strong>to exist<strong>in</strong>g signifiers and thereby<br />

communicated. This forsak<strong>in</strong>g is a condition of entry <strong>in</strong>to the symbolic; it is what one gives up <strong>in</strong> order<br />

to be able to become a social, speak<strong>in</strong>g be<strong>in</strong>g. ‘Man [sic] speaks, then, but it is because the symbol<br />

has made him man’ (Lacan 2006, 72)<br />

The Social Contract as Castration and the Leviathan as the ‘Name of the Father’<br />

This symbolic debt casts a new light on the depths that, I argue, Hobbes plumbs with the<br />

understand<strong>in</strong>g of the social contract he puts forward. First, <strong>in</strong> contract<strong>in</strong>g with the Leviathan, the<br />

<strong>in</strong>dividual forsakes her liberty <strong>in</strong> exchange for secur<strong>in</strong>g her life and, centrally, be<strong>in</strong>g rid of the fear of<br />

death. That fundamental freedom, I argue, is that which perta<strong>in</strong>s to the realm of immediate<br />

33


experience and unimpeded desires. Hobbes ‘natural man’ is the creature that does exactly as it<br />

pleases, takes exactly what its wants, call<strong>in</strong>g whatever suits its momentary appetite ‘good’ and<br />

whatever displeases him, ‘evil’. It wanders without any moral compass, his wants unh<strong>in</strong>dered. What<br />

Hobbes offers, I suggest, is fact a phantasmatical representation of the pre-verbal <strong>in</strong>dividual prior to<br />

its encounter with the symbolic and castration tak<strong>in</strong>g hold. Hobbes state of nature is an apt depiction<br />

of the world of Lacan’s <strong>in</strong>fant who, unaware of its limit, experiences itself as all-powerful. Its<br />

primordial liberty is what is ‘lost’ <strong>in</strong> order to enter the social order; but it is also, however, a<br />

fantasmatical liberty, an expression of this illusion of omnipotence. Seen <strong>in</strong> this light, what Hobbes<br />

draws out perhaps more than any other social contract theorist is the extreme vulnerability that<br />

‘natural man’ is <strong>in</strong>, which direly drives him <strong>in</strong>to enter<strong>in</strong>g the contract with the Leviathan. That ‘fear of<br />

death’ is a fundamental fear, ak<strong>in</strong> to that of the slave <strong>in</strong> Hegel’s master-slave relationship. It is not just<br />

the fear of dy<strong>in</strong>g after hav<strong>in</strong>g lived a free life. It is the fear of not be<strong>in</strong>g able to live <strong>in</strong> the first place, to<br />

establish oneself as an autonomous self.<br />

<strong>In</strong> this light, then, <strong>in</strong> the contract that is passed between the <strong>in</strong>dividual and the Leviathan, the<br />

Leviathan is, much more fundamentally than has been recognised, the Other upon whom the self<br />

fundamentally depends <strong>in</strong> order to acquire the means to become herself. That contract serves to<br />

<strong>in</strong>stitute not merely the subject of the monarch, not merely the political subject (or the subject of a<br />

certa<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>d of political order). Rather it founds the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject itself. It constitutes the <strong>in</strong>dividual<br />

as political animal. This is the true mean<strong>in</strong>g of that symbolic pact: it is an exchange of the freedom to<br />

do however one pleases aga<strong>in</strong>st language and the ability to act politically. It is underwritten, and<br />

here<strong>in</strong> lies Hobbes’ Lacanian <strong>in</strong>sight, by a symbol, the Leviathan.<br />

34


<strong>In</strong> Lacanian thought, one signifier <strong>in</strong> particular performs a similar function, which he terms<br />

‘the name of the father’. 24 Lacan (1956) elaborates the concept notion <strong>in</strong> the same sem<strong>in</strong>ar III where<br />

he co<strong>in</strong>s the concept of ‘quilt<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>ts’. He realises that there is a signifier more fundamental still,<br />

one that ‘holds no signifier’ (Lacan 1975, 74 my translation). This is properly the master signifier, or<br />

‘pure signifier’ as Juranville (1984) captures it, <strong>in</strong> that it attaches to no particular signified but <strong>in</strong>stead<br />

encompasses them all. It is the <strong>in</strong>stance underwrites all other signifiers, all cha<strong>in</strong>s of signification. It is<br />

what makes mean<strong>in</strong>g possible <strong>in</strong> the first place.<br />

Return<strong>in</strong>g to developmental perspective to flesh out this complex concept, the father is the<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance that triangulates the mother-child relationship and thereby opens it up to the symbolic.<br />

The father breaks the symbiosis between mother and child. This constitutes an essential loss; but it is<br />

also what ushers the child <strong>in</strong>to the symbolic order and thereby <strong>in</strong>stitutes the possibility of<br />

symboliz<strong>in</strong>g, of speak<strong>in</strong>g. Subsequently, this <strong>in</strong>stance detaches from the actual father <strong>in</strong> this<br />

primordial configuration, and becomes the Other that supports all social relationships, all possibility<br />

of <strong>in</strong>teraction between a ‘self’ and an ‘other’. Hence why it a signifier, ‘the name of the father’. It is<br />

the signifier that designates the order of Other and, <strong>in</strong> do<strong>in</strong>g so, underwrites the possibility of<br />

signification itself. <strong>In</strong> Hobbes’s world that signifier is none other than the Leviathan, the <strong>in</strong>stance that<br />

makes possible two units <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g with one another with a set of shared mean<strong>in</strong>gs.<br />

25<br />

The State as Speak<strong>in</strong>g Subject: Conclusions For IR Theory<br />

24 To be specific, Lacan terms it at different stages of theoretical development, ‘The Name-of-the-<br />

Father’, ‘master signifier’ or ‘S1’. These terms are thus <strong>in</strong>terchangeable at this f<strong>in</strong>al stage of my<br />

argument.<br />

25 To clarify, the mother (once aga<strong>in</strong>, as a figure <strong>in</strong> the structure of the relationship, not as a real person)<br />

is the imag<strong>in</strong>ary other, that is, the very first other, <strong>in</strong> the realm of identification and imag<strong>in</strong>ary capture;<br />

where as the father constitutes properly the Other).<br />

35


Read<strong>in</strong>g Hobbes through Lacan sh<strong>in</strong>es a drastically different light upon the <strong>in</strong>dividual that has stood <strong>in</strong><br />

the discipl<strong>in</strong>e’s sights ever s<strong>in</strong>ce it turned to Hobbes’ state of nature for its first cues about the<br />

structure of the <strong>in</strong>ternational system (<strong>in</strong> realism); and that rema<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> its sights even when it moved<br />

away from Hobbes to further distil the essence of these unit’s selves (<strong>in</strong> constructivism). Specifically, it<br />

restores the half of the Hobbesian <strong>in</strong>dividual that was hidden by IR’s lenses be<strong>in</strong>g fastened upon the<br />

state of nature alone. The key realist <strong>in</strong>sight that does carry over <strong>in</strong>to a Lacanian read<strong>in</strong>g is that the<br />

agonistic relations dramatized by his mythical nature, that state of permanent and latent warfare<br />

between the units, is constitutive and it is structural. Where the Lacanian read<strong>in</strong>g departs from<br />

realism, however, is that, with Hobbes’ full picture and the Leviathan back <strong>in</strong> sights, that unit is not a<br />

discrete, self-conta<strong>in</strong>ed entity or billiard ball; nor does it consequently yield an atomistic billiard board<br />

of utility-maximis<strong>in</strong>g units – whether collid<strong>in</strong>g or roll<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the same direction.<br />

This <strong>in</strong>dividualist conception of the <strong>in</strong>dividual, for which Hobbes’ ‘natural man’ was first<br />

marshalled by rationalism, and which has not been entirely shaken off by constructivism’s concept of<br />

the ‘self’, actually falls short of appreciat<strong>in</strong>g just how far Hobbes reaches <strong>in</strong> foreground<strong>in</strong>g the fear of<br />

death as prime mover of this ‘natural man’s’ behaviour. This fear is <strong>in</strong>deed what drives the <strong>in</strong>dividual,<br />

and subsequently for realism, states, to seek security as their primary objective, to echo Aron’s (1966,<br />

72) words. But it is also what drives the <strong>in</strong>dividual to not dwell <strong>in</strong> the state of nature at all. Hence<br />

freez<strong>in</strong>g the narrative at this po<strong>in</strong>t to uphold only the state of nature <strong>in</strong> focus makes little sense. What<br />

is to be found there, a Lacanian read<strong>in</strong>g reveals, is noth<strong>in</strong>g but a wordless <strong>in</strong>fant, a naked be<strong>in</strong>g<br />

stripped of the trapp<strong>in</strong>gs of agency, a pre-actor, whose life would be very short <strong>in</strong>deed. The rational<br />

actor, for its part, that is, an actor presumably equipped with the means to act – who can, say, talk<br />

and walk, at the very least – is the one who leaves the state of nature as quickly as possible and<br />

contracts with the Leviathan <strong>in</strong> order to stay alive. That is the rational th<strong>in</strong>g to do. That survival is at<br />

stake is true <strong>in</strong> a fundamental, constitutive sense. It is what constitutes the <strong>in</strong>dividual per se; not a<br />

36


‘natural man’ or a powerless wordless <strong>in</strong>fant, but the full-blown <strong>in</strong>dividual, complete with the<br />

trapp<strong>in</strong>gs of agency. But it also means that the actor, the <strong>in</strong>stance who enters <strong>in</strong>to <strong>in</strong>teractions with<br />

other actors, is always already a social be<strong>in</strong>g, who does not exist outside of its relation to the<br />

Leviathan-Other. It is, <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’ dramatization, simply crushed by all the dangers that loom <strong>in</strong> the<br />

state of nature.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g a new basis for elaborat<strong>in</strong>g human agency first requires restor<strong>in</strong>g these two halves to<br />

Hobbes’ <strong>in</strong>dividual, his ‘natural man’ and his political, that is to say, speak<strong>in</strong>g subject. The picture thus<br />

emerg<strong>in</strong>g overlies Lacan’s subject. It reveals an <strong>in</strong>dividual fundamentally split between these two<br />

realms, the realm of immediate, unimpeded impulses (here is the state of nature) and the symbolic,<br />

the realm of language and the social; but also, importantly, an <strong>in</strong>dividual who (<strong>in</strong> normal<br />

circumstances) is not so rent between these two as to be reduced to paralysis. The speak<strong>in</strong>g subject<br />

forever straddles these two realms, one foot <strong>in</strong> either. That tension is the motor of her desire. As I<br />

have shown extensively elsewhere, because it centrally foregrounds the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s desire (as does<br />

Hobbes’), Lacan’s theorisation avoids the critique levelled at certa<strong>in</strong> post-structuralist theories of the<br />

subject, notably <strong>in</strong> the wake of Michel Foucault, for elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g agency (Epste<strong>in</strong> 2010). Lacan’s is<br />

<strong>in</strong>deed a fully-fledged theory of agency, only one that carefully circumscribes where the subject acts,<br />

and where she is acted upon by the structures, social and l<strong>in</strong>guistic, with<strong>in</strong> which she is enmeshed; <strong>in</strong><br />

accordance with a structurationist social theory. It is precisely because theirs are theories that centre<br />

upon this dynamic component of the human psyche, desire, that Lacan and Hobbes need to be<br />

reckoned with <strong>in</strong> apprais<strong>in</strong>g agency. Desire, <strong>in</strong> both Lacan and Hobbes, is the eng<strong>in</strong>e, not of the<br />

natural <strong>in</strong>dividual (that was the fear of death, <strong>in</strong> Hobbes) but of human agency itself – that is, of the<br />

whole of the <strong>in</strong>dividual rather than only half. Hobbes’ desire for power that so captured the<br />

37


imag<strong>in</strong>ation of the discipl<strong>in</strong>e’s found<strong>in</strong>g fathers is a desire to secure the means of one’s agency. 26 It is<br />

a desire for potency rather than for (material) power as conceptualised <strong>in</strong> IR. The splitt<strong>in</strong>g, that is<br />

dramatized <strong>in</strong> Hobbes by leav<strong>in</strong>g the state of nature and contract<strong>in</strong>g with the Leviathan, is<br />

constitutive of the <strong>in</strong>dividual’s desire and of her ability to act <strong>in</strong> the world<br />

Second, however, f<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g a different foundation for theoris<strong>in</strong>g agency <strong>in</strong> IR also means<br />

com<strong>in</strong>g to terms with this foundational dependence of the self upon the Other; rather than revert<strong>in</strong>g<br />

to an <strong>in</strong>dividualist ontology that posits an autonomous, soveregn ‘Self’ <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g with a discrete<br />

‘Other’. The self-other relations that underp<strong>in</strong> constructivism’s social theory feature an alreadyconstituted<br />

‘Self’ encounter<strong>in</strong>g an already constituted ‘Other’ and <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g more or less friendlily<br />

with it, accord<strong>in</strong>g to their respective background histories, cultures etc. (Wendt 1999, 246-312). What<br />

is be<strong>in</strong>g confused here <strong>in</strong> Lacanian terms is the small ‘other’ (other social actors) with ‘the Other’<br />

underp<strong>in</strong>n<strong>in</strong>g the social order itself, impersonated <strong>in</strong> Hobbes’ drama by the Leviathan. Yet this<br />

Lacanian read<strong>in</strong>g of Hobbes speaks to constructivism’s central concern with constitution. It lays the<br />

foundation for a type of social theoris<strong>in</strong>g that centrally foregrounds the mutual constitution of the<br />

units and the system, but not merely at the po<strong>in</strong>t of orig<strong>in</strong>, soon to be forgotten as the units are then<br />

considered as discrete <strong>in</strong>teract<strong>in</strong>g entities. It draws the dependence of the self upon the Other as an<br />

ongo<strong>in</strong>g feature of political order itself. More than a social, <strong>in</strong> the sense entrenched by<br />

constructivism, his is a deeply relational ontology. With Hobbes and Lacan the social construction of<br />

the units and the systems f<strong>in</strong>ally runs all the way down.<br />

26 The realist legacy confuses the means of the desire for power with its ends. The key chapter here is<br />

chapter 11, and the key sentence (Hobbes p.70?):<br />

And the cause of this , is not alwayes that a man hopes for a more <strong>in</strong>tensive delight, than he has already<br />

atta<strong>in</strong>ed to; or that he cannot be content with a moderate power: but because he cannot assure the power<br />

and means to live well, which he hath present, without acquisition of more.<br />

The quest for more (goods or power) is not about the acquisition of more goods or power per se but<br />

rather about keep<strong>in</strong>g desire itself, the eng<strong>in</strong>e of human agency, <strong>in</strong> motion.<br />

38


Ultimately, what this read<strong>in</strong>g of Hobbes drew out is that the speak<strong>in</strong>g subject, theorised by<br />

Jacques Lacan and operationalised <strong>in</strong> discursive approaches, provides a theoretically coherent and<br />

methodologically parsimonious basis for conceptualis<strong>in</strong>g agency <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>ternational politics. On the one<br />

hand it harbours a specific conception of the <strong>in</strong>dividual as a divided, speak<strong>in</strong>g subject, as we have<br />

seen. On other, however, as I have shown extensively elsewhere (Epste<strong>in</strong> 2010) the purchase of this<br />

concept empirically is that it actually suspends all these ontological considerations, and provides a<br />

parsimonious way of cont<strong>in</strong>u<strong>in</strong>g to explore identity concerns. The parsimony stems from the absence<br />

of hav<strong>in</strong>g to hold any presumptions regard<strong>in</strong>g the actor’s selves. Discursive approaches consider<br />

simply what the actors say, <strong>in</strong> order to know, not just who they are, but what they achieve. This,<br />

moreover, is what enables the analysis to move beyond IR’s characteristic state-centrism: the actors<br />

com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>to focus are simply those that have made a difference <strong>in</strong> a specific area of <strong>in</strong>ternational<br />

politics – whether these be states or Non-Governmental Organizations (see also Epste<strong>in</strong> 2008).<br />

Lastly, to apprehend the actors of <strong>in</strong>ternational politics as speak<strong>in</strong>g subjects opens up the<br />

question of the nature of the structures <strong>in</strong> <strong>in</strong>terest<strong>in</strong>g ways. First, no more than constructivism does it<br />

preclude considerations of the material structures that preoccupied the rationalists. Discursive<br />

approaches are not a totaliz<strong>in</strong>g enterprise that seeks to reduce everyth<strong>in</strong>g to words or to crowd out<br />

the central role of material <strong>in</strong>terests <strong>in</strong> shap<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ternational politics. Rather, they simply casts the<br />

focus upon an additional type of social structures to those already <strong>in</strong> sight, namely the structures of<br />

language themselves. What a careful read<strong>in</strong>g of Hobbes shows is that they grow their roots with<strong>in</strong> IR’s<br />

own foundations.<br />

39


Citations<br />

Aron, Raymond (1966 [1962]), Peace and War. A Theory of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>, London: Weidenfeld and<br />

Nicolson.<br />

Aust<strong>in</strong>, John. 1962. How to Do Th<strong>in</strong>gs with Words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.<br />

Ball, Terence (1985), ‘Hobbes and the L<strong>in</strong>guistic Turn’ Polity, 17,4 739-760<br />

Bially Mattern, Jennifer (2005). Order<strong>in</strong>g <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Politics. Identity, Crisis and Representational Force. New<br />

York: Routledge.<br />

Brams, Steve J. (1985) Rational Politics. Decisions, Games and Strategy Wash<strong>in</strong>gton: CQ Press<br />

Brown, Keith (1980). ‘Thomas Hobbes and the Title Page of Leviathan’, Philosophy, 55, 410-411<br />

Bull, Hedley (1977), ‘Hobbes and the <strong>in</strong>ternational anarchy’, Social Research, 41: 717-738<br />

Bull, Hedley (1995/1977), The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order <strong>in</strong> World Politics, New York: Colombia<br />

University Press, second edition<br />

Buzan, Barry (2004) From <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> To World Society? English school theory and the social structure of<br />

globalization Cambridge: Cambridge University Press<br />

Campbell, D. (1998) Writ<strong>in</strong>g Security: United States Foreign Policy and the Politics of Identity, M<strong>in</strong>neapolis:<br />

University of M<strong>in</strong>nesota Press, 2 nd edition.<br />

Carr, Edward Hallet (1946) The Twenty Year Crisis 1919-1939, 2 nd edition, New York: Harper Perennial<br />

Chomsky, Noam (1981), Lectures on Government and B<strong>in</strong>d<strong>in</strong>g: The Pisa Lectures. Holland: Foris Publications.<br />

Repr<strong>in</strong>t. 7 th Edition. Berl<strong>in</strong> and New York: Mouton de Gruyter, 1993.<br />

Claude, <strong>In</strong>is L. Jr (1962), Power and <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> New York: Random House<br />

40


Drulak, Petr (2010) ‘Polemics: Of Metaphors, Concepts and Reality – A Reply to Onuf’, Perspectives, 18,1, 77-86.<br />

Edk<strong>in</strong>s, Jenny (1999), Poststructuralism and <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>: Br<strong>in</strong>g<strong>in</strong>g the Political Back <strong>In</strong>, Boulder, Co<br />

and London: Lynne Rienner<br />

Epste<strong>in</strong>, Charlotte (2010) ‘Us<strong>in</strong>g Discourse to Study <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>: Can Jacques Lacan Help?’ European<br />

Journal of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> (available as Onl<strong>in</strong>e First)<br />

F<strong>in</strong>nemore, Martha and Sikk<strong>in</strong>k, Katheryn (2001), 'Tak<strong>in</strong>g Stock: the Constructivist Research Program <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> and Comparative Politics', Annual Review <strong>in</strong> Political Science, ', 391-416.<br />

F<strong>in</strong>nemore, Martha. 2001. ‘Export<strong>in</strong>g the English School?’ Review of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Studies 27 (3): 509-513.<br />

Foucault, M (2004). Sécurité, Territoire, Population. Cours au College de France 1977-78, Paris: Gallimard<br />

Freud, Sigmund (1950 [1913]), Totem and Taboo, translated by James Strachey, London: Routledge and Paul<br />

Kegan<br />

Gauthier, David (1969), The Logic of Leviathan Oxford: Oxford University Press<br />

Gauthier, David (1977), ‘The Social Contract as Ideology’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 6, 2, pp.130-164<br />

Gellner, Ernest (1974), ‘The Concept of a Story’, <strong>in</strong> Selected Philosophical Themes. London: Routledge and Paul<br />

Kegan. 95-112.<br />

Goldgeier, J. M. Tetlock, P. E. (2001) 'Psychology and <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> Theory' 67-92 Annual Review of<br />

Political Science 4.<br />

Greenhill, Brian (2008), 'Recognition and Collective Identity Formation <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Politics' European Journal<br />

of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>, 14, 2, 343-368<br />

Hampton, Jean (1986), Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press<br />

41


Hansen, L.(2006), Security As Practice: Discourse Analysis and the Bosnian War, London and New York:<br />

Routledge.<br />

Heller, Marc (1980), ‘The Uses and Abuses of the State of Nature <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>’ Polity,13, 1. 21-32<br />

Hobbes, Thomas (1946 [1651] Leviathan, edited by Michael Oakeshott, Oxford : Basil Blackwell<br />

Howarth, D. (2000) Discourse, Buck<strong>in</strong>gham, Philadelphia: Open University Press<br />

Hymans, Jacques E.C. (2010), ‘The Arrival of Psychological Constructivism’, <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Theory, 2, 461-467<br />

Jahn, Beate (2000), The Cultural Construction of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>: The <strong>In</strong>vention of the State of Nature,<br />

Palgrave Macmillan<br />

Juignet, Patrick (2003), ‘Lacan, le symbolique et le signifiant’, Cl<strong>in</strong>iques Méditerranéennes, 68 :131-144.<br />

Juranville, Ala<strong>in</strong> (1984) Lacan et La Philosophie, Paris : Presses Universitaires de France<br />

Kaplan, Morton (1956) ‘How Sovereign is Hobbes’s Sovereign?’, The Western Political Quarterly, 9,2: 389-405<br />

Katzenste<strong>in</strong>, Peter J. (ed.) (1996)The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity <strong>in</strong> World Politics, New<br />

York: Columbia University Press<br />

Kavka, Gregory (1983) ‘Hobbes War of all Aga<strong>in</strong>st All’ Ethics 93: 291-310<br />

Keohane, R.O (1988), ‘<strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>In</strong>stitutions: Two Approaches’, <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Studies Quarterly, 32,4, 379-96.<br />

Kratochwil, Friedrich (1989), Rules, Norms and Decision. On the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reason<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong><br />

<strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> and Domestic Affairs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press<br />

Lacan, Jacques ( 1964) Sem<strong>in</strong>ar XI, Les Quatre concepts fondamentaux de la Pyschanlayse, orig<strong>in</strong>al transcript<br />

consulted onl<strong>in</strong>e, http://nosubject.com/Jacques_Lacan:Sem<strong>in</strong>ars (last accessed 03/02/2010)<br />

42


Lacan, Jacques (1956), Sem<strong>in</strong>are III, les Psychoses, orig<strong>in</strong>al transcript consulted onl<strong>in</strong>e,<br />

http://nosubject.com/Jacques_Lacan:Sem<strong>in</strong>ars (last accessed 03/02/2010)<br />

Lacan, Jacques (1975), Encore, Paris: Editions du Seuil<br />

Lacan, Jacques (1988) Lacan, Jacques. The Sem<strong>in</strong>ar. Book I. Freud's Papers on Technique, 1953-54. Trans. John<br />

Forrester. New York: Nortion; Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Lacan, Jacques (2006 [1977]) Ecrits: a Selection, translated by Alan Sheridan, London: Tavistock/Routledge<br />

Laclau, Ernesto, and Mouffe, Chantal (1985), Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic<br />

Politics, London and New York: Verso.<br />

Lapid, Yosef and Kratochwil, Friedrich (eds.) (1996) The Return of Culture and Identity <strong>in</strong> IR Theory, Boulder,<br />

Colorado, Lynne Rienner Publishers.<br />

Lebow, Richard N. 2008. A Cultural Theory of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Lynn Doty, R. (2000), ‘Desire All the Way Down’, Review of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Studies, 26, 137-139.<br />

Malcolm, Noel (2002), ‘Hobbes’s Theory of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>’ <strong>in</strong> Aspects of Hobbes, Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press, 432-456<br />

Malcom, Noel (2002), ‘Hobbes’s Theory of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>’, <strong>in</strong> Aspects of Hobbes Oxford: Oxford<br />

University Press, pp432-456.<br />

McLean, Ian (1981), The Social Contract <strong>in</strong> Leviathan and the Prisoner’s Dilemma Supergame’ Political Studies,<br />

29:339-51<br />

Mercer, Jonathan (2005), “Rationality and Psychology <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Politics,” <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong><br />

Organization, vol. 59, pp. 77–106.<br />

Milliken, Jennifer (1999), 'The Study of Discourse <strong>in</strong> <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>: a Critique of Research and Methods,<br />

European Journal of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong>, 5,2, 225-254.<br />

43


Morgenthau, Hans J. (1960), Politics Among Nations. The Struggle for Power and Peace, 3 rd edition, New York:<br />

Alfred A. Knopf<br />

Neal, Patrick (1988), ‘Hobbes and Rational Choice Theory’, The Western Political Quarterly, 41, 4: 635-652<br />

Neumann, Iver (2004), 'Beware of organicism: the narrative self of the state', <strong>in</strong> Review of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Studies,<br />

30, 259-267.<br />

Onuf, Nicholas (1989), World of our Mak<strong>in</strong>g, Columbia, SC: University of South Carol<strong>in</strong>a Press.<br />

Ross, Andrew A.G. (2006) ‘Com<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> From the Cold: Constructivism and Emotions’, European Journal of<br />

<strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> 12, 2, 197-222<br />

Saussure, Ferd<strong>in</strong>and de (1995 [1916]), Cours de l<strong>in</strong>guistique générale, Paris : Editions Payet et Rivage.<br />

Scheuerman, William (2007). Carl Schmitt and Hans Morgenthau: Realism and Beyond, <strong>in</strong> Realism Reconsidered:<br />

the Legacy of Hans Morthenthau, Michael C. Williams (ed.) Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.62-92.<br />

Schmitt, Carl (2008 [1938]), The Leviathan <strong>in</strong> the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Mean<strong>in</strong>g and Failure of A<br />

Political Symbol, translated by George Schwab, Cambridge, Ma.: MIT press.<br />

Schwab, Georges (2008), ‘<strong>In</strong>troduction’ <strong>in</strong> Carl Schmitt, The Leviathan, xxxi-liii<br />

Sk<strong>in</strong>ner, Quent<strong>in</strong> (1996), Reason and Rhetoric <strong>in</strong> the Philosophy of Hobbes Cambridge: CUP<br />

Smith, Michael J. (1986), Realist Thought From Weber to Kiss<strong>in</strong>ger, Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press<br />

Smith, R. M. (2004) 'Identities, <strong>In</strong>terests, and the Future of Political Science', 301-312, Perspective on Politics<br />

Smith, S. (2000), ‘Wendt’s World’, Review of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Studies, 26, 151-163<br />

Souriau, (1990) Vocabulaire d’Esthétique, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France<br />

44


Spr<strong>in</strong>gborg, Patricia (1996), Hobbes’s ‘Biblical Beasts: Leviathan and Behemoth’ Political Theory, 23, 2, 353-375<br />

Stavrakakis, Yannis (1999), Lacan and the Political, London and New York: Routledge<br />

Stillman, Robert E. (1995) ‘Hobbes’s “Leviathan”: Monsters, Metaphors and Magic’, ELH 62, 4, 791-819.<br />

Strong, Tracy, (2008), ‘Carl Schmitt and Thomas Hobbes: Myth and Politics’, <strong>in</strong> Carl Schmitt, The Leviathan, viixxviii<br />

Tuck, Richard (1989) Hobbes Oxford: Oxford University Press.<br />

V<strong>in</strong>cent, John R. (1981) ‘The Hobbesian Tradition <strong>in</strong> Twentieth Century Thought’, Millennium, 10, 2: 91-101.<br />

Walker, R.J.B. (1992), <strong>In</strong>side/Outside: <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> <strong>Relations</strong> as Political Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge<br />

University Press.<br />

Waltz, Kenneth (1969 [1959]) Man, the State and War. A Theoretical Analysis, New York: Columbia University<br />

Press.<br />

Waltz, Kenneth (1979), Theory of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Politics New York: Columbia University Press.<br />

Watk<strong>in</strong>s, John (1989 [1965]), Hobbes’s System of Ideas, London: Gower Publish<strong>in</strong>g/London School of Economics,<br />

2 nd ed.<br />

Weiler, Gershon (1970), Hobbes and Peformatives, Philosophy, 45, 173 (210-220)<br />

Wendt, Alexander. (1999). Social Theory of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.<br />

Wight, Mart<strong>in</strong> (1992) <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Theory: The Three Traditions London: Royal <strong>In</strong>stitute for <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Affairs<br />

Williams, Michael (1996), ‘Hobbes and <strong>in</strong>ternational relations: a reconsideration ’<strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong> Organization, 50,<br />

2, 213-36.<br />

45


Wolfers, Arnold (1962), Discord and Collaboration, Baltimore: John Hopk<strong>in</strong>s Press.<br />

Zehfuss, M. (2001), “Constructivism and Identity: A Dangerous Liaison,” European Journal of <strong><strong>In</strong>ternational</strong><br />

<strong>Relations</strong>, vol. 7, no. 3, pp. 315–348.<br />

Zizek, Slavoj (2003), Jacques Lacan: Society, politics, Ideology, London and New York: Routledge<br />

46

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!