25.12.2013 Views

Handout #3: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 7: Practical Syllogisms ...

Handout #3: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 7: Practical Syllogisms ...

Handout #3: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 7: Practical Syllogisms ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Handout</strong> <strong>#3</strong>: <strong>Aristotle</strong>, <strong>Nicomachean</strong> <strong>Ethics</strong> 7: <strong>Practical</strong> <strong>Syllogisms</strong><br />

Phil 309, Dr. T. Hoffmann<br />

Theoretical syllogism<br />

All mammals are animals<br />

All horses are mammals<br />

_________________________<br />

All horses are animals<br />

Theoretical syllogism<br />

All brownies are delicious<br />

This is a brownie<br />

______________________<br />

This brownie is delicious<br />

<strong>Practical</strong> syllogism<br />

All brownies are delicious<br />

This is a brownie<br />

______________________<br />

I eat this brownie<br />

Note that in a practical syllogism, the conclusion is an action, whereas in a theoretical syllogism,<br />

the conclusion is a statement (although a theoretical syllogism may be about practical<br />

matters!). Furthermore, in practical syllogisms, what is understood but not spelled out is that<br />

whatever is delicious is desirable, and I pursue whatever is desirable (when it is in my reach).<br />

A. (example of Aquinas)<br />

No fornication is to be committed<br />

Everything pleasurable is to be enjoyed<br />

B. (cf. example of <strong>Aristotle</strong>)<br />

Sweet things are harmful<br />

Sweet things are pleasant<br />

Thomas Aquinas, De malo (On Evil), 3.9 ad 7<br />

(see next page).<br />

Cf. <strong>Aristotle</strong>, EN 7.3.1147a23–b5<br />

Self-controlled<br />

person<br />

Morally strong<br />

person<br />

Morally weak<br />

person<br />

Self-indulgent<br />

person<br />

“considers” /<br />

engages in <br />

Reason<br />

controls<br />

sense<br />

desire<br />

⇒ reason<br />

determines<br />

the<br />

action<br />

Reason<br />

brings <br />

to the<br />

awareness<br />

“considers” / engages in & <br />

Sense desire<br />

brings<br />

to the<br />

awareness<br />

Sense<br />

desire<br />

controls<br />

reason<br />

“considers” /<br />

engages in <br />

⇒ sense<br />

desire<br />

determines<br />

the<br />

action<br />

A.<br />

No fornication is to be committed<br />

This act is fornication<br />

________________________________<br />

This act is not to be done<br />

B.<br />

Sweet things are harmful<br />

This is sweet<br />

____________________<br />

I don’t eat it<br />

A.<br />

Everything pleasurable is to be enjoyed<br />

This act is pleasurable<br />

____________________________________<br />

This act is to be done<br />

B.<br />

Sweet things are pleasant<br />

This is sweet<br />

___________________<br />

I eat it


Thomas Aquinas, De malo (On Evil), question 3, article 9, reply to objection 7 (trans.: J.<br />

Oesterle, Notre Dame 1993):<br />

“Since an act of sin and of virtue is done by choice, and choice is the desire of what has been<br />

decided on by previous deliberation, and deliberation is a kind of inquiry, it follows that in<br />

every act of virtue or of sin there must be a quasi-syllogistic deduction. But nevertheless the<br />

temperate man syllogizes in one way, the intemperate man in another, the continent man in<br />

one way, the incontinent man in another.<br />

For the temperate man is moved only according to the judgment of reason; hence he<br />

uses a syllogism containing three propositions, making a deduction such as this: No fornication<br />

is to be committed, this act is fornication, therefore, this act is not to be done.<br />

But the intemperate man yields entirely to the movement of concupiscence, and so he<br />

too uses a syllogism containing three propositions, making a deduction such as this: everything<br />

pleasurable is to be enjoyed, this act is pleasurable, therefore this act is to be done.<br />

However both the continent and the incontinent man are moved in two directions: according<br />

to reason to avoid sin, and according to concupiscence to commit sin; but in the<br />

continent man the judgment of reason prevails, in the incontinent man the movement of<br />

concupiscence prevails. Consequently each uses a syllogism having four propositions, but for<br />

contrary conclusions.<br />

For the continent man syllogizes in this manner: No sin is to be committed. And this he<br />

proposes in accordance with the judgment of reason, yet according to the movement of<br />

concupiscence he turns over and over in his mind that everything pleasurable is to be pursued;<br />

but because in him the judgment of reason prevails he adopts the first proposition and<br />

concludes under it: this act is a sin, therefore, it is not to be done.<br />

However the incontinent man, in whom the movement of concupiscence prevails, adopts<br />

the second proposition and concludes under it: this is pleasurable, therefore it is to be pursued.<br />

And such is properly the man who sins from weakness. And therefore it is evident that<br />

although he may know universally, nevertheless he does not know in particular, because he<br />

does not adopt the premise in keeping with reason but in keeping with concupiscence.”<br />

Ad septimum dicendum, quod cum actus peccati et virtutis sit secundum electionem, electio autem est<br />

appetitus praeconsiliati, consilium vero est quaedam inquisitio; necesse est quod in quolibet actu virtutis<br />

vel peccati sit quaedam deductio quasi syllogistica; sed tamen aliter syllogizat temperatus, aliter intemperatus;<br />

aliter continens, aliter incontinens. Temperatus enim movetur tantum secundum iudicium rationis;<br />

unde utitur syllogismo trium propositionum; quasi sic deducens: nulla fornicatio est committenda, hic<br />

actus est fornicatio, ergo non est faciendus. Intemperatus vero totaliter sequitur concupiscentiam; et ideo<br />

etiam ipse utitur syllogismo trium propositionum, quasi sic deducens: omni delectabili est fruendum, hic<br />

actus est delectabilis, ergo hoc est fruendum. Sed tam continens quam incontinens dupliciter movetur;<br />

secundum rationem quidem ad vitandum peccatum, secundum concupiscentiam vero ad committendum:<br />

sed in continente vincit iudicium rationis, in incontinente vero motus concupiscentiae. Unde uterque utitur<br />

syllogismo quatuor propositionum, sed ad contrarias conclusiones. Continens enim sic syllogizat: nullum<br />

peccatum est faciendum; et hoc proponit secundum iudicium rationis; secundum vero motum concupiscentiae<br />

versatur in corde eius quod omne delectabile est prosequendum; sed quia iudicium rationis<br />

in eo vincit, assumit et concludit sub primo: hoc est peccatum; ergo non est faciendum. Incontinens vero,<br />

in quo vincit motus concupiscentiae, assumit et concludit sub secundo: hoc est delectabile; ergo est<br />

prosequendum; et talis proprie est qui peccat ex infirmitate. Et ideo patet quod licet sciat in universali,<br />

non tamen scit in particulari; quia non assumit secundum rationem, sed secundum concupiscentiam.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!