25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SINGLE-TYPE ONTOLOGY 83<br />

entities and propositions via (minimally informative) indices, and of representing partial<br />

indices via sets of their extending total indices. The latter is a corollary of Stone’s Theorem<br />

(Stone, 1936), (cf. Davey and Priestley, 2002). The possibility of representing partial indices<br />

via sets of total indices also justifies the possibility of associating representations of entities<br />

and propositions in the type with functions from partial indices to functions from<br />

total indices to total truth-values. Note, however, that the resulting representations no longer<br />

satisfy the intensionality requirement from Property 3.<br />

This completes our identification of the suitable single basic types. We close the paper by<br />

comparing Partee’s preliminary basic-type choice and with our newly identified single basic<br />

types.<br />

4. Single-Type Candidates and Partee’s Hypothesis<br />

The above considerations disclose three interesting facts about Partee’s preliminary singletype<br />

candidate:<br />

1. Partee’s chosen type (i.e. properties of situations, type ) is a suitable single<br />

basic type that satisfies the requirements from Properties 0–5.<br />

2. Partee places more semantic constraints on single-type objects than necessary.<br />

Granted her disregard of intensionality, Montagovian properties of possible worlds are<br />

equally suitable.<br />

3. Partee neglects an alternative type (for situation-to-proposition functions, type ), whose objects are semantically ‘richer’ than type- objects.<br />

The observations from items (1) to (3) support Partee’s basic-type choice. However, they<br />

point out the possibility of adhering more closely to Montague’s original ontology (cf. the<br />

adoption of possible worlds; (2)), and of not prematurely excluding competing candidates (3).<br />

More generally, the possibility of representing partial situations via sets of their extending<br />

possible worlds (in Sect. 3.4) emphasizes the role of semantic operations and representational<br />

strategies in ontology (as opposed to the identity of the different object types).<br />

Kristina Liefke<br />

Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität, München &<br />

Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Universiteit Tilburg<br />

Kristina.Liefke@lrz.uni-muenchen.de<br />

References<br />

Barwise, J., and J. Perry. 1983: Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge (MA): The MIT Press.<br />

van Benthem, J. 1991: ‘General Dynamics’, Theoretical Linguistics, 159–201.<br />

Carstairs-McCarthy, A. 1999: The Origins of Complex Language: An Inquiry into the<br />

Evolutionary Beginnings of Sentences, Syllables, and Truth. Oxford and New York:<br />

Oxford University Press.<br />

Cheney, D. L., and R. M. Seyfarth. 1990: How Monkeys See the World: Inside the Mind of<br />

Another Species. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.<br />

Chierchia G., and R. Turner. 1988: ‘Semantics and Property Theory’, Linguistics and<br />

Philosophy 11, 261–302.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!