25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SINGLE-TYPE ONTOLOGY 81<br />

For greater understandability, we again illustrate our representational strategy by means of<br />

an example: Consider the rich -representation of the proposition ‘John loves Mary’<br />

(abbreviated Lmj) at @ in a universe consisting of three indices @, w 1, and w 2, and three<br />

(distinct) entities John (j), Mary (m), and Bill (b). Assume further that, at @, the propositions<br />

‘John runs’ (Rj), ‘Mary does not run’ (¬Rm), and ‘Bill runs’ (Rb) are true, that, at the index<br />

w 1, the propositions ‘John loves Mary’, ‘John runs’, ‘Mary doesn’t run’, and ‘Bill doesn’t run’<br />

are true (such that Lmb, Rj, ¬Rm, and ¬Rb obtain at w 1), and that, at the index w 2, the<br />

propositions ‘John loves Mary’, ‘John runs’, ‘Mary runs’, and ‘Bill doesn’t run’ are true (such<br />

that Lmj, Rj, Rm, and ¬Rb obtain at w 2):<br />

Then, the propositions ‘John runs’ and ‘Mary doesn’t run’ are the only true propositions at @<br />

which carry information about the aboutness subjects of the proposition ‘John loves Mary’. As<br />

a result, we represent the truth-value of ‘John loves Mary’ at @ by the subset of the set {@,<br />

w1, w2} at whose members the propositions ‘John runs’, ‘Mary doesn’t run’, and ‘John loves<br />

Mary’ are true. 6 We identify the latter with the singleton set {w1} (underbraced in Fig. 3).<br />

To ensure a correspondence between propositions and their rich single-type representations<br />

(in analogy with (10)), we represent propositions φ by an index-general variant, (14), of their<br />

representation from (13):<br />

(14) { | w ∈ φ & for all p , if w 1 ∈ p &<br />

for some x, (φ ∧ p) ‘is about’ x, then w ∈ p}<br />

We will sometimes denote objects of the above form by φ † .<br />

This completes our elimination of single-type candidates on the basis of their failure to satisfy<br />

the representability requirement from Property 2.<br />

Our investigation of the Booleanness and Representability requirements from Sections 3.1<br />

and 3.2 has reduced the set of single-type candidates from Table 1 to all but two members: the<br />

types and . Since the requirements of Intensionality and Partiality depend<br />

only on the domanial structure of an algebraic type, they are unable to exclude further singletype<br />

candidates. However, we will see below that they place specific constraints on the<br />

candidates’ associated objects. The latter are specified below. Since the requirement of<br />

Intensionality is trivially satisfied in virtue of the types’ partiality (cf. Sect. 2.4), we only<br />

discuss the requirement of Partiality.<br />

3.4. Obtaining Partial Types<br />

The previous subsection has described representations of entities and propositions in the type<br />

as relations between pairs of indices of the form from (10) and (14).<br />

Correspondingly, at the index w 1 from Figure 1, the entity John and the proposition ‘John<br />

whistles’ are represented by the set of indices from (15):<br />

6<br />

The last requirement compensates for the fact that ‘John loves Mary’ is undefined at @. The latter is<br />

analogous to the existence requirement on the representation of entities from (9).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!