25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

SINGLE-TYPE ONTOLOGY 79<br />

compensate for this shortcoming. 5 In particular, their representational strategy follows the<br />

strategy for the representation of entities in the type (cf. (1), (2)). Only, rather than<br />

representing an entity via the set of its extensional properties at @, we represent the latter via<br />

the set of true propositions at @ which carry information about it; or, equivalently, via the set<br />

of indices at which all true propositions at @ which carry information about the entity are<br />

true. An entity a is then represented by the set of indices from (8):<br />

(8) {w s | for all p , if @ ∈ p & p ‘is about’ a, then w ∈ p}<br />

To ease reference, we hereafter denote the representation of a from (8) by ‘a † @’.<br />

We illustrate the above representation strategy by means of an example: Consider the<br />

representation of John in a universe consisting of three indices @, w 1, and w 2, and two<br />

distinct entities: John (abbreviated j) and Mary (abbreviated m). Assume further that, at the<br />

current index, the propositions ‘John runs’ (Rj), ‘Mary runs’ (Rm) and ‘Mary doesn’t whistle’<br />

(¬Wm) are true, that, at the index w 1, the propositions ‘John runs’, ‘John whistles’, ‘Mary<br />

runs’ and ‘Mary doesn’t whistle’ are true (such that Rj, Wj, Rm, and ¬Wm obtain at w 1), and<br />

that, at the index w 2, the propositions ‘John doesn’t run’, ‘Mary runs’, ‘John whistles’, and<br />

‘Mary whistles’ are true (such that ¬Rj , Rm, Wj, and Wm obtain at w 2) (cf. Fig.1) .<br />

Then, by the characterization of aboutness from Section 3.2, the proposition ‘John runs’ is the<br />

only true proposition at @ which carries information about John. As a result, we represent<br />

John at @ by the subset of the set {@, w 1, w 2} at whose members John runs. We identify the<br />

latter with the set {@, w 1} (underbraced in Fig. 1). The latter encodes the information that<br />

John runs at @.<br />

Notably, the representation of entities along the lines of (8) presupposes the existence of the<br />

represented entity a at the current index: If a does not exist at @, no proposition p will satisfy<br />

the condition on the set from (8). Since a will thus be represented by the empty set of indices,<br />

its type- representation at @ will be identified with the type- representations of all<br />

other non-existing entities at @. But this is arguably undesirable.<br />

To solve this problem, we hedge the condition, @ ∈ p & p ‘is about’ a, on the set a † @ from (8)<br />

with the conjunct ‘a exists in w’. The entity a is then represented by the set of indices from<br />

(9):<br />

(9) {w s | a exists in w & for all p , if @ ∈ p & p ‘is about’ a, then w ∈ p}<br />

Figure 2 illustrates the representation of John at an index in which he does not exist. In the<br />

figure, we abbreviate ‘John exists’ as ‘Ej’.<br />

5<br />

Since they encode semantically ‘richer’ information than type- propositions, objects of the type<br />

still satisfy the simplicity requirement from Property 5.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!