25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

WHAT MAKES MORAL VALUES QUEER? 683<br />

morality is about. Morality loses its point if it is not fixed by actions, states of affairs, or<br />

attitudes. If morality did not require moral properties to be fixed by non-moral properties,<br />

then it would allow for moral properties to be free floating, detached from the non-moral<br />

world. Furthermore, it would not be conceptually guaranteed that morality gives as reliable<br />

a verdict about what we ought to do. Therefore, Jackson calls this part of supervenience “the<br />

most salient and least controversial part of folk moral theory” (Jackson 1998: 118) and<br />

Michael Smith writes, “Everyone agrees that the moral features of things supervene on their<br />

natural features [...]. For recognition of the way in which the moral supervenes on the<br />

natural is a constraint on the proper use of moral concepts“ (Smith 1994: 21).<br />

Why are the two necessity operators critical in the context of this paper? The metaphysical<br />

necessity claim purports to describe part of the behavior of moral properties, i.e. how they<br />

relate to descriptive properties. It is this part of moral supervenience that stands in need of<br />

explanation. As I showed in the first paragraph, Mackie argues that if these necessities<br />

remain unexplained, they would be queer. Second, conceptual necessity is about what sort<br />

of relation morality incontrovertibly requires. Mackie’s error theory, for example, embraces<br />

the conceptual constraint arguing that it is an integral part of morality for moral properties<br />

to be supervenient (he argues that moral value “would have to be” supervenient). But, he<br />

denies that unexplained metaphysical necessities exist, as the existence of such a relation<br />

would be queer and implausible. To sum up, unexplained metaphysical necessity is the<br />

target of the queerness argument and the conceptual necessity secures its importance.<br />

To remind ourselves, from the formula for strong moral supervenience the embedded<br />

metaphysical necessities – □ M∀y(Gy→Fy) – stand in need for explanation. Suppose there is<br />

something (say, X) that explains these necessities. Then, an explanation for those necessities<br />

could be expressed as follows:<br />

EXP<br />

X explains that it is metaphysically necessary that everything that is G is also F.<br />

But EXP could mean either of two things. In one sense, X might explain why <strong>bei</strong>ng G<br />

necessitates the instantiation of a particular property F and not that of another property such<br />

as E (where F and E are not identical). In another sense, X might explain why something’s<br />

<strong>bei</strong>ng G necessitates anything at all and not just nothing. In this latter case, X would explain<br />

why a certain relation obtains, namely that of necessitation.<br />

5. Explaining Supervenience: Two Accounts<br />

Any metaethical account is conceptually committed to moral supervenience and normative<br />

realists in particular to supervenience <strong>bei</strong>ng a relation between distinct types of properties.<br />

However, the charge goes that if these necessities remain unexplained, they are queer, e.g.<br />

they are utterly different from anything else in the universe and a commitment to these<br />

entities is therefore implausible.<br />

Turning this uneasiness into a serious queerness argument against normative realism<br />

requires finding a plausible account of ‘explanation’ that explains all remaining cases of<br />

supervenience but which leaves moral supervenience in particular as an unexplained queer<br />

residue. The rest of the paper will be concerned with pointing to two difficulties in meeting<br />

this challenge: First, if one were to choose a demanding account of explanation, one might<br />

manage to leave the moral case unexplained. But such an account might also leave other types<br />

of facts or properties such as mental properties unexplained. Hence, if we do not want to give<br />

up our commitment to these other properties, moral supervenience could, though<br />

unexplained, escape queerness. On the other hand, if one chooses an account of ‘explanation’

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!