25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

PRACTICAL KNOWLEDGE 609<br />

But how is this possible? I think this is possible only if there is what Anscombe, at one point<br />

in Intention, calls “knowledge in intention” (Anscombe 2000: 57). Basically, this is the idea<br />

that, in acting on an intention, one’s knowledge of what one is doing is constituted by one’s<br />

intention itself. That is, my intention to do A is a thought through which I know that I am<br />

doing A; and, since my intention is the cause of my doing A, this means that the relevant<br />

thought is the cause of what is known through it. This is why, according to Anscombe, the<br />

knowledge of my intentional action is practical knowledge, which she defines as knowledge<br />

that is the cause of what it understands. If this idea could be rendered intelligible, it would<br />

indeed explain why knowledge in intentional action is no accident. For, if the thought through<br />

which I know what I am doing is the cause of my doing it, then the existence of my action<br />

includes my knowledge of this action. So, the basic idea is that, in order to account for the<br />

knowledge-requirement, what we have to understand is how the cause of an intentional<br />

action can be, as such, a source of knowledge of this action. However, the difficulty certainly<br />

is to understand how this idea of practical knowledge is to be spelled out in any detail. What I<br />

want to argue now is that, given a certain widespread conception of practical thought, it is<br />

indeed not obvious that there is a satisfactory way of spelling out this idea.<br />

The conception of practical thought that I have in mind is defined by the assumption that a<br />

practical thought is basically composed of two independent elements: a conceptual content<br />

and a certain causal force. On this view, my intention to do A has a kind of content that it<br />

shares with other kinds of thought (for example, with belief); a kind of content that is often<br />

taken to be expressible in a proposition like “I am doing A” (at least if, as I assume, it is an<br />

intention in action). To this kind of content different attitudes may be attached, which in turn<br />

are to be distinguished in terms of their different causal roles. Very roughly, the idea is that<br />

my intention is a practical thought in that it is the cause of what it represents, whereas a<br />

belief is a theoretical thought in that it is causally dependent on what it represents (however<br />

mediated this causal dependency might be). So, on this view, it is possible to understand what<br />

it is for an agent’s intention to be a representation of the relevant movement without thereby<br />

implying an understanding of the intention as <strong>bei</strong>ng the cause of the movement. And,<br />

accordingly, it is possible to understand what it is for the intention to be the cause of the<br />

movement without thereby implying an understanding of the intention as <strong>bei</strong>ng a<br />

representation of the movement. This is what I want to call the compositional view of<br />

practical thought.<br />

What’s crucial is that, on this view, the fact that my intention is a representation of my doing<br />

A does not include, and is not included in, the fact that it is the cause of my doing A. Its <strong>bei</strong>ng<br />

a representation of my doing A and its <strong>bei</strong>ng the cause of my doing A are two independent<br />

features of my practical thought. But if this is so, it is difficult to see how my intention can be<br />

a thought that is, as such, knowledge of its own effect – as the knowledge-requirement<br />

demands. To see the problem, consider that for my practical thought to be knowledge of its<br />

own effect, there must be a non-accidental connection between my thought’s <strong>bei</strong>ng the cause<br />

of my doing A and its <strong>bei</strong>ng a representation of my doing A. But, on the compositional view of<br />

practical thought, representation and causal efficacy are independent of one another: taken as<br />

such, there is nothing in the idea of causality that requires the presence of representation;<br />

and, correspondingly, there is nothing in the idea of representation that requires the presence<br />

of causality. So, it seems that there is nothing in the relevant notions of causality and<br />

representation that explains why it is not just an accident if my thought represents what it<br />

causes. Consequently, it seems that there is nothing that can account for my practical<br />

thought’s qualification as knowledge of its own effect.<br />

The problem is not just that my intention might fail to be causally efficacious. Rather, the<br />

problem is that, if the causal efficacy of my intention is independent of its content, it seems to<br />

be an accident that what my intention causes and what it represents come together in the<br />

right way, namely so that the effect of my intention is the movement it represents. And if

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!