25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

590 DOHRN<br />

attached to John before John came into existence. But from an epistemic position which<br />

includes her attachment to John, she ought to have conceived John.<br />

However, I do not think the relevant distinction is an epistemic one, at least epistemic in the<br />

sense intended by Hare. It is not Mary’s learning something about John that brings about her<br />

John-centred feelings. It is no peculiar intrinsic property of John as opposed to some other<br />

possible child of Mary’s which makes him the appropriate target of her emotions. Moreover,<br />

Mary could have perfectly anticipated that whoever would be her child would be the subject of<br />

her feelings. So it is neither her ignorance of John’s specific properties nor her ignorance of<br />

the nature of her attachment that explains why she ought MR not to have conceived John.<br />

I use Hare’s own idea of an omniscient observer to shed further doubt on the idea that the<br />

problem is an epistemic one. The omniscient observer knows everything about the<br />

consequences of Mary’s actual actions. Assume Mary (like Frank Jackson’s Mary) is an<br />

extremely efficient learner. Before she conceives John, the omniscient observer has told her<br />

everything about her future child John, including Mary’s special affection for John and so on.<br />

Say she is provided with a complete description of the future situation. If we frame the<br />

distinction of two kinds of ought as an epistemic one, Mary’s position at t1 (even before she<br />

has conceived John) should now be characterized by ought OD . Still I do not think that this<br />

enforces a change in Mary’s obligations or values. Judging from her own vantage point before<br />

she conceives John, she still ought to have waited, although she is in the very same epistemic<br />

position she will be after giving birth to John. In sum, Hare’s epistemically based distinction<br />

of two kinds of ought does not dissolve the puzzle.<br />

Before proceeding with my criticism of Hare, I briefly sketch my own preferred solution: the<br />

change in Mary’s valuation is not brought about by her learning something but by becoming<br />

emotionally acquainted with John (cf. Velleman 2006: 269). Acquaintance is not understood<br />

in informational terms but in the sense of intimacy between mother and child. There is<br />

nothing Mary could not have known in advance about her attachment to John, except,<br />

perhaps, what it is like to feel acquaintanted with John. We cannot feel the same for John.<br />

Thus we retain our judgement. But we acknowledge that it is appropriate for Mary to adopt<br />

her new feelings upon becoming acquainted with John. In contrast to Velleman, I do not<br />

claim Mary to judge at t 2 that she should not have conceived John (except in the non-default<br />

reading exposed above). Thus, I do not have to accept inconsistent valuations in claiming<br />

Mary to judge at t 2 that she should not have conceived John.<br />

3. Criticism of Hare’s Counterfactual Account<br />

I criticize Hare’s counterfactual account of the different senses of ‘ought’ he distinguishes.<br />

Assume you may spin a wheel of for<strong>tun</strong>e. If it were spun with a force of 15.88348N, it would<br />

show red, if it were spun with 15.88349N, it would show black. You do not spin the wheel.<br />

Arguably it is indeterminate what would have happened if you had spun the wheel. Hare<br />

contends that in general, such indeterminacy is resilient under embedding. Now consider a<br />

varied case: let S stand for ‘the wheel is spun’, R for ‘it shows Red’. S → R is by assumption<br />

indeterminate. Assume S and R obtain. Moreover, outcome R actually leads to a loss but the<br />

expected value of spinning was positive. As a test what one ought OD to have done (whether<br />

one ought to have spun the wheel), Hare imagines an omniscient <strong>bei</strong>ng who knows that S<br />

actually leads to the unfor<strong>tun</strong>ate outcome R. From the perspective of this <strong>bei</strong>ng, one ought OD<br />

not to have spun the wheel. In order to figure out what one ought MR to have done, Hare<br />

suggests, one should ask what would have happened if one had not spun the wheel by an<br />

embedded counterfactual. If one had not spun, then if one had spun, would the outcome have<br />

been positive? Since S → R is indeterminate, Hare argues, so is ¬S →(S → R). As a<br />

consequence, to figure out what one ought MR to have done, one must resort to a weaker

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!