25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

556 BURKARD<br />

epistemic standard formulated in the second can clearly be challenged. There is no room to<br />

discuss these options in any detail here, but promising responses have been developed in the<br />

literature from both realist and anti-realist perspectives, responses which can be used in a<br />

defence of moral intuitionism. To just briefly state these two options with respect to the<br />

evolutionary debunking argument: We may doubt that the influence of evolutionary forces is<br />

indeed so considerable that all or most of our intuitions are (directly or indirectly) affected.<br />

Or we could argue that the influence of evolutionary forces is not necessarily detrimental to<br />

the trustworthiness of our moral intuitions. That could be so because we may regard our<br />

ability to form justified moral beliefs as a by-product of the development of those epistemic<br />

faculties that can reasonably be considered as providing us with justified or true beliefs and<br />

as beneficial for survival (or as ‘fitness enhancing’). 17 Remember, however, that a proponent<br />

of the minimalist intuitionist position is not necessarily committed to this kind of realism, or<br />

to moral realism at all. As Street argues, anti-realists have different resources to react to<br />

hypotheses about the influence of evolutionary forces on our moral (and other evaluative)<br />

views, and to avoid scepticism about the beliefs in question (cf. Street 2006: sect. 10).<br />

Let me now comment on the third option described above, that of accepting a debunking<br />

argument but using it constructively in a positive account of moral justification. It may seem<br />

obvious that this response is not available in the case of global debunking arguments, for<br />

there would simply be no intuitions left to rely on if such an argument succeeded in showing<br />

that none of them are justified or trustworthy. However, this verdict is premature. We can see<br />

why when we adopt what may be called a holistic approach to debunking attempts.<br />

According to such an approach, we may be rationally required to start our reflection process<br />

anew if a global debunking argument seems to force us to conclude that no moral belief is<br />

justified. This sort of response to debunking arguments is constructive in the following sense:<br />

Global debunking attempts can indicate that some moral convictions are so central to our<br />

belief system that in cases of conflict, it is more reasonable to give up some theoretical beliefs<br />

than those convictions. That is, global debunking arguments can function as a reductio of the<br />

empirical or theoretical thesis in question.<br />

If it were the case, say, that the apparently best explanation for why we hold moral beliefs, in<br />

combination with a robust version of realism, leads us to conclude that no moral beliefs are<br />

justified, then this could be a reason to either reconsider the explanation in question or to<br />

reject this form of realism. In fact, also local debunking arguments can sometimes be treated<br />

as reductiones of this sort. For example, I might be impressed by Singer’s debunking argument,<br />

but also be deeply convinced that it is permissible to throw the switch in the first trolley<br />

case but impermissible to push the big man in the second. In such a case, my moral<br />

conviction can give me a reason to treat the argument as a recuctio and search for a nondebunking<br />

account of my judgment and thus gain (new) justification for it (a search that<br />

might fail, of course).<br />

This description of debunking arguments implies that (certain) moral beliefs can give us<br />

reasons to either reconsider an explanation of why we make moral judgments or to adopt<br />

some metaethical view rather than another. That is, although debunking arguments can put<br />

pressure on moral convictions as well as on theoretical views about morality, they do not<br />

necessarily have the final say. In this vein, Street and others take their conjecture that our<br />

moral beliefs have been shaped considerably by evolutionary forces as a reason to reject<br />

certain metaethical views rather than moral convictions.<br />

The assessment that we may have reason to give up some theoretical assumptions or to<br />

rethink certain explanations so that we can coherently hold on to some moral convictions,<br />

dovetails well with the intuitionist outlook. For though we should certainly not claim that<br />

17<br />

Cf. e.g. FitzPatrick 2008, Enoch 2010 and Skarsaune 2011, who all try to defend a robust version of<br />

moral realism against an evolutionary debunking argument.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!