25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

546 WÜNDISCH<br />

This assessment carelessly neglects the analysts’ awareness of the weaknesses of their<br />

predictions as well as their ability to take into account the risk aversion of those the analysis is<br />

supposed to guide. Just as climatologists offer confidence intervals for their predictions, any<br />

thoughtful cost-benefit analysis will comment on the contingencies of its predictions and<br />

address uncertainties in any recommendation. To deny this implies that economists are<br />

strangers to analyzing decisions under uncertainty – little is further from the truth. If we use<br />

an imperfect analysis in the knowledge that it is imperfect it can very well help us.<br />

In summary, the basic observation that it is challenging to forecast the development of<br />

economies especially in the face of exogenous shocks is justified and well supported.<br />

However, there are three reasons to be skeptical of the general claim that economic analysis is<br />

practically useless when confronted with the uncertainties brought about by climate change.<br />

First, economic analysis is not only concerned with the development of economies alone but<br />

seeks to take into account all effects a policy change has on welfare. No plausible analysis can<br />

avoid considering these effects and facing the relevant uncertainties. Second, even if<br />

economic analysis was focused on the workings and the development of economies alone, it is<br />

unclear how an ethical theory could avoid taking them into account as long as they are<br />

assumed to impact welfare or any other important policy goal. Third, economic analysis is<br />

well adapted to analyzing decisions under uncertainty and therefore produces normative<br />

recommendations that take into account its exposure to that uncertainty.<br />

6. Conclusion<br />

Many of the common criticisms voiced against economic analysis as a tool within public<br />

policy are either based on misinterpretations about the aims and capabilities of normative<br />

economics or formulated without taking into view the specific practical challenges that arise<br />

in any attempt to make a theory of welfare operational. However, critics are correct to point<br />

out that the criterion of economic efficiency is not of exclusive importance. Given the<br />

dominance of economic analysis within the public policy discourse this may be an important<br />

reminder for some – even if economics as a science says nothing different and most<br />

economists are well aware of that.<br />

One important effect of the critiques raised against economics by moral philosophers is that<br />

they inspire collaboration and bring about theoretical advancements. The work of that kind<br />

best known among philosophers is probably the capabilities approach to well-<strong>bei</strong>ng<br />

developed by Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen as well as Sen’s application of that<br />

approach to questions of egalitarianism. 23 As long as criticisms like those of Jamieson<br />

encourage further investigation into the important field of the philosophy of economics they<br />

are valuable.<br />

Joachim Wündisch<br />

Heinrich-Heine-Universität Düsseldorf<br />

Joachim.Wuendisch@uni-duesseldorf.de<br />

References<br />

Adler, M. D. and E. A. Posner 2006: New Foundations of Cost-Benefit Analysis. Cambridge,<br />

(MA): Harvard University Press.<br />

23<br />

Sen 1992, Nussbaum and Sen 1993, Sen 1999, as well as Hausman 2008: 31.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!