25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

ECONOMIC ANALYSIS & COMBATING CLIMATE CHANGE 537<br />

light bulb, subsidies for electric cars, and, of course, cap-and-trade systems for greenhouse<br />

gas emissions.<br />

According to Jamieson these management approaches are rooted in the unjustified<br />

assumption that “the perception of self-interest is the only motivator for human <strong>bei</strong>ngs”<br />

which in turn suggests that “[i]f you want people to do something give them a carrot; if you<br />

want them to desist, give them a stick” (Jamieson 1992: 143). 1 These components of<br />

management approaches are geared toward reaching a previously identified goal of public<br />

policy by means of structuring individual incentives in such a way that individuals have<br />

reason to align their behavior with that public policy goal. Jamieson criticizes that course of<br />

action because he believes that “exploiting people’s perceptions of self-interest may not be the<br />

only way to move them” (Jamieson 1992: 144). Jamieson’s first critique of management<br />

approaches assumes that they are based on an incorrect view of human psychology. It<br />

amounts to the claim that management approaches therefore champion deficient means of<br />

public policy implementation.<br />

However, Jamieson’s misgivings about the role of economic analysis within the context of the<br />

climate change debate go deeper. The management approaches fuelled by economic analyses<br />

are not only purported to be deficient in how they implement public policy but also misguided<br />

regarding which public policy they support and for what reasons they do so. To illustrate this<br />

point Jamieson correctly recounts the basic idea of cost-benefit analysis within economics:<br />

[w]hen faced with a policy decision, what we need to do is assess the benefits and costs<br />

o[f] various alternatives. The alternative that maximizes the benefits less the costs is<br />

the one we should prefer. This alternative is “efficient” and choosing it is “rational.”<br />

(Jamieson 1992: 143)<br />

However, according to Jamieson the application of cost-benefit analysis is misguided in the<br />

context of public policy because it is narrowly focused on economic efficiency. This he argues<br />

to be problematic because “economic efficiency is only one value, and it may not be the most<br />

important one” (Jamieson 1992: 143). Rather than focusing on economic efficiency public<br />

policy makers should take a broader view and consider other values – such as equity – which<br />

Jamieson believes to be often more important. Jamieson’s second critique of management<br />

approaches and economic analyses assumes that they put far too great an emphasis on<br />

economic efficiency within public policy and therefore support the wrong ends.<br />

Lastly, Jamieson argues that because even the overall impacts of climate change – such as the<br />

increase in the global mean surface temperature or the changes in precipitation – are so<br />

uncertain, there is virtually no way to forecast their economic consequences. This supposed<br />

special exposure of economic forecasts to uncertainty is the essence of Jamieson’s third<br />

critique and according to him, “a further reason why economic considerations should take a<br />

back seat in our thinking about global climate change […]” (Jamieson 1992: 144).<br />

If justified, these criticisms amount to a strong argument against giving special weight to<br />

economic analyses in the context of climate change. Supposedly, management approaches<br />

attempt to reach the wrong ends by deficient means and are in the process particularly<br />

vulnerable to forecasting uncertainties. On a superficial level these claims appear to be<br />

plausible. However, as detailed assessment will reveal, these criticisms of economic analysis<br />

are in large part misguided. Sections three, four, and five provide that assessment.<br />

1<br />

To support his claim Jamieson also refers to Meyers 1983.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!