25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

532 SEIDEL<br />

the socio-relational critique would simply sidestep essentially distributive questions. 11<br />

Moreover (and consequently), if ESV is really about something else (like freedom or valuable<br />

human relationships), then not undermining this value would be a condition of adequacy for<br />

any conception of distributive justice and not just for distributive egalitarianism.<br />

Sufficientarians and prioritarians, too, may also accept that we should treat each other with<br />

equal respect; but their agreement on this understanding of ESV would not settle their<br />

substantive disagreements about what constitutes a fair distribution. In other words: By restating<br />

ESV in this way, ESV ceases to have any bearing on distributive questions – it would<br />

be “distributively inert”. Again, the socio-relational critique looses much of its appeal: If<br />

taking this ideal into account is a general criterion for any plausible conception of justice, why<br />

should the (luck-)egalitarian be especially worried about it?<br />

A last reply to my line of reasoning may be called the “stipulative currency objection”: “Of<br />

course,” the critic may say, “we may talk about distributing something (e.g. rank, power,<br />

status, social standing) equally; but it would be completely stipulative to do this, a purely<br />

formal and artificial way to plug in something as a currency just for the sake of having a<br />

currency.” I think that the stipulative currency objection is either self-refuting or<br />

overgeneralises. Regarding the first horn of this dilemma, note that “artificial” cannot mean<br />

“unimportant”, “unwarranted” or “not <strong>bei</strong>ng supported by further reasons”. The currencies<br />

under consideration (e.g. rank, power, status, social standing) clearly are important from the<br />

critic’s point of view, because these are the very concepts employed to characterise the<br />

content of ESV; and while it is true that no reasons are given why differences in the currencies<br />

under consideration (differences in e.g. rank, power, status, social standing) are supposed to<br />

be relevant, this charge would, mutatis mutandis, apply to ESV as well because no further<br />

reasons are given why certain human relation ought not to be governed by differences in<br />

rank, power, status, social standing etc. Let us turn to the second horn: The stipulative<br />

currency objection may also be read as complaining not so much about what is regarded as a<br />

currency or distribuendum but rather as objecting to the fact that something is regarded as a<br />

distribuendum in the first place. The objection will be then be that it is misleading to think of<br />

rank, status, power etc. as something like apples, newspaper or spam mails which may be<br />

literally “distributed” by a distributor who, at some point in time, has all of the distribuendum<br />

at her disposal and then hands it out to the recipients. But this objection is too strong; if valid,<br />

it would apply to all distribuenda which are discussed in the debate on distributive justice<br />

(e.g. welfare, resources, oppor<strong>tun</strong>ities): Of course, no single entity, person or institution<br />

possesses (or ever possessed) all of the welfare, resources or oppor<strong>tun</strong>ities and then, after<br />

careful thinking, hands it out to the people. The existence of such a distributor or “social<br />

planner” is not necessary for questions of distributive justice to arise since we can also be said<br />

to “distribute something” if we have some sort of causal influence on the distribution of<br />

something by shaping our social institutions. For instance, as long as we are able to influence<br />

the distribution of income through taxes, expropriation, education or whatever, we may call<br />

any action that so affects the distribution of income an act of (re)distributing income. And<br />

given that, through institutional arrangements, we surely do have such a causal impact on<br />

differences in rank, status, power, social standing etc., there is nothing artificial or stipulative<br />

in talking about the distribution of rank, status, power or social standing. I thus conclude that<br />

the stipulative currency objection fails and that the first problem with the socio-relational<br />

critique is still unsolved: ESV is not distinct from DE but rather presupposes some from of<br />

DE.<br />

11<br />

This answer to the critic naturally invites the following question: What distinguishes “a question of<br />

distributive justice” from a “question of morality in general”? While I am not able to give a fullydeveloped<br />

answer, a plausible first approximation is that paradigmatic questions of distributive justice<br />

arise where (1) a group of persons benefits from (2) some important good which (3) is provided by a<br />

(possibly different) group of persons and (4) whose distribution can intentionally be affected (either<br />

directly or through social institutions).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!