25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE SOCIO-RELATIONAL CRITIQUE OF DISTRIBUTIVE EGALITARIANISM 527<br />

allow for trade-offs with other reasons (so again, (T2*) allows the pluralist to enter the stage).<br />

The equality-grounded reason may be of different types in that it may have various structural<br />

features (e.g. it may be a “silencing” or an “exclusionary” reason), although it will probably be<br />

a moral (rather than an aesthetic or prudential) reason. For the sake of the present argument,<br />

we do not have to bother with these details. Third, (T2*) can be specified with a whole lot of<br />

currencies of justice (see the remark above). What currency we will plug in for C will of course<br />

affect the plausibility of the resulting position; but it is not constitutive of <strong>bei</strong>ng a distributive<br />

egalitarian that one is committed so some specific currency; all that is needed is that there is<br />

some currency with regard to which unequal distributions count as reasons against the<br />

distribution.<br />

For the present purposes, (T1) and (T2*) provide a suitable explication of distributive<br />

egalitarianism. Indeed I think that this explication is quite uncontroversial; in particular, it<br />

should be acceptable to all critics of distributive egalitarianism.<br />

2. The Socio-Relational Critique<br />

Distributive egalitarianism, is subject to many objections. Perhaps the most widely discussed<br />

problem is the so-called “levelling-down” objection; it purports to show that (T2*) is false, i.e.<br />

that distributive equality is not intrinsically valuable. I am not going to deal with this<br />

objection.<br />

A second prominent problem for distributive egalitarians concerns (T1); on a strong reading<br />

of (T1) – a view that may be called “pure” distributive egalitarianism –, DE is all that is<br />

needed to account for distributive justice; i.e. distributive justice is to be explained in terms of<br />

DE only. The quite common problem for pure distributive egalitarianism is to account for the<br />

proper place of individual responsibility in our intuitions about distributive justice. It seems<br />

that a simple “everyone gets the same, equal amount of the currency of justice” does not<br />

adequately reflect the idea that people sometimes deserve more or less of whatever is up for<br />

distribution simply because of good (clever) or bad (foolish) choices they made. In response,<br />

distributive egalitarians tried to “incorporate” individual responsibility into their accounts,<br />

thereby creating various forms of “luck-egalitarianism”. Luck-egalitarianism is the main<br />

target of the socio-relational critique since it is – rightly or wrongly – often regarded as the<br />

most plausible form of distributive egalitarianism. That it is, indeed, a form of distributive<br />

egalitarianism can be explained within the proposed framework: The luck-egalitarian<br />

distinguishes between two kinds of inequalities – acceptable and unacceptable inequalities.<br />

She does so by some further distinction which she takes to be normatively relevant: the<br />

distinction between features for which a person can be held responsible (like autonomous<br />

choices) and features for which a person cannot be held responsible (like <strong>bei</strong>ng born with a<br />

handicap). The idea is that inequalities in something (resources, advantages, well-<strong>bei</strong>ng, …)<br />

which are due to features for which a person can be held responsible are acceptable while<br />

inequalities which are due to features for which a person cannot be held responsible are not<br />

acceptable. Where exactly the line should be drawn (i.e. which features we can be held<br />

responsible for) is a matter of dispute within the luck-egalitarian camp. 3 Disregarding this<br />

dispute, what makes luck-egalitarianism a version of distributive egalitarianism in the sense<br />

defined above is that first, it tries to explicate distributive justice in terms of certain<br />

(in)equalities – namely (in)equalities in the distribution of resources, advantages, well-<strong>bei</strong>ng,<br />

…which are due to features for which someone cannot be held responsible; and second that<br />

luck-egalitarians, too, think that equality with regard to something (namely with regard to<br />

resources, advantages, well-<strong>bei</strong>ng, etc. which derive from features for which one cannot be<br />

3<br />

For instance, Dworkin (2002) and Cohen (1989) disagree about whether we can be held responsible<br />

for some of our expensive tastes or character traits.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!