25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Relativism and Superassertibility<br />

Manfred Harth<br />

In this paper, I shall explore the prospects of a shape of relativism in ethics that is supposed<br />

to be an alternative to the relativist account of truth that recently emerged in semantics,<br />

which relativizes the truth predicate by adding an extra parameter for a perspective, a<br />

context of assessment or the like. This alternative is based on an epistemic account of ethical<br />

truth as superassertibility; and the straightforward road to relativism then is to hold that two<br />

contradictory propositions may be both stably assertible relative to divergent starting points<br />

of information. Yet this sort of relativism requires a relativization of the truth predicate –<br />

which was to be avoided from the outset. I’ll discuss the following response to this problem:<br />

limiting relativism to epistemic relativism conjoint with an account of ethical truth as<br />

monadic superassertibility – thereby denying the possibility that two contradictory<br />

propositions may be both stably assertible – and a restriction to intuitionistic logic. I’ll<br />

conclude that this account, which I call Anti-realist Epistemic Relativism, yields a promising<br />

approach to ethical relativism that presents an alternative to semantic truth-relativism.<br />

1. The Role(s) of Faultless Disagreement<br />

1. The idea that in some area of thought and language there may be genuine disagreement in<br />

which nobody can be accused of having failed or of having done something wrong or of <strong>bei</strong>ng<br />

mistaken etc. – for which the term “faultless disagreement” has established in the literature –<br />

plays a crucial role in the philosophical debate about relativism. Yet there are at least two<br />

different roles to play for faultless disagreement depending on the region of discourse one is<br />

concerned with. For discourse about matters of taste, humour and the like it has a<br />

motivational role. That is, the possibility of disagreement in which nobody needs to be wrong<br />

is a widespread intuition, or arguably the pre-theoretic view, about matters of taste or<br />

humour that should be explained by a semantic theory. For other regions, notably for ethical<br />

discourse, with which I’m concerned here, the possibility of faultless disagreement plays a<br />

different role: it doesn’t seem to be the common pre-theoretic view or a widespread intuition<br />

that has to be explained by semanticists – quite the contrary, many ordinary people seem to<br />

be inclined to think that in a disagreement about morals one party has to be wrong, although<br />

it might be hard or in some cases even impossible to find out which one is. Nevertheless,<br />

some people are inclined to think otherwise, and we may call them relativists. So one way to<br />

be an ethical relativist is to claim that for moral matters faultless disagreement is possible –<br />

this is the second role of the possibility of faultless disagreement: it defines a relativist<br />

position. That is, ethical relativists of that shape maintain that there may be ethical questions,<br />

e.g. the question whether or not abortion is always morally wrong, to which more than one<br />

correct answer can be given: Alice might belief that abortion is always wrong and Bob might<br />

belief that it is not, and neither of them needs to be at fault. However, simple considerations<br />

show that faultless disagreement thus conceived is not possible; it gives rise to contradiction,<br />

which is proved by the following Simple Deduction (cf. Wright 2002: 105):<br />

(1) A believes that P and B believes that not-P Disagreement<br />

(2) Neither A nor B has made a mistake Faultlessness<br />

(3) ∀X: If X believes that P, and not-P, X has made a mistake Error Principle

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!