25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

NON-NOMINAL QUANTIFICATION 35<br />

interpretation of the analysis of truth by employing sentential quantification in the<br />

satisfaction conditions as well:<br />

A proposition α satisfies the open sentence ‘The Pythagorean Theorem = [P] & P’ if and<br />

only if the Pythagorean Theorem is identical with the proposition that things are as α<br />

says they are and things are as α says they are. 2 Alternatively: A proposition α<br />

satisfies the open sentence ‘The Pythagorean Theorem = [P] & P’ if and only if, for<br />

some S, α says that S, where the Pythagorean Theorem is the proposition that S, and S.<br />

However, if one is willing to tolerate non-nominal quantification in the satisfaction conditions<br />

then one might feel there is no need to appeal to a domain of objects in the first place. For one<br />

can avoid mention of properties and propositions and account for any form of quantification<br />

in the object language by using the same form of quantification in the metalanguage. Hugly<br />

and Sayward (1996: 303–16) and Williamson (1999) have developed this approach.<br />

Of course, one may think that truth and exemplification need not be explained in terms of<br />

non-nominal generality: one might prefer to give an alternative account in terms of sets, for<br />

example. A set-theoretic account, however, is not suitable for all purposes. Neo-Fregeans<br />

employ non-nominal quantification in their attempted reduction of arithmetic to logic: if,<br />

however, the semantics of non-nominal quantification is set-theoretic then the mathematics<br />

is in the logic from the start. 3 The second problem with set-theoretic accounts would be that<br />

one of the goals of a semantics for non-nominal quantification is to reveal the structure of our<br />

language and thereby tell us something about our linguistic capacities. An account in which<br />

the semantic values of predicates are given extensionally will not explain what speakers of a<br />

language know when they understand a predicate. For speakers must understand that what<br />

the objects in the extension of a predicate ‘F’ have in common is that that they are all F.<br />

The difficulty of avoiding implicit non-nominal quantification in the satisfaction conditions<br />

becomes more apparent when we consider intensional contexts. Note that in the satisfaction<br />

conditions Künne gave for sentential quantification the appearance of a sentential variable in<br />

the context of a that-clause was treated differently to its appearance outside of a that-clause: a<br />

proposition satisfies ‘a = [P]’ if and only if it is identical with the referent of ‘a’; a proposition<br />

satisfies ‘P’ if and only if it is true. Now, there is nothing wrong with this in itself, but it<br />

illustrates the fact that while we might be able to explain truth in terms of non-nominal<br />

quantification, we cannot explain non-nominal quantification in terms of truth. If both<br />

appearances of the variable were treated the same way then ‘a = [P]’ would be satisfied by a<br />

proposition α if and only if the referent of ‘a’ is identical with the proposition that α is true.<br />

Clearly this is not what is intended: if the referent of ‘a’ is not a proposition about a<br />

proposition then no proposition in the domain will satisfy the open sentence. It is for that<br />

reason that the semantics must give the additional rule for appearances of a sentential<br />

variable in the context of a that-clause: a proposition satisfies ‘a = [P]’ if and only if it is<br />

identical with the referent of ‘a’.<br />

However, this rule suffices only for the occurrence of a single sentential variable in a thatclause.<br />

Were we to extend our language further, for instance to accommodate expressions<br />

such as ‘the proposition that p and q’, we should need additional recourse to non-nominal<br />

quantification in order to define new relations in the metalanguage. ‘[p & q]’ should refer to<br />

the proposition expressed by ‘p & q’ but we must define what proposition this is in terms of<br />

the semantic values of ‘p’ and ‘q’. One systematic way to do this would be to give designation<br />

conditions to supplement the satisfaction conditions: the referent of ‘[φ & ϕ]’ is the<br />

proposition which results from the conjunction of the proposition expressed by ‘φ’ with the<br />

2<br />

Like Künne I take the expressions here italicised to function as prosentences.<br />

3<br />

See Wright 2007 for a discussion of this point as well as an interesting suggestion as to how we should<br />

understand interpretations of the quantifiers.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!