25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

34 DOLBY<br />

So whether ‘∃F (Ann is F & Ben is F)’ expresses a truth depends on whether there is an<br />

object within the range of the variable—that is to say, a property (of <strong>bei</strong>ng somehow)—<br />

which satisfies the condition signified by the open sentence ‘Ann is F & Ben is F’. A<br />

property (of <strong>bei</strong>ng somehow) meets this condition if and only if it is exemplified by Ann<br />

and by Ben. (Künne 2003: 363)<br />

Quantification into sentence position is explained in a similar fashion (‘[P]’ is read as ‘the<br />

proposition that P’):<br />

If the sentential quantifier subserves higher-order quantification over propositions, it<br />

is objectual. Hence whether ‘∃P (The Pythagorean Theorem = [P] & P)’ expresses a<br />

truth depends on whether there is an object within the range of the variable, a<br />

proposition, that is, which satisfies the condition signified by the open sentence ‘The<br />

Pythagorean Theorem = [P] & P’. A proposition meets this condition if and only if it is<br />

identical with the Pythagorean Theorem and true. Unsurprisingly, at this point we<br />

cannot avoid employing the concept of truth. (Künne: 2003: 363. I have capitalised the<br />

sentential variables to avoid confusion.)<br />

The objectual account thus explained seems to offer a way to remove the traditional<br />

restriction of quantification to nominal positions while offering a way of understanding nonnominal<br />

quantifications as generalisations about the extra-linguistic world (properties and<br />

propositions) and not merely about linguistic items (predicates and sentences).<br />

4. Implicit Non-Nominal Quantification<br />

According to Prior it is not possible to account for the truth-conditions of non-nominal<br />

quantifications in a way that does not rely on non-nominal generality. The difficulty in<br />

explaining general term and sentential quantification in terms of properties and propositions<br />

arises from the fact that what is relevant to the meaning of a general term quantification over<br />

properties is how something is said to be if one ascribes a particular property to it, just as<br />

what is relevant to a sentential quantification over propositions is how things are said to be if<br />

one asserts a particular proposition. Having effectively nominalized an expression to refer to<br />

an intensional entity we need to denominalize in order to recover the sense of the original<br />

non-nominal expression. Nevertheless, the account of quantification given in the previous<br />

section appears to provide a systematic account of the satisfaction conditions for sentences<br />

with unbound variables in non-nominal positions in a way that does not appeal to nonnominal<br />

generality in the metalanguage. If Prior is right, then appearances must deceive.<br />

The first thing to note about the explanations of satisfaction conditions given above is that<br />

they involve concepts such as exemplification and truth, concepts which are most plausibly<br />

explained in non-nominally quantified terms:<br />

∀x∀y (x exemplifies y ↔ ∃F (y = the property of <strong>bei</strong>ng F & x is F))<br />

Indeed, Künne himself explains truth quantificationally:<br />

∀x (x is true ↔ ∃P (P & x = the proposition that P)) (2003: 337)<br />

The appearance in the satisfaction conditions of concepts which seem to call for a nonnominal<br />

explanation should give us pause. Künne argued that the employment of truth in the<br />

satisfaction conditions was unproblematic since the interpretation is a codification of our<br />

ordinary understanding of idiomatic non-nominal quantification in natural language. He said<br />

moreover that the appearance of truth in such a codification is inevitable (2003: 363–4). It is<br />

not, however, inevitable that one appeal to truth in the satisfaction conditions for sentential<br />

quantification; that is, not unless one wishes to avoid the explicit appearance of sentential<br />

quantification in the satisfaction conditions. For one could easily eliminate truth from the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!