25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

342 KRUSE<br />

principle is also necessary for ascribing epistemic blame and praise, which is also important<br />

for guiding the intellectual conduct of epistemic agents 4 .<br />

Alston himself gives one of the most famous arguments for the fourth premise. He argues that<br />

epistemic agents are not able to form doxastic attitudes voluntarily because of the epistemicreason-responsive<br />

nature of the cognitive processes, which are used to form doxastic attitudes<br />

(Alston 1988: 263-268). Alston identifies having voluntary control over one’s doxastic<br />

attitudes with having an effective choice about what doxastic attitude one takes toward a<br />

proposition p in a certain situation (Alston 1988: 261). According to Alston voluntarily<br />

bringing about a state of affairs φ implies that one has the control to bring about φ as well as<br />

some incompatible alternative to φ 5 (cf. Alston 1988: 261). He then asks us to consider<br />

whether we have an effective choice, given we take our evidence to speak (conclusively) in<br />

favor of p? He answers that if we take our evidence to speak (conclusively) in favor of p, we do<br />

not have the power to bring about another doxastic attitude toward p than the belief that p.<br />

The same holds for the formation of the disbelief that p if we take our evidence (conclusively)<br />

to speak against the truth of p. If we take our evidence to speak neither against nor for the<br />

truth of p, Alston argues that we do not have the power to form a different doxastic attitude<br />

toward p than the suspension of judgment about p (cf. Alston 1988: 263-268). From these<br />

considerations Alston concludes that we do not have an effective choice over our doxastic<br />

attitudes and, therefore, we are not psychologically able to form doxastic attitudes voluntarily<br />

(cf. Alston 1988: 263).<br />

Premise three and four together with modus tollens give us five. Five and premise one<br />

together with modus tollens give us the conclusion that there are no epistemic duties. Since<br />

epistemic duties unlike epistemic norms in general serve to guide the intellectual conduct of<br />

epistemic agents, the third premise does not hold for epistemic norms in general. Therefore,<br />

the argument is not an argument against the existence of epistemic norms. However, the<br />

argument raises doubts on the viability of the “ethics of belief”, taken as an epistemic theory,<br />

and the viability of the epistemic realm which is concerned with the epistemological aim to<br />

guide our intellectual conduct. As far as the viability of those research disciplines is<br />

dependent on a viable notion of epistemic duty, Alston’s argument threatens the viability of<br />

those disciplines as well.<br />

1.3 The Norm of Evidentialism<br />

Especially, proponents of evidentialism like Feldman (2001, 2002) and Steup (1998), who<br />

take evidentialism to be the only viable epistemic theory of the “ethics of belief”, have<br />

objected to Alston’s argument. In what follows, I will shortly describe how each of them tries<br />

to reject Alston’s argument. After that I will explain why they fail to show that the norm of<br />

evidentialism is an epistemic duty.<br />

Feldman characterizes the evidentialist norm in the following way:<br />

For any person S and time t, if S considers p at t, then S has the duty to have the<br />

attitude toward p that fits the evidence S has at t concerning p. (Feldman 2002: 368)<br />

Beside Feldman and Steup, many epistemologists consider the evidentialist norm as the<br />

paradigmatic epistemic duty. According to this norm, there is only one doxastic attitude<br />

which the epistemic agent ought to have at t toward a certain p, she is considering at t. The<br />

epistemic agent ought to have the doxastic attitude toward p which fits her available evidence<br />

at t (cf. Feldman 2000: 680). Feldman agrees with Alston that we do not have direct<br />

4<br />

I will explain this in more detail in the third section of this paper.<br />

5<br />

Whether Alston’s notion of voluntary control is neutral regarding compatibilist and incompatibilist<br />

approaches to the free will need not concern us here, because there are compatibilist as well as<br />

incompatibilitist interpretations of the condition of having an effective choice.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!