25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

332 FISCHER<br />

activation spreads out from it with decreasing strength to the several nodes directly or<br />

indirectly linked to it, subject to the principles that familiarity attracts and use strengthens:<br />

The more often a subject is exposed to a concept, the more strongly its node is activated each<br />

time; and the more frequently a link is activated, the more activation it gradually comes to<br />

pass on, while gradually atrophying upon disuse. An activated concept or proposition<br />

becomes conscious when the node representing it is activated above a certain threshold and<br />

more strongly than competitors. Association can therefore duplicate inferences, by spreading<br />

activation in sufficient strength from connected nodes representing one proposition to nodes<br />

that jointly represent another.<br />

Associative processing within such a network is governed by the principle of partial matching<br />

(Kamas et al. 1996). To encounter it, answer the question: ‘How many animals of each kind<br />

did Moses take on the ark?’ In a classic experiment (Erickson and Mattson 1981), subjects<br />

were asked to read this and other questions out aloud, and either answer them or indicate<br />

that something is wrong with them, as appropriate. Over 80% answered “2” to the present<br />

question – even though they knew that the protagonist of the ark story is Noah, not Moses. In<br />

an attenuated form, the phenomenon persists when statements replace questions: In an<br />

analogous task, 40% of knowledgeable subjects assented to the corresponding statement<br />

about Moses. It seems subjects spontaneously interpret a question or statement about Moses<br />

as stating a familiar fact or prior belief about Noah. So why is that? Such semantic illusions<br />

are not explicable by reference to Gricean principles; but they may be due to partial matching<br />

in associative processing which ensures that relevant answers can be retrieved to differently<br />

phrased questions (Park and Reder 2004): Activation spreads from the node for the stimulus<br />

concept (‘Moses’) via nodes for attributes and relations possessed by its bearer (Biblical<br />

figure, leader, covenant with God, etc.) to nodes for bearers sharing these attributes<br />

(including Noah). When one of these similar bearers’ node is activated also through other<br />

channels (say, upon mention of the ark), propositions about this similar bearer may be<br />

retrieved from memory.<br />

A relevant process is outlined by the theory of interpretation-based processing INP (Budiu<br />

and Anderson 2004). Its interpretation process exploits the possibilities of partial matching<br />

and is incremental: It begins the moment the first semantic unit is read and parsed; results<br />

are updated after each unit is read. At each point, propositions with semantically similar<br />

concepts in matching positions are activated, where a concept is ‘semantically similar’ to<br />

another, to the extent to which the things (individuals, stuffs, properties, etc.) they stand for<br />

are believed to share the same attributes or relations. At each point, the most strongly<br />

activated proposition is chosen as ‘candidate interpretation’ which specifies what the<br />

processed statement states. As the subject reads each semantic unit (verb, adverb, noun<br />

phrase), activation spreads to representations of several propositions with concepts<br />

semantically similar to the one represented by that unit: about other Biblical figures, leaders,<br />

etc. The most strongly activated candidate interpretation at a given point, say, ‘Moses took his<br />

people out of Egypt’, retains such rapidly decaying activation – only – while the next semantic<br />

unit is read, so that momentarily both the candidate and the new stimulus spread activation.<br />

This may activate more strongly the representation of another proposition, which thus<br />

replaces the previous candidate, and so on, until the entire sentence is read. In this way, a<br />

semantically similar proposition the subject already believes true (Noah took two animals of<br />

each kind onto the ark) may come to be accepted as content of the statement (‘Moses took…’).<br />

This process is liable to interact in two ways with spontaneous applications of the metaphor<br />

heuristic: INP will turn some clearly wrong conclusions of spontaneous analogical inferences<br />

(conclusions ‘about Moses’, as it were) into apparent truisms (‘about Noah’). And it will help<br />

forge fresh mappings which facilitate novel analogical inferences – and are not recommended<br />

by the metaphor heuristic. This interaction is best explained through an example. Various<br />

scholars have already connected the deliberate or unconscious use of visual metaphors with

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!