25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

284 WILUTZKY<br />

experiential representation of the framed situation. However, Montague also explicitly states<br />

that “the sadness of the cat’s death, experienced as something objective” (ibid 183) is distinct<br />

from the affective phenomenology of the experience, i.e. the feeling of sadness, and even<br />

maintains that they appear as distinct objects in the experience of emotion. This simultaneous<br />

endowment of affectivity with intentionality and segregation of the affective content from the<br />

cognitive content is problematic.<br />

On the one hand, as Peter Goldie (2000) has pointed out, it is phenomenologically<br />

implausible to assume two such independent objects in emotion: one does not first judge a<br />

situation to be e.g. dangerous and in addition feel fear; rather, one “thinks of the danger with<br />

feeling” from the very start (Goldie 2000, 40). While emotion can be made intelligible by<br />

reference to beliefs, desires and feelings, when actually experiencing an emotion or acting out<br />

of emotion, beliefs and desires do not usually figure in the experience’s content (cf. ibid 147).<br />

Furthermore, Goldie has shown that both cognitive and feeling elements may be present in<br />

consciousness without them <strong>bei</strong>ng experienced as distinct objects: There is an ambiguity in<br />

saying that A feels an emotion E. It can either simply mean that A has feelings which are E-<br />

related, or it can mean that A is aware of feelings which A recognizes as <strong>bei</strong>ng E-related. In<br />

the latter case A is reflectively conscious of her feelings and thus the feelings are indeed an<br />

individual object in the experience of emotion as A directs her attention towards them. On the<br />

former interpretation A is “unreflectively emotionally engaged with the world” so that she is<br />

not aware of her feelings in an object-like manner, but nonetheless A’s thoughts and actions<br />

are structured by these feelings so that it would be wrong to claim that A is unconscious of her<br />

feelings (ibid 64-66). As it stands, Montague’s proposal cannot accommodate the familiar<br />

phenomenon of unreflective feeling described by Goldie. What is needed is an explanation of<br />

how the affective content structures the cognitive content, so that both come together as one<br />

object in experience.<br />

On the other hand, the separation of the affective from the cognitive content, and in<br />

particular Montague’s description of the affective content as the result of the interactions<br />

between evaluative and cognitive contents, neglects the ways in which affectivity itself can<br />

contribute to both the cognitive and the evaluative aspects of emotion. The rendition of the<br />

affective phenomenology of emotions as an experiential representation of the evaluative<br />

content, which in turn is arrived at via the cognitive framing, implies that the affective<br />

content is merely a reiteration of a content that has already been previously established in a<br />

non-affective way (i.e. what was formerly “a representation of her joyful win” now is “an<br />

experience of her joyful win”, ibid 190). Although Montague concedes that affective content<br />

may have a reinforcing effect on the cognitive content, so that the feeling of sadness may<br />

strengthen the framing of one’s cat’s death as sad (cf. ibid 184), no further way in which the<br />

affective content may help establish the intentionality of emotions is discussed. Indeed, any<br />

such endeavors would most likely stand at odds with Montague’s previously outlined account,<br />

since the affective content is effectively the result of (or something triggered by) previously<br />

established cognitive and evaluative contents. That the affective contents of emotions is more<br />

than a byproduct of an otherwise non-affective, cognitive process becomes evident in Helm’s<br />

portrayal of the interconnectedness of evaluative and affective contents: the loss of an object<br />

of affection is felt as painful, and it is in virtue of this feeling that the loss is evaluated as bad.<br />

Conversely, it is because of the value that the lost object has that its loss pains you in the first<br />

place (Helm 2009, 250). Affect and evaluation are thus interdependent and affective content<br />

therefore can certainly not be regarded as the end of a causal chain of events. Instead,<br />

affective content can contribute to cognitive and other functions in several respects. For one<br />

thing, the affective contents “reverberate through [a subject’s] entire mental economy,<br />

affecting not only her desires, her expressive behaviour and the way in which she acts [...] also<br />

her imaginations and memories” (Goldie 2002, 245). The way in which we think of those<br />

objects towards which we feel emotion changes drastically due to the affective content that is<br />

experienced, and these new ways of thinking can lead us to generate new goals and desires -

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!