25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

EVALUATIVE AND AFFECTIVE INTENTIONALITY OF EMOTIONS 283<br />

the examples of framing that she uses (e.g. winning the grant <strong>bei</strong>ng framed as a success, the<br />

sadness of one’ cat’s death). However, the relation of the formal object to the target object<br />

(i.e. whether a dog charging at you is perceived as dangerous or whether your cat’s death is<br />

considered sad or whether Jane regards winning the grant as a success) can only be<br />

established with respect to the subject’s focus on that object, that is, what import or value the<br />

target has for the subject (cf. Helm 2009, 5). Thus, the target of Jane’s joy (winning the grant)<br />

can only be framed as a success, and thereby establish the formal object, because Jane’s focus<br />

on the target object is of such a kind that she regards it as something that she values and<br />

deems desirable. In order for emotions to occur, certain evaluative aspects must be in place<br />

from the very beginning and shape any further cognitive assessment of a situation. Situations<br />

are not assessed from an “emotional nowhere” and then eventually lead to an emotion.<br />

Rather, there is always a background of import and concern out of which emotions arise and<br />

which scaffold the cognitive content. Montague’s proposal of a non-evaluative or “neutral”<br />

framing prior to evaluative content is simply irreconcilable with these considerations.<br />

To use a cognitively less loaded and affectively more salient example, imagine you are<br />

watching a small child that you are fond of <strong>bei</strong>ng approached by a large, barking dog. Because<br />

the child has import to you, it is an object worth of your attention and, if so required, also<br />

your action. You are constantly vigilant and prepared to act on its behalf, so that watching the<br />

dog coming close to the toddler is bound to grab your attention and, if so required, also your<br />

action. You are afraid for the child, and this fear is not merely a response to the barking dog<br />

<strong>bei</strong>ng associated with a danger, possibly through some inborn instinct, but arises from your<br />

concern for the child. The dog is perceived as a threat or danger to the child, not as a potential<br />

threat or danger that just happens to be in the child’s vicinity. In other words, the dog is<br />

perceived as a danger not because he has a general property of ‘dangerousness’ which can be<br />

cognitively and non-evaluatively assessed or framed, but because it stands in a certain<br />

relation to an object that has import to you.<br />

What seems to lie at the root of Montague’s problematic proposal that a situation can be nonevaluatively<br />

framed as joyful, sad etc. is her assumption that perceptions of value may be true<br />

or false, or, put differently, that value can be correctly or incorrectly represented. “[W]hether<br />

the state of affairs in question has been legitimately or accurately framed”, in Montague’s<br />

opinion, depends on the correct representation of “the evaluative features of the state of<br />

affairs in question” (Montague 2009, 181). For Montague values seem to be out there in the<br />

world and need only be detected. Hence, framing is merely a representation of what is given<br />

in the world itself and not an active evaluation of the situation performed by the subject. That<br />

this assumption of the objectivity of value is untenable when wanting to explain the evaluative<br />

intentionality of emotions should be evident by now, given Helm’s considerations on the<br />

importance of a subject’s concerns in determining a situation’s value for a subject. To repeat,<br />

the value of a situation for a subject can only be determined with respect to her other<br />

evaluations and concerns.<br />

4.2. Second Problem: Affective, Evaluative and Cognitive Contents as distinct from one<br />

another<br />

Secondly, Montague treats the cognitive, evaluative and affective contents of emotion as<br />

distinct components and, what is more, even as distinct objects in the experience of emotions.<br />

Considering the example of <strong>bei</strong>ng sad over a cat’s death, Montague claims that the nonevaluative<br />

framing of the cat’s death as sad is “experienced as something as objective” and is<br />

an object which the subject stands in an intentional relation to (ibid 183). This intentional<br />

relation in which the subject stands to the “objective sadness” of the situation gives rise to a<br />

second intentional object, the affective content. Montague wishes to surpass those emotion<br />

theories which regard affectivity as a mere accompanying, non-intentional feeling to emotion<br />

and argues that the affective content itself is world-directed, namely in virtue of <strong>bei</strong>ng an

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!