25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

282 WILUTZKY<br />

unwarranted, for representing something as a success in emotion already is an evaluation of<br />

the state of affairs. (This does not mean that one cannot represent the conditions of<br />

someone’s success in a non-emotional way, e.g by coolly analyzing the situation’s implications<br />

without any personal investment. But when one perceives something as a success in emotion,<br />

it is not first represented non-evaluatively.)<br />

In this respect Bennett Helm’s (2009) account of the evaluative nature of emotions’<br />

intentionality advances over Montague’s. For Helm, the framing or, in his terminology, the<br />

representation of a state of affairs relative to a subject’s focus already gives the evaluative<br />

content of an emotion, due to its inherent relatedness to the subject’s interests and concerns:<br />

Jane only feels joy over her successful application because she regards it as something<br />

desirable and something that is of import to her. She cares about winning the grant and this<br />

caring commits Jane not only to feel joy when winning it, but also to an entire range of<br />

emotions, such as hoping to win the grant, fearing that she will not get it and <strong>bei</strong>ng<br />

disappointed if she should not get it. All these emotions arise from one and the same focus,<br />

namely that winning the grant has import to her. Any failure of Jane’s to respond emotionally<br />

in such ways under the respective circumstances would entail either a failure in rationality or<br />

that winning is in fact not of import to her. Likewise, if, for whatever reason, Jane was hoping<br />

not to win she would be disappointed upon hearing that she won, even though according to<br />

Montague Jane’s framing of the situation (i.e. her <strong>bei</strong>ng successful) would have to be the<br />

same as in the original scenario. Montague fails to provide an explanation of why one and the<br />

same framing would be associated with such disparate evaluative contents. In fact,<br />

Montague’s proposal has the even greater difficulty of explaining why a non-evaluative,<br />

cognitive framing of a situation is at all associated with an evaluative content and thereby<br />

leads to an emotion, whereas other framings of situations could go by without any emotional<br />

response at all. This is what Helm has termed the “problem of import”: why are certain<br />

cognitive states infused with emotionality, whereas others remain “cold” and lead to no<br />

emotional response? Helm’s answer is that certain evaluative aspects (such as import and<br />

concern) must be in place before a situation is cognitively assessed, as any post-hoc addition<br />

of evaluative contents would only return to the problem of import (cf. Helm 2009, 250). In<br />

other words: you have to value something first in order to have any kind of emotional<br />

response at all. Situations are not assessed from an “emotional nowhere” and then eventually<br />

lead to an emotion. Rather, there is always a background of import and concern out of which<br />

emotions arise and which scaffold the cognitive content. A subject’s focus on those things that<br />

are of import to her direct her attention and guide her perception of a situation, thereby<br />

making Montague’s proposal of a fully non-evaluative, cognitive framing as the first step in<br />

constructing an emotion’s intentionality nonviable.<br />

The same point can be made by appeal to an established distinction of the intentional objects<br />

of emotions: the target and the formal object of emotion. The target of an emotion is that<br />

which an emotion is directed at in a particular situation (e.g. Jane’s winning the grant),<br />

whereas the formal object is the relation in which the experiencing subject stands to the target<br />

and which makes the emotion intelligible (e.g. winning the grant is a success). 2 It is widely<br />

held that emotion types are characterized by different kinds of formal objects, so that the<br />

formal object of fear for instance is the evaluation of a target as dangerous to one and in<br />

sadness a target object is assessed as irretrievably lost. Seemingly unbeknown to Montague,<br />

the notion of a formal object resembles her concept of framing, as is, inter alia, suggested by<br />

a possibility. If this were indeed Montague’s claim, then her account would by no means square well<br />

with studies on how attention and perception mechanisms are guided by emotions (cf. Lewis 2005).<br />

2<br />

I will leave it open here whether the formal object requires the reference to a belief (e.g. the belief that<br />

a certain target is dangerous, as Anthony Kenny proposed) or whether it is a property of the situation<br />

(as Ronald de Sousa has suggested), and furthermore whether formal objects are in fact characteristic of<br />

emotion types (i.e. that the formal object of fear is to evaluate something as dangerous, that of anger is<br />

to evaluate a target as offensive etc.).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!