25.12.2013 Views

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

Was sollen wir tun? Was dürfen wir glauben? - bei DuEPublico ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

266 WEBER & VOSGERAU<br />

equations. 1 Such a view is also supported by Brook’s (1991) research in robotics and in<br />

artificial life because his findings can be applied to explain adaptive behavior without any<br />

strong notion of representation. Brooks insists: “Representation is the wrong unit of<br />

abstraction in building the bulkiest parts of intelligent systems” (Brooks 1991: 140), because<br />

“the world is its own best model” (Brooks 1990: 6). Those authors do not postulate the<br />

existence of an internal representational model of a cognitive system that guides its behavior<br />

and its actions. Moreover, they reject the idea that a cognitive system ought to be conceived of<br />

as relatively independent from the world in its ability to representationally reproduce the<br />

external structure of the environment to guide its behavior.<br />

But many still suspect that in developing an adequate theory of cognition, especially as<br />

regards belief formation and action planning, we need to postulate internal mental<br />

representations. For example, at first sight a theory of dynamical interaction between an<br />

organism and its environment alone provides no satisfying explanation when it comes to<br />

anticipatory behavior. A dynamical systems theory may face serious difficulties in providing<br />

an account of how systems are able to deal with “representation-hungry” tasks, such as those<br />

involving abstract thought and high-level reasoning. Cognitive processes like problem solving,<br />

planning, language acquisition, thinking about absent, even non-existent states of affairs,<br />

counterfactual reasoning and learning in general which are all conceived of as cases of purely<br />

internal processing in this context seem most naturally explained by appeal to internal<br />

representations (cf. Clark and Toribio 1994). So, the essential challenge is to explain those<br />

aspects of behavior that involve internal factors beyond immediate interaction.<br />

We further want to pay attention to the relation between perception, action and cognition as<br />

conceived in dynamical approaches. For instance, Thelen et al. state that “cognition depends<br />

on the kinds of experiences that come from having a body with particular perceptual and<br />

motor capabilities that are inseparably linked” (2001: 1; emphasis added by the authors). But<br />

what does “inseparably linked” or “depend” mean for the mutual contribution of the domains<br />

or “capabilities” of perception, action and cognition while cognition is – in some not yet<br />

specified sense – “embodied”? What do we learn about the nature or architecture of the mind,<br />

its functional makeup and its relation to bodily functions? Is cognition in this sense<br />

“embodied” that it is entirely dependent of sensorimotor processes?<br />

An adequate theory of embodied cognition ought to allow for a further understanding of the<br />

nature of mental representations. An alternative and more moderate (qua<br />

representationalist) view in embodied cognitive science is a project called “grounded<br />

cognition” (Barsalou 1999, 2008). Therefore, we discern that the major outstanding issues<br />

center on the representationalist understanding of grounded cognition in contrast to antirepresentationalist<br />

conceptions of embodied cognition. The idea of grounded cognition is that<br />

cognitive and perceptual mechanisms share the same representational states: the core<br />

sources of representation that “ground” cognition are thought of as simulations in the brain’s<br />

modal systems such as the sensorimotor system. Contrary to the language of thought<br />

hypothesis, the theory especially challenges the view that core representations are amodal<br />

symbols and data structures processed independently of the brain’s modal systems for<br />

perception, action, and introspection. Barsalou summarizes the project of grounded cognition<br />

as follows:<br />

Grounded cognition rejects traditional views that cognition is computation on amodal<br />

symbols in a modular system, independent of the brain’s modal systems for perception,<br />

1<br />

This is not to claim that every possible dynamical account like the dynamical systems theory is per se<br />

an anti-representationalist view. There are works rebuilding and integrating even an elaborated notion<br />

of representation in dynamic approaches; for example, Spivey’s “attempt to raise awareness of the<br />

benefits of emphasizing continuous processing, and therefore continuous representation as well”<br />

(Spivey 2007: 3) suggests some kind of “symbolic dynamics” (2007: 262 ff.), thereby reconsidering<br />

symbolic, but not computational representations.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!